Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T06:15:16.427Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scientific Progress

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 September 2023

Darrell P. Rowbottom
Affiliation:
Lingnan University, Hong Kong

Summary

What constitutes cognitive scientific progress? This Element begins with an extensive survey of the contemporary debate on how to answer this question. It provides a blow-by-blow critical summary of the key literature on the issue over the past fifteen years, covering the central positions and arguments therein. It also draws upon older literature, where appropriate, to inform the treatment. The Element then enters novel territory by considering meta-normative issues concerning scientific progress. It focuses on how the standards involved in assessing progress arise. Does science have aims, which determine what counts as progress, as many authors assume? If so, what is it to be an aim of science? And how does one identify such things? If not, how do normative standards arise? After arguing that science does not have overarching aims, the Element proposes that the standards are ultimately subjective.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108625753
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 12 October 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aaserud, F. and Heilbron, J. L. 2013. Love, literature, and the quantum atom: Niels Bohr’s 1913 trilogy revisited. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Abbott, B. P. et al. 2016. Observation of gravitational waves from a binary black hole merger. Physics review letters 116, 06110.Google Scholar
Bagnoli, C. 2021. Constructivism in metaethics. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/constructivism-metaethics.Google Scholar
Baker, D. 2018. The varieties of normativity. In McPherson, T. and Plunkett, D. (eds.), The Routledge handbook of meta-ethics, 567–81. Routledge.Google Scholar
Bangu, S. 2015. Scientific progress, understanding and unification. In I. D. Toader, G. Sandu & I. Pȃrvu (eds.), Romanian studies in philosophy of science. Springer.Google Scholar
Barnes, E. 1991. Beyond verisimilitude: A linguistically invariant basis for scientific progress. Synthese 88, 309–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berker, S. 2019. Mackie was not an error theorist. Philosophical perspectives 33, 525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. 2007. What is scientific progress? Noûs 41, 6489.Google Scholar
Bird, A. 2008. Scientific progress as accumulation of knowledge: A reply to Rowbottom. Studies in history and philosophy of science part A 39, 279–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. 2022. Knowing science. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bohr, N. 1913. On the constitution of atoms and molecules. Philosophical magazine series 6, 151, 125.Google Scholar
Carter, J. A. and Pritchard, D. 2015. Knowledge-how and epistemic value. Australasian journal of philosophy 93, 799816.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cevolani, G. and Tambolo, L. 2013. Progress as approximation to the truth: A defence of the verisimilitudinarian approach. Erkenntnis 78, 921–35.Google Scholar
Cevolani, G. and Tambolo, L. 2019. Why adding truths is not enough: A reply to Mizrahi on progress as approximation to the truth. International studies in the philosophy of science 32, 129–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakravartty, A. 2017. Scientific realism. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/scientific-realism.Google Scholar
Chang, H. 2004. Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1980. What has science to do with truth? Synthese 45, 489510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cushing, J. T. 1990. Is scientific methodology interestingly atemporal? British journal for the philosophy of science 41, 177–94.Google Scholar
Dellsén, F. 2016. Scientific progress: Knowledge versus understanding. Studies in history and philosophy of science 56, 7283.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dellsén, F. 2018a. Scientific progress: Four accounts. Philosophy compass. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12525.Google Scholar
Dellsén, F. 2018b. Scientific progress, understanding and knowledge: Reply to Park. Journal for general philosophy of science 49, 451–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dellsén, F. 2021. Understanding scientific progress: The noetic account. Synthese 199, 11249–78.Google Scholar
Dellsén, F., Lawler, I., and Norton, J. 2022. Thinking about progress: From science to philosophy. Noûs 56: 814–40.Google Scholar
de Regt, H. 2017. Understanding scientific understanding. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deutsch, M. 2015. The myth of the intuitive: Experimental philosophy and philosophical method. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Douglas, H. 2014. Pure science and the problem of progress. Studies in the history and philosophy of science 46, 5563.Google Scholar
Elgin, C. Z. 2017. True enough. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Emmerson, N. 2022. Understanding and scientific progress: Lessons from epistemology. Synthese 200: 7.Google Scholar
Galison, P. 1997. Image and logic: A material culture of microphysics. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gillies, D. 2000. Philosophical theories of probability. Routledge.Google Scholar
Heilbron, J. L. and Kuhn, T. S. 1969. The genesis of the Bohr atom. Historical studies in the physical sciences 1, vi290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hetherington, S. 2011. How to know: A practicalist conception of knowledge. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. 1651. Leviathan. Andrew Crooke.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, P. 2013. Systematicity: The nature of science. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
James, W. 1896. The will to believe: And other popular essays in philosophy. Longman, Green, & Company.Google Scholar
Keller, E. F. 2002. Making sense of life: Explaining biological development with models, metaphors, and machines. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. 2014. Two for the knowledge goal of inquiry. American philosophical quarterly 51, 227–32.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1990. The division of cognitive labor. Journal of philosophy 87, 522.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1993. The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 2015. Pragmatism and progress. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce society 51, 475–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions. 2nd ed. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1977. The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lagemann, R. T. 1977. New light on old rays: N rays. American journal of physics 45, 281–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. 1978. The methodology of scientific research programmes. Edited by Worrall, J. and Currie, G.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. 1977. Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Routledge.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. 1981. A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of science 48, 1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. 1984. Science and values: The aims of science and their role in scientific debate. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Longino, H. 2001. The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Losee, J. 2004. Theories of scientific progress: An introduction. Routledge.Google Scholar
Lutz, M. and Lenman, J. 2018. Moral naturalism. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/naturalism-moral.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Pelican Books.Google Scholar
McMullin, E. 1979. Discussion review: Laudan’s progress and its problems. Philosophy of science 46, 623–44.Google Scholar
Miller, K. and Tuomela, R. 2014. Collective goals analyzed. In Chant, S. R., Hindriks, F., and Preyer, G. (eds.), From individual to collective intentionality: New essays. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mizrahi, M. 2013. What is scientific progress? Lessons from scientific practice. Journal for general philosophy of science 44, 375–90.Google Scholar
Mizrahi, M. 2017. Scientific progress: Why getting closer to the truth is not enough. International studies in the philosophy of science 31, 415–19.Google Scholar
Mizrahi, M. 2021. Conceptions of scientific progress in scientific practice: An empirical study. Synthese 199, 2375–94.Google Scholar
Mizrahi, M. and Buckwalter, W. 2014. The role of justification in the ordinary concept of scientific progress. Journal for general philosophy of science 45, 151–66.Google Scholar
Moberger, V. 2017. Not just errors: A new interpretation of Mackie’s error theory. Journal for the history of analytical philosophy 5, 112.Google Scholar
Moberger, V. 2018. The queerness of objective values: An essay on Mackiean metaethics and the arguments from queerness. PhD Thesis, Uppsala University.Google Scholar
Moxham, N. and Fyfe, A. 2018. The Royal Society and the prehistory of peer review, 1665–1965. The historical journal 6, 863–89.Google Scholar
Muldoon, R. 2013. Diversity and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy compass 8, 117–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nado, J. 2014. Philosophical expertise. Philosophy compass 9, 631–41.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 1984. Is science progressive? D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 1999. Critical scientific realism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 2014. Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude. Studies in history and philosophy of science 46, 73–7.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 2017. Optimistic realism about scientific progress. Synthese 194, 32913309.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 2019. Scientific progress. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/scientific-progress.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 2020. Social aspects of scientific knowledge. Synthese 197, 447–68.Google Scholar
Nye, M. J. 1980. N-rays: An episode in the history and psychology of science. Historical studies in the physical sciences 11, 125–56.Google Scholar
Okasha, S. 2011. Theory choice and social choice: Kuhn versus Arrow. Mind 120, 83115.Google Scholar
Oreskes, N. 2019. Systematicity is necessary but not sufficient: On the problem of facsimile science. Synthese 196, 881905.Google Scholar
Orwell, G. 1946. Politics and the English language. Horizon 13, 252–65.Google Scholar
Park, S. 2017. Does scientific progress consist in increasing knowledge or understanding? Journal for general philosophy of science 48, 569–79.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. 1963. Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. Routledge.Google Scholar
Popper, K. 1983. Realism and the aim of science. Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Potochnik, A. 2015. The diverse aims of science. Studies in history and philosophy of science 53, 7180.Google Scholar
Potochnik, A. 2017. Idealization and the aims of science. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. 1999. Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rancourt, B. 2017. Better understanding through falsehood. Pacific philosophical quarterly 98, 382405.Google Scholar
Resnik, D. B. 1993. Do scientific aims justify methodological rules? Erkenntnis 38, 223–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, G. 1994. What is constructive empiricism? Philosophical studies 74, 143–78.Google Scholar
Rousseau, D. L. 1971. ’Polywater’ and sweat: Similarities between the infrared spectra. Science 171, 3967, 170–2.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2008. N-rays and the semantic view of scientific progress. Studies in history and philosophy of science 39, 277–8.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2010. What scientific progress is not: Against Bird’s epistemic view. International studies in the philosophy of science 24, 241–55.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2011a. Kuhn vs. Popper on criticism and dogmatism in science: A resolution at the group level. Studies in history and philosophy of science 42, 117–24.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2011b. Approximations, idealizations, and ‘experiments’ at the physics-biology interface. Studies in history and philosophy of biological and biomedical sciences 42, 145–54.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2014. Aimless science. Synthese 191, 1211–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2015a. Scientific progress without increasing verisimilitude: In response to Niiniluoto. Studies in history and philosophy of science 51, 100–4.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2015b. Probability. Polity.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2018a. Scientific realism: What it is, the contemporary debate, and new directions. Synthese 196, 451–84.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2018b. Beyond Kuhn: Methodological contextualism and partial paradigms. In Mizrahi, M. (ed.), The Kuhnian image of science: Time for a decisive transformation? 191208. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2019. The instrument of science: Scientific anti-realism revitalised. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2021. A methodological argument against scientific realism. Synthese 198: 2153–67.Google Scholar
Rowbottom, D. P. 2022. Can meaningless statements be approximately true? On relaxing the semantic component of scientific realism. Philosophy of science. 89, 879–88.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. 1949. The concept of mind. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Saatsi, J. 2005. On the pessimistic induction and two fallacies. Philosophy of science 72, 1088–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saatsi, J. 2019. What is theoretical progress of science? Synthese 196, 611–31.Google Scholar
Schweikard, D. P. and Schmid, H-B. 2020. Collective intentionality. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/collective-intentionality.Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, E. 2002. A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Noûs 36, 249–75.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. 2003. Moral realism: A defence. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shan, Y. 2019. A new functional approach to scientific progress. Philosophy of science 86, 739–58.Google Scholar
Shan, Y. (ed.) 2022. New philosophical perspectives on scientific progress. Routledge.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. and Williamson, T. 2001. Knowing how. Journal of philosophy 98, 411–44.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1993. The fragmentation of reason. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tännsjö, T. 2015. A realist and internalist response to one of Mackie’s arguments from queerness. Philosophical studies 172, 347–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuomela, R. 2007. The philosophy of sociality: The shared point of view. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Brakel, J. 1993. Polywater and experimental realism. British journal for the philosophy of science 44, 775–84.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1980. The scientific image. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1994. Gideon Rosen on constructive empiricism. Philosophical studies 74, 179–92.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1998. The agnostic subtly probabilified. Analysis 58, 212–20.Google Scholar
Wallis, C. 2008. Consciousness, context, and know-how. Synthese 160, 123–53.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wray, B. 2018. Resisting scientific realism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Scientific Progress
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Scientific Progress
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Scientific Progress
Available formats
×