Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-28T20:29:32.099Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Change in Manner: Hume's Scepticism in the Treatise and the first Enquiry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Miriam McCormick*
Affiliation:
McGill University, Montreal, PQ, CanadaH3A 2T7

Extract

The year before his death, Hume asked his publisher to affix an advertisement to all existing and future editions of his works. In this advertisement, Hume disavows the Treatise and directs all criticism to his later work. Hume himself is relatively clear as to why he preferred this later work. In his autobiography, when discussing the poor public reception given his Treatise, Hume says, ‘I had always entertained a Notion, that my want of Success in publishing the Treatise of human nature, had proceeded more from the manner than the matter; and that I had been guilty of a very usual Indiscretion, in going to the Press too early.’ In a letter to Gilbert Elliot, written in 1751, Hume says that ‘The philosophical Principles are the same in both’ the Treatise and the first Enquiry.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 The Letters of David Hume, 2 vols., Greig, J.Y.T. ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1932), vol.1, 158Google Scholar

2 Popkin, Richard H.David Hume: His Pyrrhonism and His Critique of Pyrrhonism.’ References to this paper are from The High Road to Pyrrhonism, Watson, Richard A. and Force, James E. eds. (San Diego: Austin Hill Press 1980), 103132Google Scholar.

3 Penelhum, Terence God and Skepticism: A Study in Skepticism and Fideism (Dordrecht: D. Reidel 1983), 124-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In his David Hume, An Introduction to His Philosophical System (Purdue: Purdue University Press 1992), he says that the sceptic of the Treatise’ copes with his anxieties by being Pyrrhonian and dogmatic by turns, and alternating his activities.'

4 Norton, David FateHow a Sceptic May Live Scepticism’ in Faith, Scepticism and Personal Identity, Macintosh, J.J. and Meynell, H.A. (Calgary: University of Calgary Press 1994), 121Google Scholar

5 Fogelin, R.J. Hume's Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature (New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1985), 2Google Scholar

6 Those who agree that there is no substantial difference between the two works tend to argue that Hume is less sceptical than I think he is. For example, in ‘Hume's Academic Scepticism: A Reappraisal of his Philosophy of Human Understanding,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (1986) 407-35, John P. Wright argues that Hume is committed to a realist ontology. He says that ‘the scepticism which Hume himself adopted requires a commitment to an objective world’ (411) and that ‘whatever we might mean by calling Hume a sceptic, this does not mean that he is agnostic regarding our fundamental ontological suppositions’ (416). Wright argues that Hume has these realist commitments in both the Treatise and the first Enquiry. Although I do not think Hume denies the existence of an objective world or tries to undermine our fundamental suppositions, his scepticism does commit him to being open to the possibility that these suppositions can be questioned and may turn out to be false. Although they must be accepted if any action and inquiry is to be possible, this does not mean we can know that they are true.

7 Hume, David A Treatise of Human Nature, Selby-Bigge, L.A. and Nidditch, P.H. eds. (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1978), 183Google Scholar. Hereafter cited in text as T. When I refer to ‘radical,’ ‘excessive,’ or ‘total’ scepticism, I am referring to the position that Hume attributes (probably unfairly) to a fantastic sect, namely, the Pyrrhonians.

8 Livingston, Donald has pointed out that the extreme sceptical doubt Hume describes is only one stage in the philosophical reflection that leads to the adoption of Hume's ‘true philosophy.’ He says the ‘Pyrrhonian arguments are a necessary stage in the natural history of philosophical reflection from vulgar thought through false philosophy to philosophy that is true(Hume's Philosophy of Common Life [Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1984], 27-8)Google Scholar. Livingston, has recently pointed out that many readers have made the ‘error of confusing a moment in the dialectic with its final result(Philosophical Melancholy and Delirium [Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1998], 147)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 ‘Belief in distinct and continued existence’ and ‘belief in body’ mean the same thing. I shall often use the second locution for brevity.

10 When Hume asks in 1.4.2 whether reason is responsible for belief in body, I take it that he is asking whether any activity of the understanding is responsible for this belief. Does any kind of reasoning, be it demonstrative, or probable, cause us to have this belief?

Hume uses ‘reason’ in several ways in the Treatise, and it is not always clear in which sense he is using it. Norton identifies seven principal senses in which Hume uses the term. See his discussion for further details on these various uses in David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1982) 97-8.

11 Hume, David Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, Selby-Bigge, L.A. and Nidditch, P.H. eds. (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1975), 149CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Hereafter cited in text as ECHU.

12 Hume says that the supposition that there is a connection between our perceptions and some external object is ‘without any foundation in reasoning.’ He rejects Descartes’ appeal to God's undeceitful nature as evidence that external objects do exist. Hume argues that to refer to the ‘veracity of the supreme Being’ to prove the existence of objects ‘is surely making a very unexpected circuit’ (ECHU 153). For how can we prove the existence of God or any of his attributes once we have called into question the existence of the external world? We could not base any arguments to prove His existence on what we see around us, for we are doubting that there is anything around us. To rely on God's veracity is to beg the question at issue: are there existences external to the mind?

13 Penelhum, T.M. ‘Comments and Responses,’ in Faith, Scepticism and Personal Identity, 270Google Scholar

14 An earlier version of this paper was read at the 22nd international Hume conference in Park City, Utah. I am greatly indebted to David Norton for his many comments and suggestions.