Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T13:12:00.229Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Civil Disobedience and International Law: Sketch for a Theoretical Argument

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 March 2016

Get access

Summary

This article argues that there is an increasing trend of civil society resorting to civil disobedience in relation to international legal values. International law, however, has not caught up with this trend. In fact, both international law and civil disobedience can gain much from a better understanding of their interaction. The article briefly traces the record of arguments drawn from international law in civil disobedience cases, highlights the theoretical constraints of the debate, and seeks to establish some basic foundations for an international legal theory of legitimate civil disobedience.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Canadian Council on International Law / Conseil Canadien de Droit International, representing the Board of Editors, Canadian Yearbook of International Law / Comité de Rédaction, Annuaire Canadien de Droit International 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Franck, T.M., The Power of Legitimacy among Nations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).Google Scholar

2 Already, Henry Thoreau’s tax boycott following the annexation of California was based on the Mexican war being contrary to international law.

3 With a few notable exceptions. See, for example, Rajagopal, Balakrishnan, International Law from Below: Development, Social Movements, and Third World Resistance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar Rajagopal, however, is not interested in civil disobedience specifically.

4 Falk, R.A., “The Adequacy of Contemporary Theories of International Law: Gaps in Legal Thinking” (1964) 50 Va. L. Rev. 231 at 255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 For example, the classical moral theory dilemma is whether there is a moral obligation to obey/disobey the law. The question is often raised as if the law itself had little interesting to say on the issue, except presumably the stubborn assertion that it is binding.

6 For example, many books on civil disobedience do not mention international law once. Bedau, H.A., Civil Disobedience in Focus (New York: Routledge, 1991).CrossRefGoogle Scholar The vast majority of writings on civil disobedience come from the United States where, for all the occasional references to international law, the debate remains dominated either by domestic political theory or domestic constitutional concerns. In particular, the treatment of civil disobedience in political theory typically emphasizes the nature of the problem in, to use Rawls’s expression, “the special case of a nearly just society.” Rawls, J., A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1999) at 319 Google Scholar; see also, Dworkin, R.M., A Matter of Principle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986) at 105.Google Scholar Dworkin defines civil disobedience as not “challenging the legitimacy of the government or of the dimensions of the political community.” However, that is arguably what many civil disobeyers have done, and it does not seem crucial to a proper understanding of civil disobedience that they do not.

7 This article is part of a larger project funded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council to critically re-examine a neglected tradition of “resistance” in international law, in order to recapture some of international law’s subversive potential, whose emphasis is, to use the expression of Balakrishna Rajagopal, on the construction of “international law from below.”

8 See Thoreau, H.D., On the Duty of Civil Disobedience (N.p.: Forgotten Books, 2008).Google Scholar King, M.L. and Jackson, J., Why We Can’t Wait (New York: Signet Classics, 2000).Google Scholar

9 International law, particularly international human rights law, has had considerable things to say on the latter, protecting as it does such key civil and political rights as freedom of expression or freedom of assembly as well as various provisions protecting the integrity and freedom of individuals. In other words, the state is not at liberty to prohibit or frustrate a number of manifestations of political dissent.

10 The debates on conscientious objection, and “conscience-inspired” civil disobedience are sometimes unhelpfully confused. The former is not really a transformative, as much as a privacy-based, claim; the latter considers that it is not enough to be part of something, she also wants that something changed for her conscience to be assuaged.

11 Sagi, A. and Shapira, R., “Civil Disobedience and Conscientious Objection” (2002) 36 Isr. L.R. 181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 Herr, W.A., “Thoreau: A Civil Disobedient?” (1974) 85 Ethics 87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 The willingness to accept one’s punishment is characteristic of civil disobedience launched in broadly democratic and rule of law-based societies, not fundamentally oppressive ones. In this respect, my understanding of civil disobedience is closer to that of Howard Zinn. See Zinn, H., Disobedience and Democracy: Nine Fallacies of Law and Order (N.p.: South End Press, 2002).Google Scholar

14 Hess, D. and Martin, B., “Repression, Backfire, and the Theory of Transformative Events” (2006) 11(2) Mobilization: An International Quarterly 249.Google Scholar

15 Interestingly, one of the great figures of civil disobedience, Martin Luther King, often emphasized the fact that the Vietnam War was, above all, in violation of international law. See Martin Luther King, “The Casualties of the War in Vietnam,” National Institute, Los Angeles, 25 February 1967 (emphasizing violations of the Charter of the United Nations and the principle of self-determination).

16 Smith, Christian, Resisting Reagan: The US Central America Peace Movement (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 Quigley, B., “The St. Patrick’s Four: Jury Votes 9–3 to Acquit Peace Activists Despite Admission They Poured Blood in Military Recruiting Center” (2004) 61 Guild Practitioner 110.Google Scholar

18 Awad, Mubarak E., “Non-Violent Resistance: A Strategy for the Occupied Territories” (1984) 13(4) J. Palestine Stud. 22 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sharp, Gene, “The Intifadah and Nonviolent Struggle” (1989) 19(1) J. Palestine Stud. 22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 Stephan, M.J., “Nonviolent Insurgency: The Role of Civilian-Based Resistance in the East Timorese, Palestinian, and Kosovo Albanian Self-Determination Movements” (Ph.D. thesis, Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy, 2005) [unpublished].Google Scholar

20 Falk, R., “Citizenship and the Modern State: The Spirit of Thoreau in the Age of Trident” (1985) 9 Aus. J. Leg. Phil. 254.Google Scholar

21 Hilson, C., “Framing the Local and the Global in the Anti-Nuclear Movement: Law and the Politics of Place” (2009) 36 J.L. & Soc’y 94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Stephan, M.J., “Strategic Nonviolence: Fighting for Statehood: The Role of Civilian-Based Resistance in the East Timorese, Palestinian, and Kosovo Albanian Self-Determination Movements” (2006) 30 Fletcher F. World Aff. 57.Google Scholar

23 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 10 December 1948, UNGA Resolution 217A III at art. 25(1).

24 Gassama, I.J., “Reaffirming Faith in the Dignity of Each Human Being: The United Nations, NGOs, and Apartheid” (1995) 19 Fordham Int’l L.J. 1464.Google Scholar

25 Fekete, Liz, “Civil Disobedience Campaign against Detention Centres Launched,” Independent Race and Refugee News Network (19 May 2002), <https://www.irr.org.uk/cgi-bin/news/open.pl?id=5257>.Google Scholar

26 Karvela, Patricia and Colman, Elizabeth, “Raids Hit ‘Passport Racket,’The Australian (2 December 2004).Google Scholar

27 On the “Shut Down the Camp” initiative in Denmark, see Lejren, Luk, “Shut Down the Camp,” Luk Lejren, <http://luklejren.dk/spip.php?article14>..>Google Scholar

28 Patsias, C. and Vaillancourt, L., Les églises comme dernier refuge face à la loi: les dilemmes de la désobéissance civile au sein des sociétés démocratiques (Colloque international du Sodrus, L’asile religieux entre désobéissance et obligation légale, Université de Sherbrooke, 7–8 February 2007, <http://www.usherbrooke.ca/politique_appliquee/2e_cycle/cahiers/cahier-6.pdf> [unpublished].Google Scholar

29 On the “No More Deaths” movement and its role in the US-Mexico border, see Caminero-Santangelo, M., “Responding to the Human Costs of US Immigration Policy: No More Deaths and the New Sanctuary Movement” (2009) 7(1) Latino Studies 112 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Failinger, M.A., “No More Deaths: On Conscience, Civil Disobedience, and a New Role for Truth Commissions” (2006) 75 U.M.K.C. L. Rev. 401.Google Scholar See also the earlier, Coutin, S.B., “Smugglers or Samaritans in Tucson, Arizona: Producing and Contesting Legal Truth” (1995) American Ethnologist 549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

30 Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees, 28July 1951, 189 U.N.T.S. 150.

31 Neveu, Erik, Sociologie des mouvements sociaux (Paris: La découverte, 2000) at 3.Google Scholar See also Roberts, A., Civil Resistance in the East European and Soviet Revolutions (Boston: Albert Einstein Institution, 1991).Google Scholar

32 Zunes, S., “Unarmed Insurrections against Authoritarian Governments in the Third World: A New Kind of Revolution” (1994) 15(3) Third World Q. 403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

33 Naidoo, Kumi, “Time for Global Civil Disobedience?: Five Things to Advance the Universal Declaration of Human Rights,” Huffinggton Post (10 December 2008), <http://www.huffingtonpost.com>.Google Scholar

34 Kotiswaran, P., “Preparing for Civil Disobedience: Indian Sex Workers and the Law” (2001) 21 B.C. Third World L.J. 161.Google Scholar

35 Bob, C., “‘Dalit Rights Are Human Rights’: Caste Discrimination, International Activism, and the Construction of a New Human Rights Issue” (2007) 29(1) Hum. Rts. Q. 167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

36 Rucht, D., “Social Movements Challenging Neo-Liberal Globalization” (2006) Civil Society: Berlin Perspectives 189.Google Scholar

37 Diamond, S.F., “Bridging the Divide: An Alternative Approach to International Labor Rights after the Battle of Seattle” (2001) 29 Pepp. L. Rev. 115.Google Scholar

38 Barker, M.D., “Flying over the Judicial Hump: A Human Rights Drama Featuring Burma, the Commonwealth of Massachusetts, the WTO, and the Federal Courts” (2000) 32 Geo. J. Int’l L. 51.Google Scholar

39 “Largest Civil Disobedience on Global Warming in U.S. History Turns up the Heat on Congress,” Greenpeace USA (3 March 2009), <http://www.greenpeace.org/usa/news/largest-civil-disobedience-on>.

40 Hernandez, C.C.G., “Radical Environmentalism: New Civil Disobedience” (2007) 6 Seattle J. Social Justice 289.Google Scholar

41 Rezwan, , “Bangladesh, India: No to Tipaimukh Dam,” Global Voices (27 May 2009), <http://globalvoicesonline.org/2009/05/27/bangladesh-india-no-to-tipaimukh-dam>.Google Scholar

42 Convention on Biological Diversity, 5 June 1992, 31 I.L.M. 818 (1992); Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety, 29 January 2000, <http://sedac.ciesin.org/pidb/texts-menu.html>.

43 Arendt, H., Crises of the Republic (New York: Harcourt, Brace and Jovanovich, 1972) at 49102.Google Scholar

44 Smith, J. and Johnston, H., Globalization and Resistance: Transnational Dimensions of Social Movements (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2002)Google Scholar; Chabot, S., “Transnational Diffusion and the African American Reinvention of Gandhian Repertoire” (2000) 5(2) Mobilization: An International Quarterly 201 Google Scholar; Hayes, G., “Vulnerability and Disobedience: New Repertoires in French Environmental Protests” (2006) 15(5) Environmental Politics 821 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Scalmer, S., “The Labor of Diffusion: The Peace Pledge Union and the Adaptation of the Gandhian Repertoire” (2002) 7(3) Mobilization: An International Quarterly 269.Google Scholar

45 Loesch, M.C., “Motive Testimony and a Civil Disobedience Justification” (1990) 5 N.D. J. L. Ethics & Public Pol’y 1070.Google Scholar

46 A great many comments on civil disobedience in the US context emphasize this aspect and insist that, at the very least, juries should be able to hear arguments drawn from civil disobedience. This is a procedural rather than a substantive position and, as such, rather incomplete (not to mention that the jury issue will not be relevant in all jurisdictions).

47 McMorrow, J.A., “Civil Disobedience and the Lawyer’s Obligation to the Law” (1991) 48 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 139.Google Scholar

48 For a contrary argument, see Colby, C.P., “Civil Disobedience: A Case for Separate Treatment” (1967) 14 Wayne L. Rev. 1165.Google Scholar

49 For reference to a few US cases, see Lippman, M., “Civil Resistance: Revitalizing International Law in the Nuclear Age” (1992) 13 Whittier L. Rev. 17 at 47.Google Scholar

50 Lord (Trident) v. Angela Zelter, Bodil Ulla Roder, Ellen Moxley, Advocate’s Reference no. 1 of 2000 by Her Majesty’s advocate referring for the opinion of the High Court on points of law, 30 March 2001.

51 Moxley, C.J., “The Unlawfulness of the United Kingdom’s Policy of Nuclear Deterrence: The Invalidity of the Scots High Court’s Decision in Zelter” (2001) Jurid. Rev. 319.Google Scholar See also Schwartz, R.E., “Chaos, Oppression, and Rebellion: The Use of Self-Help to Secure Individual Rights under International Law” (1994) 12 B.U. Int’l L.J. 255.Google Scholar

52 United States v. Murdock, 290 U.S. 389 (1933). Also Keegan v. United States, 325 U.S. 478 (1945).

53 The reverse is of course also true — although less interesting for the purposes of this article — in that civil disobedience distorts, or at least purports to distort, the common law defence of necessity. See United States v. Schoon, 971 F.2d at 199 (1992).

54 The exception are a few European Court of Human Rights cases related to civil disobedience, in which the court re-qualified the purported disobedience as being, in fact, an exercise in a legitimate freedom of expression. Since it was not for the state to punish the conduct in question in the first place, the issue of civil disobedience did not truly arise in any strong sense. See case of Irfan Temel and others v. Turkey (2009), Application no. 36458/02, Judgment, 3 March 2009, European Court of Human Rights <http://www.echr.coe.int>.

55 Bull, H., Hurrell, A., and Hoffmann, S., The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 2002).Google Scholar

56 Porter, R.O., “Tribal Disobedience” (2005) 11 Tex. J. on Cl. & Cr. 137.Google Scholar

57 Bloomfield, Janet, “Resisting the British Bomb: Recent Times,” in Holdstock, D. and Barnaby, F., eds., The British Nuclear Weapons Programme, 1952–2002 (N.p.: Routledge, 2003).Google Scholar

58 Starr, A., Global Revolt: A Guide to the Movements against Globalization (New York: Zed Books, 2005) at 63.Google Scholar

59 Appadurai, Arjun, “Broken Promises” (2002) 132 Foreign Policy 42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

60 On the theme of the effectiveness of civil disobedience, see Stephan, M.J. and Chenoweth, E., “Why Civil Resistance Works: The Strategic Logic of Nonviolent Conflict” (2008) 33(1) International Security 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

61 Mégret, Frédéric, “Le droit international peut-il être un droit de résistance? Dix conditions pour un renouveau de l’ambition normative internationale” (2008) 39 Études internationales 39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

62 There are many defenses of civil disobedience of this sort. See Haksar, V., “The Right to Civil Disobedience” (2003) 41 Osgoode Hall L.J. 407.Google Scholar

63 Habermas, J. and Calhoun, M., “Right and Violence: A German Trauma” (1985) 1 Cultural Critique 125 at 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

64 Beauverger, Benjamin, La désobéissance civique, de nouvelles perspectives pour la séparation des pouvoirs (Congrès de Paris: VIIe Congrès français de droit constitutionnel, Paris 2008), <http://www.droitconstitutionnel.org/>.Google Scholar

65 See, for example, Marks, J. and Crawford, S., “The Global Democracy Deficit: An Essay in International Law and its Limits,” in Archibugi, D. and Held, D., eds., ReimaginingPolitical Community: Studies in Cosmopolitan Democracy (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1998).Google Scholar

66 Kutner, L., “Due Process of Rebellion” (1972) 7 Val. U.L. Rev. 1 at 50.Google Scholar

67 Indeed, civil disobeyers themselves have often pointed out that their approach is often the only alternative to violent confrontation, since the status quo is in-tolerable. For example, Luther King emphasized civil disobedience as the only “alternative to riots.”

68 Zunes, supra note 32 at 406. Stephan, M.J. and Mundy, J., “A Battlefield Transformed: From Guerilla Resistance to Mass Nonviolent Struggle in the Western Sahara” (2006) 8(3) J. Military and Strategic Stud. 2.Google Scholar

69 See, for example, the discussion of the petition, first printed in al-Quds on 19 June 2002 and signed by prominent Palestinian public figures condemning resort to suicide bombings against Israeli civilians in Allen, L.A., “Palestinians Debate ‘Polite’ Resistance to Occupation” (2002) Middle East Report 38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

70 Melber, H., “The Virtues of Civil Courage and Civil Disobedience in the Historical Context of Namibia and South Africa” (2001) 28(2) Politikon 236 at 236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

71 Indeed, one of the criticisms of civil disobedience theorizing is too great a readiness to accept certain basic assumptions about what makes law constraining. Howenstein, M.S, “Procrustes and His Bed: Limits of the Modern Theory of Civil Disobedience” (1997) 21 Legal Stud. F. 541.Google Scholar On the relationship between obedience and disobedience, law and non-law, and a critique of the idea that law morally (always) requires obedience, see Zinn, H., “Law, Justice and Disobedience” (1990) 5 N.D. J.L., Ethics & Public Pol’y 899.Google Scholar See also Lyons, D., “Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience” (1998) Philosophy and Public Affairs 31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

72 See Simmons, A.J., “Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law,” in Frey, R. and Wellman, C., eds., A Companion to Applied Ethics (Cornwall, UK: Wiley-Black-well, 2003) at 50.Google Scholar

73 Cohen, C., “Civil Disobedience and the Law” (1966) 21 Rutgers L. Rev. 1.Google Scholar

74 Falk, supra note 20 at 263.

75 Turenne, S., “Judicial Responses to Civil Disobedience: A Comparative Approach” (2004) 10(4) Res Publica 379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar It is interesting that Turenne mixes invocations of human rights with references to the European Convention on Human Rights as a “federating element of European societies,” which makes “consideration of the civil isobedient’s claims imperative.”

76 Dworkin, supra note 6 at 112.

77 Bauer, S.M. and Eckerstrom, P.J., “The State Made Me Do It: The Applicability of the Necessity Defense to Civil Disobedience” (1986) 39 Stan. L. Rev. 1173 at 1176, n. 1117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

78 This is reflected by the increasing tendency of civil disobedience to be framed in terms of “civil resistance,” where violation of the law is not acknowledged. Lippman, M., “Civil Resistance: The Dictates of Conscience and International Law versus the American Judiciary” (1990) 6 Fla. J. Int’l L. 5 at 7.Google Scholar

79 Nonn, Tim, “Charting a New Course for the Darfur Movement,” The Promise of Engagement, <http://bechamilton.com/?p=1050>..>Google Scholar

80 Reisman, W.M., “The Tormented Conscience: Applying and Appraising Unauthorized Coercion” (1983) 32 Emory L.J. 499.Google Scholar

81 Dworkin, supra note 6 at 115. This is validated by history. For example, “freedom riders” in the American South were eventually vindicated by the Supreme Court of the United States, which found that their interpretation of the law, not the South’s police, was the right one. Needless to say, they did not complain that they were not ultimately punished for their acts. In other words, being punished for having violated an unjust law is not ultimately the goal of disobeyers, although it may certainly be a tactical goal.

82 Dworkin, C., “Civil Disobedience: The Case against Prosecution” (1968) 10(6) N.Y. Rev. Books 6.Google Scholar

83 Boyle, F.A., Protesting Power: War, Resistance, and Law (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, 2007) at 41.Google Scholar

84 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, supra note 23.

85 This was the case for example after the Vietnam War.

86 Falk, supra note 20 at 261–63.

87 Boyle, supra note 83 at 10.

88 Lambek, B.D., “Necessity and International Law: Arguments for the Legality of Civil Disobedience” (1986) 5 Yale L. & Pol’y Rev. 472 at 489–91.Google Scholar

89 Streletz, Kessler and Krenz v. Germany (2001), 33 E.H.R.R. 31. However, it is important to note that the case involved officials and not ordinary citizens. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 999 U.N.T.S. 171.

90 This is consonant, at least in the common law, with the quite central idea that one cannot commit crimes by omission except in cases where a prior duty to act exists. This duty to act is typically a function of a higher degree of responsibility imposed in certain cases, in the case of the military a higher capacity to provoke harm.

91 See, for example, United States v. Montgomery, 772 F.2d 733 (11th Cir. 1985).

92 In State v. Marley, 54 Haw. 450, 509 P.2d (1973), the court dismissed as “frivolous any contention that (the defendants) were legally obligated to act to avoid criminal liability” under Nuremberg principles.

93 See, in particular, Coutin, S.B., “Enacting Law through Social Practice: Sanctuary as a Form of Resistance,” in Falk, Sally F., ed., Law and Anthropology: A Reader (Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell, 2005) 278.Google Scholar

94 In this respect, an argument for decentralized enforcement through civil resistance might emphasize that, for all of its drive to centralization and institution-alization, the international community remains in an embryonic state and is often incapable of honouring some of its most cherished international commitments. See Mégret, Frédéric, “Beyond the ‘Salvation Paradigm’: Responsibility to Protect (Others) v. the Power of Protecting Oneself” (2009) 40 Security Dialogue [forthcoming in 2009].CrossRefGoogle Scholar Also Stephan, M.J. and Mundy, J., “A Battlefield Transformed: From Guerilla Resistance to Mass Nonviolent Struggle in the Western Sahara” (2006) 8(3) J. Military and Strategic Stud. 2 at 1012 Google Scholar; Falk, R., “The East Timor Ordeal: International Law and Its Limits” (2000) 32(1–2) Bulletin of Concerned Asian Scholars 49 Google Scholar; and Wedgwood, R., “Gallant Delusions” (2002) 132 Foreign Policy 44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

95 Delf, G., Humanizing Hell!: The Law v. Nuclear Weapons (N.p.: Hamish Hamilton, 1985) at 53.Google Scholar

96 Lord Advocate’s Reference No. 1 of 2000, (2002) 122 I.L.R. at 651, [2000] H.C.J.T. 1. (defendants arguing that they “acted in the knowledge that the only effective remedy open to us to prevent a nuclear holocaust was to join with other ‘global citizens’ in an effort to enforce the law ourselves as the Government, judiciary, police and other institutions were not willing to do it themselves”).

97 Lippman, M., “The Right of Civil Resistance under International Law and the Domestic Necessity Defense” (1989) 8 Penn State Int’l L. Rev. 349 at 350.Google Scholar See also Le Héno, Valérie, La désobéissance: un Moteur d’évolution (2009), Scribd, <http://www.scribd.com/doc/10054900/La-desobeissance-Un-Moteur-devolution> Google Scholar: (“parce que les autorités et pouvoirs politiques désobéissent, eux, à leur promesse de tout faire pour que les Droits de l’Homme sortent de leur idéalité”).

98 See “Captain Paul Watson Responds to the Director-General of the Japanese Institute of Cetacean Research,” Sea Sheppard News (27 December 2005), <http://www.seashepherd.org/news-and-media/news-051227-1.html>. As it happens, the argument is sketchy at best from a legal positive point of view. The provision invoked — section 21 — of the Charter is merely a standard reference to the fact that non-state entities “to the extent that they are able … shall” implement relevant provisions. In addition, the Charter is really only a soft law argument. However, merely pointing out the unorthodoxy of Captain Watson’s sort of reasoning would miss the point, in that this agency is claimed even if it is not actually conferred by international law. UN General Assembly, World Charter for Nature, Doc. A/Res/37/7 (28 October 1982),

99 Boyle, supra note 83 at 41.

100 There is obviously an old tradition in international law that has defended this point of view, most notably in France with the likes of Duguit and Scelle. Inter-estingly, Duguit also considered that there were significant limits to obedience to unjust laws. See Hiez, D., La désobéissance civile: Approches politiques et juridiques (Villeneuve-d’Ascq: Presses universitaires du Septentrion, 2008) at 59.Google Scholar

101 Mégret, Frédéric, “The Nature of Human Rights Obligations,” in Moeckli, Daniel et al., eds., International Human Rights Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press) [forthcoming in 2010].Google Scholar

102 It is interesting in this respect to reflect on the fact that the idea of erga omnes norms is often framed as being that the violation of certain norms “shocks the conscience of humanity.” The fact that the expression “humanity” is used suggests that something more is at stake than states being “shocked.”

103 Franck, supra note 1 at 11.

104 The issue of the moral authority of the state to govern is, probably much more than in international law, a central concern in political and moral theory. See Copp, D., “The Idea of a Legitimate State” (1999) Philosophy and Public Affairs 3 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wellman, C.H. and Simmons, A.J., Is There a Duty to Obey the Law? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

105 Roth, B.R., Governmental Illegitimacy in International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).Google Scholar

106 Island of Palmas case (1928) 1 R.I.A.A. 829, 839 (Arbitrator Huber), 4 I.L.R. 3.

107 Agenda Item 61, UN GAOR, 5th Sess., UN Doc. A/AC.38/L.21 (1950) at 6 (Annexes): “[A]government … should be recognized if that government … has the obedience of the bulk of the population of that territory in such a way that this control, authority, and obedience appear to be of a permanent character”).

108 See, for example, the Convention on Duties and Rights of States in the Event of Civil Strive, 10 February 1928, 134 L.N.T.S. 45 (entered into force 21 May 1928).

109 It should be noted in passing, though, that international law’s increasing proclivity to reflect on the legitimacy of domestic systems may also provide arguments against civil disobedience — for example, when it considers that a state is legitimate domestically and finds little cause to resort to extreme tactics.

110 Goodin, R.E., “Toward an International Rule of Law: Distinguishing International Law-Breakers from Would-be Law-Makers” (2005) 9(1) Journal of Ethics 225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

111 Cogan, J.K., “Noncompliance and the International Rule of Law” (2006) 31 Yale J. Int’l L. 189 at 190.Google Scholar

112 Cogan’s theorization of “operational noncompliance” is very relevant here, even though it only seems to apply to states and not civil society. Ibid. Also Wheeler, N.J., “Humanitarian Vigilantes or Legal Entrepreneurs: Enforcing Human Rights in International Society” (2000) 3(1) Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

113 Of course, the domestic system defined by the state is in a sense exactly the contrary of a decentralized system, and, under normal conditions, its constituent parts (individuals, citizens) are characteristically not supposed to “take the law in their own hands.” However, if this system is fundamentally unjust and in contravention of fundamental international norms, one can argue that the domestic legal order either dissolves or is sidelined by international law, so that the individual finds herself as a sort of newfound depository of international personhood. The civil disobeyer thus operates in a decentralized system, left vacant by the waning of a fundamentally “unjust” domestic order.

114 Falk, Richard A. and Mendlovitz, Saul H., The Strategy of World Order (New York: World Law Fund, 1966) at 310.Google Scholar

115 In addition, one should probably add a non-criterion, which is the issue of whether the state laws/policy involved are either domestic or international. I think that should be largely irrelevant if the laws/policies involved actually intersect with any of the listed criteria. Although civil disobedience will often be primarily geared towards domestic decisions, it may very well target the state’s foreign policy or, more likely, a mix of domestic and foreign policies (draft dodging in the context of the Vietnam War, for example, was based both on anti-imperialist “international” grounds and on a “domestic” resistance against the draft, which, at least in the circumstances, was seen as an abuse of its power by the state).

116 In the East German Border Guards case before various German courts after reunification, the ideas of legal philosopher Gustav Radbruch (that a legal system loses this quality if it excessively departs from certain standards ofjustice, a line of argument also associated with Fuller in the Anglo-American tradition) were largely accepted. See Quint, P.E., “The Border Guard Trials and the East German Past-Seven Arguments” (2000) 48 Am. J. Comp. L. 541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

117 One can imagine certain situations of state deliquescence — for example, an occupation — where it would be legitimate for civil disobeyers to stand up for the interests of an absent sovereign. On this subject more generally, see Mégret, F., “Grandeur et déclin de l’idée de résistance à l’occupation: à propos des ‘insurgés” (2010) Revue belge de droit international [forthcoming in 2010].Google Scholar

118 Allowance may be made for the more or less functional character of the democracy in relation to the problem at hand. For example, one of the key theoretical justifications of civil disobedience in defence of the environment even in democracies is that democracies have been very bad at taking the sort of massive action that would be required by a threat such as catastrophic global warming.

119 See, for example, “Declaration of Francis A. Boyle,” in USA v. Carol Gilbert, Jackie Marie Hudson and Ardeth Platte, Criminal Case no. 02-CR-509 R B (N.D. Col. 2002) (United States District Court for the District of ColoradoChapters, <http://chapters.scarecrowpress.com/07/425/0742538923ch1.pdf> (alleging a “breakdown in the Constitutional principle of checks and balances which implements the separation of powers”).

120 See Williams v. Wallace, 240 F. Supp. 100 (M.D. Ala. 1965).

121 For example, individuals often have to exhaust domestic remedies before they can bring a case to an international body.

122 Although proposals of the sort have no doubt been made. See, for example, Raskin, Marcus G., The Common Good: Its Politics, Policies, and Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 1986) at 298 Google Scholar; Lippman, supra note 97.

123 Bay, Christian, “Civil Disobedience,” in Parsons, T. and Sills, D., eds., International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (New York: Macmillan-Free Press, 1968) at 478.Google Scholar

124 Etienne Balibar has developed this idea of “foundational transgression.” See Balibar, E., “L’État d’urgence démocratique,” Le Monde (19 February 1997).Google Scholar