Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T23:58:01.766Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justification, Conformity, and the Norm of Belief

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 January 2019

Davide Fassio*
Affiliation:
Zhejiang University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

According to a popular view in contemporary epistemology, a belief is justified if, and only if, it amounts to knowledge. Upholders of this view also hold that knowledge is the fundamental norm governing belief and that conforming to this norm is both necessary and sufficient for justification. I argue against the claim that mere norm conformity is sufficient for justification. Rather, justification requires norm conformity for sufficient undefeated reasons. An important consequence is the rejection of the claim that conformity to the norm of belief is necessary and sufficient for epistemic justification. I illustrate some interesting consequences of this result.

Selon une thèse populaire en épistémologie contemporaine, une croyance est justifiée si, et seulement si, elle est une connaissance. Les défenseurs de cette thèse soutiennent également que la connaissance est la norme fondamentale de la croyance et que la conformité à cette norme est à la fois nécessaire et suffisante pour la justification. Je conteste l’affirmation selon laquelle la simple conformité à une norme suffit à justifier une croyance. La justification exige la conformité pour des raisons suffisantes et «invaincues» (undefeated). Une conséquence de ceci est le rejet de la thèse selon laquelle la conformité à la norme de la croyance est nécessaire et suffisante pour la justification épistémique.

Type
Original Article/Article original
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2019

According to a popular view in contemporary epistemology, a belief is justified if, and only if, it amounts to knowledge.Footnote 1 This claim fits within a general externalist framework of epistemic normativity in which the notion of knowledge plays a central role. In this framework, a justified belief is a belief conforming to the fundamental norm governing this attitude. For a belief to be justified, conformity to this norm is both necessary and sufficient. Any beliefs that do not conform to this norm are not fully defensible from rational criticisms, and thus not fully justified—at best they can be blameless and excusable if they manifest a general disposition to comply with the norm. If only knowledge can justify belief, and norm conformity is necessary and sufficient for justification, then only knowledge can be the norm of belief. The resulting framework is one in which knowledge is the necessary and sufficient condition for a series of properties including epistemic justification, full epistemic defensibility, and conformity to the norm of belief.

This broadly externalist knowledge-based model of epistemic normativity has several virtues. For example, the model is particularly well placed to address traditional problems affecting externalist accounts of justification, such as the New Evil Demon Problem.Footnote 2 A main rationale for this model relies on parallels with the use of central normative notions in other normative disciplines, in particular in the practical and legal domains, where the notion of justification is most often employed and discussed. The suggestion is to look at how notions such as ‘justification,’ ‘reason,’ and ‘excuse’ are used in these domains, and theorize by analogy about the corresponding notions in the epistemic domain.Footnote 3 This methodology relies on the assumption that normative frameworks in different domains share some deep similarities.Footnote 4 This approach has the advantage of bypassing intricate epistemological debates muddled by technical terminology and marred by an excessive appeal to intuitions about specific cases,Footnote 5 and allows epistemologists to avoid neglecting important and subtle normative distinctions, such as those between ‘justified,’ ‘rational,’ and ‘excused.’ The hope is that once these distinctions are appreciated in their full generality, real progress in the debate will be possible.

In this paper, I shall grant many of the assumptions of those who endorse this model: first, I will assume the same general framework and methodology; second, I will assume that the arguments advanced by these philosophers succeed in showing that justification cannot require anything less than norm conformity, that justification requires full defensibility from rational criticisms, and that only knowledge can grant full justification to belief. My contention is with the claims that mere conformity to a norm suffices for epistemic justification and that only knowledge can be the norm of belief. This is where, in my view, the equation

$$knowledge\, = \,full\,defensiblity\, = \,justification\, = \,norm\,conformity$$

fails, at the level of the last equivalence. I will show that the claim that norm conformity is sufficient for justification is not supported by analogical considerations about the use of the corresponding notion in the practical and legal domains. I will argue that there are very good grounds to reject this claim and endorse a view in which justification requires more than norm conformity. More precisely, I will suggest that justification requires conformity to a norm for sufficient undefeated reasons. This claim has received substantial support from many authors in other normative domains. While this conclusion concerns primarily practical and legal justification, one can mount an argument by analogy for the conclusion that a justified belief requires conforming to the norm of this attitude for sufficient undefeated reasons. Besides being of interest in itself, this result has very important consequences for the general model of epistemic normativity discussed by these philosophers. In particular, assuming that a justified belief requires knowledge, if justification can require more than conformity to the norm of belief, it follows that the norm of belief can be some property falling short of knowledge, such as truth.

Here is the plan of this article. In §1, I introduce the general externalist normative framework assumed by upholders of the knowledge-based model. I stress in particular a disagreement amongst philosophers endorsing this framework on whether justification requires mere conformity to a norm or something more than that. In §2, I present four arguments against the view that mere norm conformity is sufficient for justification. Some of these arguments also indicate that justification requires conformity for sufficient undefeated reasons. I also consider and address two possible objections to these arguments based on the alleged distinctions between personal and act justification and between act-type and act-token justification. In §3, I argue that, once we abandon the assumption that justification requires mere conformity to a norm, a familiar line of argument in support of the knowledge norm of belief fails. I also show that if we accept the claim that justification requires more than mere norm conformity, a similar line of argument turns out to support a norm of belief requiring a condition weaker than knowledge, such as truth. In §4, I sketch how a model of epistemic normativity can be developed from a truth norm of belief within the present externalist normative framework. I also stress some important differences between this model and the views of other epistemologists endorsing a truth norm of belief.

Two preliminary remarks are in order here. First, as I said above, the present discussion will assume that upholders of the knowledge-based model are right on several issues. I am aware that some of these assumptions are rather contentious. Philosophers disagreeing with such assumptions are free to read my conclusions as merely conditional. Second, for ease of exposition, my discussion in this paper will mainly follow the framework and terminology developed by Clayton Littlejohn, who has spent more effort than others in developing and defending the present model and methodology.Footnote 6 With minor terminological modifications, the same arguments apply to other similar views.

1. The Normative Framework

The general normative framework assumed by upholders of the knowledge-based model is broadly inspired by works in contemporary practical philosophy and philosophy of law (e.g., Maria Alvarez, John Gardner, Joseph Raz, Judith Jarvis Thompson), as well as by more traditional works on justification and excuses (e.g., John Austin, Peter Strawson). This framework develops around the notions of norm, reason, justification and excuses.

Norm. The central notion in this model is that of a norm, where this notion is here used in a general sense not restricted to the moral domain. Norms in this broad sense include all kind of obligations, permissions, and prohibitions.Footnote 7 Norms governing specific normative subdomains are issued by independent authoritative sources and characterize those subdomains: for example, norms governing morality specify moral normativity, laws specify legal normativity, and so on. Besides moral norms—such as the duty to keep one’s promises—typical examples of norms considered by these philosophers are rules of games and laws, norms whose conditions of satisfaction and application are fully external and objective.

An important distinction in this framework is between conformity and compliance to a norm. An agent conforms to a norm when she does what the norm requires and violates the norm when she doesn’t. An agent complies with a norm when, in addition to conforming to it, she does it because she is guided by that norm. Normative guidance here shouldn’t be conceived as involving full awareness of the norm. An implicit form of sensitivity to normative reasons is sufficient.Footnote 8 We can conceive compliance with a norm as equivalent to conformity on the basis of reasons that the norm provides. One can conform to a norm without being guided by it, or even without intending to comply with it. If Cody promises Lara that he’ll go to the party tonight, he will conform to the norm of promise-keeping if and only if he does go to the party. No matter whether Cody intends to keep his promise and tries his hardest to keep it, or whether he reasonably believes he has kept it, if Cody doesn’t go to the party, he will break his promise. And, if Cody does go to the party, he will conform to the promise-keeping norm no matter the reason for which he went to the party.Footnote 9

Reason. Reasons are facts or true propositions.Footnote 10 Normative reasons are facts counting in favour of performing certain actions or holding certain attitudes and contributing to making these actions and attitudes right or appropriate. The ‘favouring’ relation is understood as objective and independent of the access of agents to reasons. That today is Sunday is a normative reason for Jack not to go to work, even though Jack doesn’t ‘have’ this reason, i.e., he doesn’t know that it is Sunday, and consequently cannot be motivated by that not to go to work. In the present framework, norms determine which facts count as reasons. For example, the moral duty to keep one’s promise makes the fact that Cody promised to Lara to go to the party tonight a reason to do what he promised. Motivating reasons are a subset of normative reasons. They are the reasons for which a subject performs an action or holds an attitude, and highlight the features that the agent took to make her actions or attitudes right, appropriate, or fitting.Footnote 11

Justification. While philosophers endorsing this framework agree on the notions of norm and reason, for justification the agreement is only partial. On the one hand, there is a general agreement that a necessary condition for justification is doing what is all things considered right or permissible: in order to be justified to φ, there must be undefeated sufficient normative reasons to φ. An agent who does what she ought not to do cannot be justified, no matter her perspective on the facts.Footnote 12 Justification to φ is compatible with there being pro tanto reasons not to φ. For example, someone killing in legitimate self-defence is justified to the extent that she did what she ought to do in her particular circumstance, even though she also had pro tanto reasons not to kill. Such reasons are not cancelled or undermined, but merely defeated, outweighed by other reasons that make it all things considered right to kill in these specific circumstances. The thought that justification requires doing what is supported by sufficient undefeated reasons can also be put in terms of norm conformity: when the norms governing a certain φ-ing do not generate conflicting demands, if S justifiably φ-s, S conforms to these norms.

On the other hand, these philosophers disagree on whether doing what is all things considered right or permitted (thereby acting in conformity to the relevant norms) is also sufficient for justification. Littlejohn explicitly identifies the conditions for justification and those for norm conformity. For example, he claims that “[s]omething is justified when there’s sufficient reason for it and we determine whether there’s sufficient reason for something by considering whether it conforms to the relevant norms”Footnote 13 and “[t]o determine whether S’s φ-ing was justified, we have to ask whether S conformed to the norms that applied to her in φ-ing.”Footnote 14 For Littlejohn, we are justified to φ simply by the presence of sufficient normative reasons to φ, no matter what our motivating reasons are.Footnote 15 Here, Littlejohn’s view diverges from that of other philosophers in the practical and legal domain often quoted in his works. For example, Gardner explicitly denies that justification is mere norm conformity. After criticizing the idea that there are two notions of justification, one subjective and related to motivating reasons and the other objective and related to normative reasons, he focuses on the ‘fundamental conceptual’ question of whether justification depends upon normative (guiding) reasons or motivating (explanatory) reasons:

The answer, irritating but unavoidable, is that it depends upon both. No action or belief is justified unless it is true both that there was an applicable (guiding) reason for so acting or so believing and that this corresponded with the (explanatory) reason why the action was performed or the belief held. … [F]rom whatever point of view one claims justification for one’s actions or beliefs, one claims justification only if one claims both that there were, from that point of view, reasons for one to act or believe as one did and that one’s reasons for performing the act or holding the belief were among these reasons.Footnote 16

According to Gardner, for being justified to φ, it is not sufficient that there are some undefeated normative reasons to φ. In addition, some of these reasons must also be the one(s) for which the agent φ-ed. When an agent φ-s justifiably, a normative reason to φ becomes also the reason that motivates the agent to φ and explains why she φ-ed. The present disagreement on the notion of justification reflects a more general dispute in criminal law between those considering justification to be a matter of mere conformity to norms, sometimes called ‘deed’ theorists, and those who think that justification requires more than that, such as conformity for sufficient undefeated reasons.Footnote 17 In the next section, I will provide arguments against the former view and in favour of the latter.

Excuse. Justifications should not be confused with excuses. Excuses are appropriate only when one lacks justification. They are defences appealing to how one reasonably saw the world rather than how it really was, pointing to some non-culpable lack of information about the circumstances (blameless mistakes, misevaluation of the situation …).Footnote 18 An agent is excusable for φ-ing if, even though there are not sufficient undefeated reasons for the agent to φ, she φ-ed on what she wrongly but reasonably took to be sufficient undefeated reasons for φ-ing.Footnote 19

2. Is Justification Mere Conformity to a Norm?

In this section, I consider four arguments against the view that mere norm conformity is sufficient for justification. Some of these arguments also positively support a notion of justification as doing the right thing for sufficient undefeated reasons. The first three arguments are original; the fourth is Gardner’s. I also consider and address a couple of possible objections to the view that justification requires more than norm conformity.

Argument 1: Evidence from Legal Practice

Some preliminary support for the idea that justification requires more than mere norm conformity comes from one of the domains in which the notion of justification is more often used, namely, criminal law. As Gardner observes, “So far as I can see, our judges persist in using the word ‘justification’ to refer mainly to legal justifications proper, i.e., to legally recognized reasons for acting which were also the relevant agent’s reasons for acting in the case under consideration.”Footnote 20 Gardner mentions, as a paradigmatic example, the so-called Dadson doctrine, named after a real case involving a prisoner’s ‘unknown self-defence.’ The sentence says: “The prosecutor not having committed a felony known to the prisoner at the time when he fired, the latter was not justified in firing at the prosecutor.”Footnote 21 As Gardner observes, this sentence implies a notion of justification according to which, in order to be justified, the prisoner firing upon the prosecutor must have at least known the prosecutor’s intentions at the time when he fired. It must be stressed here that even the critics of the view that justification is more than conformity, such as Paul H. Robinson, recognize that a dual requirement for justification (that the actor both performs the right deed and acts for the right reason) would get support from current law, which denies a defence to the unknowingly right actor who uses force against an attacker for the wrong reason.Footnote 22

Argument 2: Full Defensibility Requires More Than Conformity

A point on which many agree is that justification requires full defensibility from possible rational criticisms. According to Gardner, justification is a type of defence that can fully exculpate an agent for φ-ing (even if it can admit pro tanto reasons not to φ). An agent is fully justified to φ only when her φ-ing can be fully defended from possible rational objections. Only the unobjectionable is in no need of justification.Footnote 23 Littlejohn seems to agree on this point. For example, he claims that proper blame excludes justification. The facts in light of which someone can be properly blamed threaten the justificatory status of her attitudes or actions.Footnote 24 Some of the arguments of both Littlejohn and Timothy Williamson for the claim that the norm of belief cannot be anything less than knowledge rely more or less explicitly on this assumption.Footnote 25

This notion of ‘full defensibility’ doesn’t square well with the idea that justification is mere norm conformity. Rather, it fits well with the idea that full justification requires, in addition to the presence of sufficient reasons for the subject to φ, that the subject also φ-s for some of these reasons, for only in the latter circumstance could her φ-ing be fully defensible from possible objections. Mere norm conformity seems insufficient to alone make the agent fully defensible and rationally unobjectionable. If, for example, there are sufficient reasons for an agent to φ, but she takes there not to be sufficient reasons to φ, her φ-ing will be open to criticisms and thus not fully defensible, even though it was right for her to φ in the circumstances. Reflection about specific cases can help us see this point more clearly:Footnote 26

Reckless Driver. Ramon drives his car through a crossroad completely ignoring the presence of traffic lights on his way. As it happens, lights are green. Ramon’s action is permissible: the presence of green lights is a sufficient reason to cross the road. Even though Ramon did a permissible thing, his driving through the crossroad is not fully defensible. In particular, his action was reckless and not exempt from criticisms for not showing the due respect to street regulations.

Lucky Chess Player. Levon is playing a chess match in a tournament. It is his turn to move and he is seriously undecided between three possible moves. He is running out of time and must make a move in the next few seconds. He randomly chooses one move from amongst the three candidates. As it happens, that is the best move. However, he didn’t make that move because he took it to be the best. Levon’s move is not fully defensible and beyond criticism. Conformity to a standard of good moves doesn’t provide a full defence for Levon’s choice in the situation. His random move, though right, needs some excuse (e.g., ‘well, I didn’t choose on the basis of a well pondered choice, but I was in time trouble and had to make a move …’).

Accidental Promise Keeper. Elena has promised Mike to be in London on Monday. While she doesn’t make any effort to keep the promise, by mere accident, she happens to be in London on Monday. Although Elena did what she promised, one may still complain about her conduct, for she didn’t keep the promise for the right reason. Intuitively, Elena’s action is not fully defensible and exempt from criticisms. Apologies to Mike would make perfect sense in the circumstance.Footnote 27

The mere conformity view of justification entails that, since the agents in the above cases do what there is reason for them to do, they are justified, fully defensible, and beyond criticisms. In particular, this view delivers the verdict that, as long as the agents’ actions conform to the norms relevant in their circumstances, these agents and their actions can be as defensible as someone who in their place would have acted for good reasons. This is a very counterintuitive consequence of the view. As the above examples show, it seems obvious that the subjects in the above cases cannot claim full defensibility for their actions, which, although right, are clearly not exempt from rational criticisms. It seems also obvious that subjects in counterpart cases conforming to norms for good reasons could claim more defensibility than those in the present cases.

A related problem well illustrated by the above cases is the following. Many philosophers in the practical and legal domain consider justification a type of defence of which a rational subject could avail herself, along with other defences, such as excuses. Full defensibility presupposes that in normal circumstances a fully rational agent aware of her own motivations is in a position to fully defend herself from possible challenges. However, the agents in the above cases do not have this ability: Ramon, in Reckless Driver, completely ignores that there was a reason to drive his car through the crossroad, namely, that lights were green. He is unable to avail himself of this reason if someone challenged him asking why he passed through the crossroad. Similarly, both Levon and Elena, in Lucky Chess Player and Accidental Promise Keeper, cannot properly avail themselves of the reasons there were for doing the things they did. Indeed, it seems appropriate for them to defend their actions by putting forward excuses rather than justifications, and excuses are appropriate only in the absence of justification.Footnote 28

A possible reply in defence of the conformity view is that, while the agents in the above examples act in conformity to a norm, they are violating some other norm sanctioning, not the act, but the attempt or the intentions of the agent. These agents would be at the same time justified in virtue of conforming to the act-norm, but unjustified for violating the attempt-norm. This strategy was first discussed by Robinson, the main proponent of the conformity view. Robinson considers cases of agents doing the right things but for the wrong reasons. Here it is a variant on his well-known attacker-thought-to-be-a-jogger example (which is significantly similar to the Dadson doctrine considered above):

Attacker-Thought-To-Be-A-Jogger. Paul sees that what looks to him like a jogger is approaching. Actually, this person is not a jogger but a robber planning an attack on him. However, Paul is completely ignorant of this fact. To him the person is just a common jogger running there by chance. When the person is sufficiently close, Paul gives him a strong punch on the face, causing the person’s loss of consciousness, and thus preventing the aggression. However, Paul completely ignores the bad intentions of the person and the threat. His motives to punch the person are malicious and completely unreasonable (say, to test the strength of his punch on the first person he meets).

Robinson’s diagnosis of this type of case is that the use of force against the attacker-thought-to-be-a-jogger is fully justified, because Paul acts in conformity to the law permitting the use of force when this is necessary to prevent an imminent unlawful harm. However, Paul may be liable for an attempt to unjustifiably assault another person.Footnote 29

This diagnosis of the case is implausible for several reasons. The main problem is that it is implausible that someone can be punished for an attempted aggression when she actually succeeded in performing that aggression. In this circumstance, the attempt is inseparable from the performed action. There simply are not two things to evaluate: an action and an attempt, but a unique thing, an action, which constitutively involves a successful attempt. We cannot punish the attempt without punishing the action. At most, we can punish the action for the attempt it involves rather than for its consequences—i.e., we can explain why we punish the action by pointing to a specific aspect of it. But, contra Robinson, we should judge the action to be unjustified and we should punish it. The very same considerations apply if we substitute ‘attempt’ with ‘intention.’ Since in the above case Paul’s intention is an inseparable constituent of his action, we cannot punish the intention without punishing the action. Paul doesn’t merely try to use force on the passerby; he actually uses it. Hence, he is liable for assault, not merely for attempted or intended assault.Footnote 30 The existence of a real threat for Paul can at most provide reasons to mitigate the punishment on the ground that the action is partially defensible under a specific aspect of it, namely, for its consequences. Similar considerations are valid for the above examples: what is deemed not fully defensible (and thus unjustified) in all these cases is not the attempt or the intention to perform a forbidden action, but the very performance of an action which, though right, is not done for sufficient reasons.Footnote 31

Argument 3: Justification Is Comparable, Norm Conformity Isn’t

Justification admits of comparisons. It is natural to compare the justifications that one has for doing different things or believing distinct propositions. For example, it is natural to say things like ‘I am more justified to believe that 2+2=4 than that Kathmandu is the capital of Nepal,’ or ‘when it comes to helping others, altruism is a better justification than egoistic reasons such as receiving credit for it.’Footnote 32 In general, we tend to ascribe more or better justification to actions or attitudes done or held for better reasons. This is problematic for the conformity view, for conformity to a norm doesn’t admit of degrees or comparisons: if a norm requires one to φ, an agent conforms to it if she φ-s, and doesn’t if she fails to φ. One can be more or less blameworthy, rational, or excusable, but one cannot be more or less right, permitted, or forbidden. It is a well-known and recognized fact that permission, obligation, and forbearance do not admit of degrees or comparisons (either an action is obligatory or it is not),Footnote 33 and norm conformity is just a matter of doing what is obligatory or permitted and avoiding doing what it is forbidden. A conformity view equating justification and conformity doesn’t have a simple explanation of comparative justification.

It is helpful here to compare this to the doing-the-right-thing-for-sufficient-undefeated-reasons view of justification (hereafter, DRTSUR). The latter view can easily explain different strengths of justification, for according to this view the reasons for which one acts matter for justification: one can φ for sufficient reasons R, which can be better or worse compared to other sufficient reasons R* for φ-ing. In this perspective, an action can be more justified than another, for there may be two sets of reasons for which one may φ which are equally sufficient to φ, but one set of reasons is better than the other. For example, while altruism and receiving credit are both sufficient reasons to help others, and both can justify the action, helping others for the former reason is better than for the latter. In contrast, the conformity view cannot explain why doing something for certain reasons is more justified than doing it for others. According to this view, the reasons for which one performs the action do not play any justificatory role at all.

An upholder of the conformity view may reply that her view can account for justification comparisons in the following way. This view admits that, within a set of permitted actions, there can be more reasons to perform certain actions than others. Justification comparisons could then depend on the comparative reasons there are—reasons determining what it is all things considered right to do—rather than those for which one acted. The problem with this reply is that strength of justification doesn’t depend on the reasons there are, but on the reasons for which one acts. Compare two agents, A and B, for which there are all things considered sufficient reasons to use force against aggressors. However, while B uses force against her aggressor for sufficient reasons (she knows about the imminent threat), A completely ignores the threat and uses the force on the attacker for vicious motives (say, because she likes causing harm to people). If we had to compare justification based on the reasons there are, A’s use of force would be as justified as B’s. But it seems clear that, while both actions are right, B’s action is more justified. The obvious explanation is that B’s action is performed for sufficient reasons, while A’s action is not. This, again, favours the DRTSUR view of justification over a mere conformity one.Footnote 34

A related advantage of the DRTSUR view is that it is able to provide an account of the variable liability to punishment, criticism, and blame of the subject in different situations.Footnote 35 In particular, the account explains the grades of liability of an unjustified agent. For example, it can account for why doing the right thing for the wrong reason makes a subject liable to criticism, but to a lesser degree than one who does the wrong thing for the wrong reason. Since the account distinguishes wrong from unjustified deeds, it allows for associating different liabilities to each condition. Furthermore, the view can admit different specific liabilities, criticisms, and appraisals (e.g., punishments, fees, duty to show regret and apologize, propriety of feeling guilty and repent, praise …) depending on the specific features making the action unjustified (lack of conformity, consequences, badness of the motives, or strength of the reasons on which the agent acted). The alternative view collapsing justification on conformity cannot provide an equally simple explanation of the variability of liabilities and assessments. The latter view seems forced to accept an implausible collapse of assessments. For example, it would deliver full exemption from liability for the unknowingly right actor in Attacker-Thought-To-Be-A-Jogger, which would conflict with both ordinary intuitive assessments and law courts’ judgements.

Argument 4: Gardner’s Argument

Gardner provides the following argument against the conformity view and for the DRTSUR view. Gardner observes that “it is quite pointless to cite, by way of justification, an undefeated reason for which one did not act, even though it would have been alright for one to act upon it if one had been minded to do so.”Footnote 36 Gardner also observes that citing such a reason would be insufficient to justify one’s action. One would have to provide some further reason on which one acted in order to clinch the justification. However, once one provides such further reason, any other reason for which one didn’t act becomes irrelevant for the justificatory status. This shows that acting for sufficient undefeated reasons is both necessary and sufficient to justify one’s action.

Two Possible Objections and Replies

One may argue that the notion of justification is ambiguous between two senses: on the one hand, there is act justification, which is an appraisal of the act or attitude and bears on the mere conformity to normative demands; on the other hand, there is personal justification, which is an appraisal of the agent and her virtuous conduct and concerns also the motives and reasons for which the agent acts. This distinction would reduce the contrast between the two considered views about justification to a terminological dispute. Upholders of the conformity view could then argue that the notion relevant for epistemic justification is that of act justification, concerning belief rather than the believer subject. My reply to this objection is that the contrast between personal and act justification may be useful in specific technical contexts, but it doesn’t correspond to any important real distinction. As a matter of fact, in our ordinary talk, we don’t distinguish between an agent being justified to φ and the agent’s φ-ing being justified. In particular, there are no circumstances whatsoever in which we attribute lack of justification to the agent but not to her action. If Paul is not justified in claiming a reward, then also Paul’s claiming the reward is unjustified.Footnote 37

Someone may suggest alternative versions of the present objection.Footnote 38 One may hold that ‘justification’ is ambiguous between two senses, but the ambiguity does not concern the distinction between act (attitude) and agent’s justification. Rather, it concerns some other notions of justification expressing different specific kinds of evaluation of an act or attitude. For example, it may be suggested that a certain act is justified* in virtue of displaying conformity to the norm, or avoiding bad consequences, but the same act is not justified** in virtue of manifesting bad will, lack of responsiveness to reasons, and so on. My response to this objection relies on the observation that, as it has been argued in literature discussed in this and the previous sections, justification is that type of defence that requires full defensibility from possible criticisms. An act or attitude φ is fully justified only when it can be fully defended from any rational objections.Footnote 39 As Gardner observed, only the unobjectionable is in no need of justification.Footnote 40 Undoubtedly, our actions and attitudes can be assessed according to several standards such as correctness, rationality, blameworthiness, safety, and so on. However, full justification is different from any such specific standard in the following respect: while an action can conform to specific standards and still be the object of criticism for failing to conform to others, an action that is fully justified is fully defensible from any kind of criticisms, unobjectionable under any normative respect. Thus, a justified action cannot fall short of conforming to any particular normative standard.Footnote 41

More plausible is the appeal to a distinction between the justification of a specific action and that of that type of action performed in relevantly similar circumstances. I think that this distinction tracks a real difference in our ordinary assessments of actions, attitudes, and agents. However, I don’t think it can be of any help for the upholder of the conformity view. The distinction is one between, on the one hand, the justification of an agent and her act in a particular circumstance, given the reasons for which she actually acted, and on the other hand, the justification of an action and a rational agent performing it in relevantly similar idealized circumstances. While a particular action φ could be unjustified if not performed for sufficient reasons, φ-ing would indeed be justified provided that a rational agent in similar circumstances φ-ed for sufficient reasons. So, for example, when we say that the use of force is justified when one is under serious threat, we mean that an agent’s using the force for defending herself from a serious threat would be justified. This is compatible with some agent’s use of force not being justified in similar circumstances, as in the Attacker-Thought-To-Be-A-Jogger case. In this respect, justification assessments when attributed to an act-type seem clearly derivative from justification assessments applied to particular actions. Obviously, this distinction doesn’t constitute any real threat for the DRTSUR view since, in both type and token assessments, justification depends on both doing the right thing and doing it for sufficient reasons.Footnote 42

It is also worth stressing that justification attributions to act-types are less common than to particular acts. While we say that the driver’s stopping at the red lights was justified, we usually don’t say that to stop at the red lights, qua type of act, is justified. More precisely, while it is appropriate to attribute permissibility and rightness to a type of action in abstraction from the reasons for performing it, it sounds odd to attribute justification to an action viewed without any connection to the agent’s reasons for performing that action. A simple explanation is that justification depends on the reasons for which an action or attitude is performed, and when assessing an act-type sounds particularly odd, this is because it is left indeterminate whether that act-type is conceived as performed for sufficient reasons. In the rare cases in which we attribute justification to a type of action, we tend to conceive that action as performed by a rational agent who would perform the action for sufficient reasons.Footnote 43

3. Justification, Norm Conformity, and the Knowledge Norm

In §2, I argued that justification requires more than norm conformity. This conclusion blocks a familiar line of argument for the knowledge norm briefly sketched in the introduction. We can reconstruct the argument as follows:

  1. 1) A belief is justified if and only if it is fully defensible from rational criticisms (assumption)

  2. 2) Knowledge is necessary and sufficient to make a belief fully defensible (assumption)

  3. 3) Knowledge is necessary and sufficient to justify a belief (from 1 and 2)

  4. 4) For any subject S and action or attitude φ, it is justified for S to φ if and only if S conforms to the relevant norm governing φ-ing (assumption)

  5. C) S’s belief that p conforms to the norm of belief if and only if S knows p (from 3 and 4)

Let’s assume, for the sake of argument, that premises 1 and 2 are true. We have already discussed motivations for premise 1 in §2. The main motivation for premise 2 adduced by upholders of the knowledge-based model is that, on the one hand, any epistemic condition falling short of knowledge is somewhat defective and open to criticisms, and on the other hand, nothing more than knowledge seems to be required for a belief being fully defensible (at least from an epistemic perspective).Footnote 44 Let’s also grant that 3 follows from 1 and 2. My objection to the argument concerns 4. Alleged support for this premise would come from parallels with the use of the notion of justification in other normative disciplines. However, as argued in §2, such parallels indicate that conformity to the relevant norms governing an action or attitude is not sufficient to justify that action or attitude. Something more than that is needed, such as conforming for sufficient undefeated reasons. We should thus substitute 4 with the weaker 4*:

  1. 4*) For any subject S and action or attitude φ, it is justified for S to φ only if S conforms to the relevant norm governing φ-ing (assumption)

From 4* and the other premises, we can conclude that knowledge is a sufficient condition to conform to the norm of belief, but not a necessary one. This conclusion is compatible with the norm of belief being some condition weaker than knowledge. The above argument for the knowledge norm of belief fails.

Furthermore, a similar line of argument turns out to support a norm of belief requiring a condition weaker than knowledge. In §2, I have argued that justified φ-ing requires more than mere conformity to the relevant norm governing φ-ing—it requires conformity for sufficient undefeated reasons.Footnote 45 If so, mere conformity to the norm requires a condition weaker than justification: the condition for justification implies the condition for norm conformity, but not vice versa. Accordingly, we should expect that the condition required by the norm of belief would be weaker than the one necessary and sufficient for epistemic justification. A belief can conform to this norm without being justified. If we keep the claim that knowledge is necessary and sufficient to justify a belief (3, derived from 1 and 2 in the previous argument), we reach the conclusion that the norm of belief requires some condition weaker than knowledge, such as truth. The argument can be reconstructed as follows:

  1. 3) Knowledge is necessary and sufficient to justify a belief (from 1 and 2)

  2. 4+) For any action or attitude φ, condition C required for conformity to the relevant norm governing φ-ing is weaker than condition J required for justified φ-ing (J implies C but not vice versa) (assumption)

  3. 5) The condition required by the norm of belief is weaker than the condition required for justified belief (from 4+, instantiation)

  4. C+) The norm of belief requires a condition weaker than knowledge (from 3 and 5)

4. Toward a Truth-Based Model of Epistemic Normativity

Until now, I have argued that it is wrong to identify justification with mere norm conformity, as upholders of the knowledge-based model do. I have also shown that this conclusion is problematic for a familiar line of argument supposed to support the knowledge norm, and that it rather lends support to a norm of belief requiring a condition weaker than knowledge, such as truth. In this section, I consider an alternative model of epistemic normativity, which develops within the general externalist normative framework introduced in §1, but which assumes a truth norm of belief. A truth norm requires that one believe what is true, or only what is true.Footnote 46 The aim is not to provide a full defence for this truth-based model. My more modest goal is to illustrate how an alternative model of epistemic normativity can be built within this framework, compatible with some central assumptions of knowledge-based models and preserving their externalist core and many of their insights and advantages, but leading to different conclusions about a number of epistemic properties.

The interesting aspect of a truth-based model is that this model doesn’t lead to a collapse of the conditions for several normative properties on a unique condition, as the knowledge-based model does. In particular, within this model, it is possible to distinguish between, on the one hand, the condition for norm conformity (truth) and, on the other hand, the condition for conforming for sufficient undefeated reasons, full defensibility and epistemic justification (knowledge). The truth-based model can leave open the possibility of conforming to the truth norm without doing it for sufficient reasons. An example is when a subject believes some true proposition p but her belief isn’t based on sufficient evidence. In this case, the belief that p is permissible but not fully defensible, and thus not justified.

If we take seriously the idea that epistemic reasons are all and only the reasons that the norm of belief provides, the adoption of truth as the norm of belief leads to a form of reason infallibilism.Footnote 47 If, for example, the norm requires believing only the truth, it provides sufficient (undefeated) reasons to believe a proposition p only if p is true. It is impossible that S believes p on the basis of sufficient reasons R, and yet S’s belief that p is not true. If the belief had been false, there would have not been sufficient reasons to believe it—in exactly the same way in which if someone thinks that she made a promise but she didn’t, there would be no reasons to do what she believes she has promised (at least none issued by a promise-keeping norm). Thus, according to the truth-based model, the only reasons (not) to believe p are the truth (falsity) of p or any truth q guaranteeing the truth of p.Footnote 48

A consequence of the adoption of such a truth-based model concerns justification. It is plausible that, within this framework, if a subject S believes a proposition p for sufficient undefeated reasons, she also knows p. This is because, as I said above, if there are sufficient undefeated reasons to believe p, these reasons guarantee the truth of p, and if S believes p on the basis of these reasons, then she also knows p. If this is true, then within this model we can maintain, with upholders of the knowledge-based model, that a belief that p is fully defensible and justified only if the subject knows p. This allows for preserving a neat distinction between assessments in ‘good cases,’ in which the subject knows and is justified, and ‘bad cases,’ in which the subject’s belief falls short of knowledge and is not justified—at most, it can be blameless and excusable if it is held reasonably. However, the truth-based model admits a richer spectrum of assessments compared to the knowledge-based one: assessments of permissibility, rightness, and correctness are associated with norm conformity (viz., true beliefs or the absence of false beliefs), assessments of excusability are associated with rational beliefs falling short of knowledge, and assessments of full defensibility and justification are associated with beliefs that conform to the norm for sufficient undefeated reasons, which in the picture I’ve just sketched amount to knowledge.Footnote 49

The present model has the resources to address a popular line of argument against the truth norm of belief. Roughly, according to this argument, only a knowledge norm can account for both objective and subjective, outward and inward looking assessments of belief and explain why a belief that falls short of knowledge is epistemically defective.Footnote 50 This argument presupposes that (i) nothing less than knowledge can grant a belief’s full defensibility from epistemic criticisms and (ii) that norm conformity is sufficient to grant full defensibility. From these assumptions, the argument concludes that no epistemic condition weaker than knowledge can be the norm of belief. As argued in §2, premise (ii) is false: full defensibility, as justification, requires more than norm conformity. We can thus maintain that the norm of belief is some weaker condition than knowledge, such as truth, while also maintaining that only knowledge can grant full epistemic defensibility and justification.

Before concluding, I would like to stress that the truth-based model of epistemic normativity sketched in this section doesn’t differ only from the knowledge-based model, but also from traditional models identifying the norm of belief with truth.Footnote 51 As a matter of fact, the respects under which the present model differs from other traditional truth-based ones are much more significant than the differences between this model and the knowledge-based one. I will mention here only what I take to be the most striking dissimilarities. Traditional truth-based views often do not distinguish between justification and rationality, and systematically take these properties as compatible with beliefs falling short of norm conformity. In contrast, in the present truth-based model justification and rationality are radically different assessments playing distinct roles in our evaluative practices: while rationality concerns the responsiveness of the subject to apparent reasons (what look like reasons from the subject’s perspective)Footnote 52 and is compatible with the existence of rational beliefs that do not conform to the norm of the attitude, a justified belief requires full defensibility and conformity to the norm for sufficient undefeated reasons. A related difference is that the present truth-based model, like the knowledge-based one, preserves a disjunctive account of epistemic assessments in good cases (in which the subject knows and is justified) and bad cases (in which a belief falls short of knowledge, is not justified, and can at most be excused). On the contrary, traditional views do not distinguish between justification and excuses and admit identical normative assessments in good and bad cases.

In the present section, I have provided a rough and incomplete picture of what a general model of epistemic normativity would look like if we adopt the general externalist framework considered in §1 and take truth to be the norm of belief. Many arguments deployed for a knowledge-based model can be used to support the present model. In particular, parallels with the use of corresponding normative notions in other normative disciplines provide a strong case for this model. No doubt the present account is very sketchy and imprecise in several respects, and several problems not considered in this paper need to be addressed. My aim in this section was just to illustrate a possible alternative to the knowledge-based model of epistemic normativity, based on the same externalist normative framework and enjoying most of the same virtues, but preserving a difference between conditions for justification and for norm conformity. Investigating further the merits and shortcomings of this model is a task for future occasions.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Jie Gao, Daniel Whiting, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the SOPHA conference 2015 in Montreal, the Epistemological Club at the Collège de France in Paris (2016), and the 2016 GRE Conference ‘Certitude et infallibilité.’ Thanks to the audiences for their helpful feedback. Research for this article has been partially funded by the Swiss National Science Foundation research project ‘The Unity of Reasons’ (P300P1-164569).

Footnotes

2 Littlejohn forthcoming; Williamson forthcoming. For an overview, see Dutant and Dorsch forthcoming.

3 Littlejohn Reference Littlejohn2013; Williamson forthcoming. For an insightful discussion of this approach, see also Sylvan manuscript.

4 The analogy between the epistemic domain and other normative domains may be incomplete. As an anonymous reviewer has observed, certain normative notions in epistemology might not completely correspond to ones used by jurists and philosophers of law. An important difference may concern, for example, the notion of truth deployed in the respective domains. While it is worth recognizing potential disanalogies, I do not think that these can substantially compromise structural parallels between the corresponding notions to such an extent that they could invalidate the present methodology.

5 Williamson uses as an example the debate surrounding the notion of epistemic justification: “‘Epistemic justification’ is manifestly technical terminology: we should be correspondingly suspicious of claims to make pre-theoretic judgments about its application. Moreover, we might then query the interest of the Gettier problem, if it merely shows that one cooked-up sense of ‘justified’ does not serve the purpose for which it was cooked up. Although merely pragmatic justification does not seem to be at issue in standard Gettier cases, ‘epistemic justification’ itself can be understood in a variety of ways” (forthcoming, 3). See also Alston Reference Alston2005 for an overview of the variety of ways in which epistemologists use the notion of justification.

6 Another motivation for focusing on Littlejohn’s framework is that the normative framework discussed by Williamson in his most recent article on the topic (forthcoming), involves a number of complexities that are irrelevant for the present discussion.

7 The present notion of norm is ‘wide’ in the sense that it doesn’t include only obligations but also permissions and prohibitions. However, in another sense, this notion is narrow to the extent that it does not obviously include items sometimes classified as ‘norms,’ such as metarules and certain kinds of constitutive rules. For a discussion of different notions of constitutive rules, see, e.g., Glüer and Pagin Reference Glüer and Pagin1999; Lewis Reference Lewis1983; Midgley Reference Midgley1958; Searle Reference Searle1969; Zelaniec Reference Zelaniec2013.

8 See Railton Reference Railton and Shafer-Landau2006 for a discussion of different forms of normative guidance. Thanks to Daniel Whiting for encouraging me to clarify this important point.

9 This example is from Williamson (forthcoming, 5-6). A terminological note: Williamson uses the word ‘compliance’ to designate what here, following standard terminology, I call ‘conformity.’ Littlejohn subscribes to the compliance/conformity distinction (2013, 303-306) and advances several arguments for the claim that norms and reasons demand nothing more than conformity, some drawn from Ross Reference Ross2002 and Thomson Reference Thomson1991. See also Moore Reference Moore2005; Graham Reference Graham2010; Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 98-99. See Hurka Reference Hurka2011, §3.3, 79-80 for a discussion of early arguments in favour of objective moral duties. For an earlier discussion of the distinction between norm compliance and conformity, see Raz Reference Raz1975.

10 Alvarez Reference Alvarez2010; Dancy Reference Dancy2000; Littlejohn, Reference Littlejohn2012, Reference Littlejohn, McHugh, Way and Whiting2018; Parfit Reference Parfit2011; Raz Reference Raz1999; Scanlon Reference Scanlon1998, Reference Scanlon2014; Skorupski Reference Skorupski2010. While Williamson avoids talk of reasons and focuses on other normative notions, Littlejohn discusses reasons at great length in his works. See, e.g., 2012, 2018, forthcoming.

11 Littlejohn Reference Littlejohn, McHugh, Way and Whiting2018; McDowell Reference McDowell1978. Littlejohn, following Alvarez, also distinguishes motivating reasons from explanatory reasons. While all motivating reasons are also explanatory, not all explanatory reasons are motivating. Sometimes what explains why we φ is not necessarily what motivated us to φ. Nothing in what follows will hinge on this further assumption.

12 E.g., Botterell Reference Botterell2009, 180; Duff Reference Duff2004; Gardner Reference Gardner2007; Littlejohn forthcoming; Strawson Reference Strawson1962; Williamson forthcoming, 10-11. On this point, these philosophers differ from others endorsing perspectivalist accounts of justification, such as Sylvan (manuscript), according to which only possessed normative reasons are relevant for justification. See also Baron Reference Baron2005 for a perspectivalist account of justification in the legal domain.

13 Littlejohn forthcoming, 21.

14 Littlejohn forthcoming, 16.

15 See also Simion, Kelp, and Ghijsen Reference Simion, Kelp and Ghijsen2016. Williamson (forthcoming, 11) assumes that primary norms determine derivative norms governing agents’ dispositions to comply with these norms. He identifies justification with conformity to the relevant primary norm. In the present framework, this is equivalent to Littlejohn’s view.

16 Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 94. Gardner also writes: “To cite explanatory reasons as well as guiding reasons is not to provide justifications from two different points of view, nor even to provide two partial justifications, but merely to provide the two essential parts of one and the same (partial or complete) justification” (2007, 94).

17 For an example of the former view, see Robinson Reference Robinson, Smith and Simester1996. Many share the latter view. See, for example, Finkelstein Reference Finkelstein1996; Fletcher Reference Fletcher1975, Reference Fletcher1978, Ch. 10; LaFave and Scott Reference LaFave and Scott1986, 685; J.C. Smith and Hogan Reference Smith and Hogan2011; Sullivan Reference Sullivan1990.

18 For similar accounts of excuses, see Austin Reference Austin1956; Baron Reference Baron2005, 389-390; Duff Reference Duff2007; Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 86; Littlejohn forthcoming; Strawson Reference Strawson1962; Williamson forthcoming. Some philosophers include amongst excuses also defences in certain cases in which an action is performed under duress.

19 Many philosophers also distinguish excuses from lack of responsibility (e.g., Duff Reference Duff2007; Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 86; Littlejohn forthcoming). Excuses are tightly related with the agent’s rational capacities to appropriately respond to apparent reasons. This involves showing sufficient concern and possessing competencies necessary to be guided by reasons in normal circumstances, and presupposes that excusable agents can be held accountable for their actions. On the contrary, when the subject’s rational capacities necessary to properly respond to reasons are either lacking or compromised, she is beyond excuse. A subject is blameless when justified or fully excusable, but also when she is not responsible and accountable for her actions.

20 Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 94.

21 R v. Dadson (1850) 4 Cox CC 358. See also North Dakota v. Leidholm, 334 N.W.2d 811 (N.D. 1983): “[A] person who believes that the force he uses is necessary to prevent imminent unlawful harm is justified in using such force if his belief is a correct belief; that is to say, if his belief corresponds with what actually is the case.” Id. at 815 (emphasis added).

22 Robinson Reference Robinson, Smith and Simester1996, 67. While Robinson recognizes that the ‘dual requirement’ view better fits current law courts’ decisions, he rejects this view on the ground that it is functionally inferior to a view identifying justification with mere law conformity. Robinson’s conclusion relies on the idea that justification should have only the function of flagging the rightness of the deed. There is room for disagreement with Robinson’s conclusion: the proper role of our ordinary notion of justification is not merely flagging whether an action is right or wrong, but whether it is fully defensible. Unfortunately, I cannot here engage in a full discussion of Robinson’s arguments.

23 Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 78, 95. See also Duff Reference Duff2007 for similar claims.

24 Littlejohn Reference Littlejohn2012, 192-193.

26 One can easily find similar examples in the literature in ethics and philosophy of law. According to Duff (2004, 848-850), a subject who is permitted to use violence because under a serious threat will not be justified if she does that for revenge, without knowing herself to be under a serious threat. For similar considerations, see also Worsnip Reference Worsnip2016, 349: “it seems to me that talk of ‘ethical justification’ is not happily independent of the agent’s cognitive position or perspective either. Suppose that someone performs the objectively right action entirely by accident; really, they were trying to do something quite dastardly. It’s pretty unnatural to describe their act as justified.”

27 This example is from Williamson forthcoming. From this example, Williamson concludes that there are secondary obligations whose violation involves blame and something to excuse in one’s action. I agree with Williamson’s diagnosis, except that I find problematic the identification of secondary assessments with obligations, even if fully derivative and instrumental ones. For problems with derivative obligations, see, for example, Broome Reference Broome2013, Ch. 3; Dancy Reference Dancy and Robertson2009, 99-100; Hawthorne and Srinivasan Reference Hawthorne, Srinivasan, Christensen and Lackey2013, §6; Gardner Reference Gardner2007; Glüer and Wikforss Reference Glüer and Wikforss2009, 44-45; Kolodny Reference Kolodny2007; Littlejohn Reference Littlejohn2013, §3; Lord Reference Lord and Schafer-Landau2015, §2.3; Parfit Reference Parfit2011; Williamson Reference Williamson2000, 192 and 223; Williamson Reference Williamson and Smith2008. Williamson himself recognizes the limits of framing the distinction in terms of primary and derivative norms when he denies that these norms have equal status: “Typically, any normative significance that [the derivative norm] possesses is merely derivative from that of [the primary norm].” He adds that “[t]he point can be put in terms of the distinction between justifications and excuses” (Williamson forthcoming, 10). The same author frames the distinction in terms of justification and excuses in other works.

28 Duff (Reference Duff2007) also stresses that while excuses exclude justification, they don’t exclude absence of wrongdoing. This implies that also in absence of wrongdoing the subject may not be fully defensible and justified.

30 Commenting on a similar case, Duff observes that “[i]t might seem no less absurd to convict [Paul] of attempted criminal mischief …. For that would imply that there was some criminal act that she tried but failed to perform, which is obviously not the case” (2004, 845). It is worth observing that the claim that we cannot separate intentions from actions is familiar in the philosophical literature at least since early works on moral luck. See, e.g., Williams Reference Williams1981.

31 Consider another reason to avoid an appeal to secondary norms sanctioning attempts and intentions to comply with norms. If to every norm we associate derivative norms governing the agent’s intentions and attempts to follow it, we end up with third-order norms governing intentions and attempts to follow secondary norms, fourth-order norms governing intentions and attempts to follow third-order norms, and so on ad infinitum. This view is ontologically unparsimonious and leads to familiar regress problems with rule following.

32 On comparability of epistemic justification, see, for example, Bird Reference Bird2007; McGlynn Reference McGlynn2014; M. Smith Reference Smith2016, §5.1.

33 Hansson Reference Hansson2001, Ch. 10; Mulligan Reference Mulligan1998, 162; Ogien and Tappolet Reference Ogien and Tappolet2009, 60-66.

34 A reviewer for this journal considers a specific way in which a knowledge-based account of justification could be gradable. Suppose that one should believe only what is known. Then facts that make likely that a certain proposition p is known (or would be known if believed) would be reasons to believe p. If this is right, then one can explain the different degree of justification with the different probabilistic support provided by these facts. The problem with this explanation is that in a knowledge-based framework facts that make likely a proposition do not count in themselves as reasons to believe it. A fact could make likely that p is (or would be) known even though p isn’t an instance of knowledge (for instance because p is false). Since the knowledge norm requires believing only what is known, it provides reasons to believe p only if p is (or would be) known. In this framework, there are no reasons to believe a proposition that falls short of being knowledge, and this no matter how facts make likely that that proposition is known. More in general, mere probabilistic support is a fallible kind of support, but if the norm of belief is factive (truth, knowledge …), reasons to believe must be infallible considerations. I will come back to this point in §4 when I will discuss a truth-based model of epistemic normativity. Notice also that, as philosophers quoted in fn 32 recognize, if conformity to the knowledge norm of belief were gradable, such degrees would reflect better or worse ways of knowing, not different degrees of evidential support. However, the claim that knowledge is a gradable condition is highly contentious.

36 Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 102.

37 In a similar vein, Dancy writes: “I reject this contrast as misconceived, since I do not think that we can make sense of there being two requirements, one on the act (get yourself done), and one on the agent (do this thing)” (Dancy Reference Dancy2000: 53). For criticisms of the present distinction in the practical and legal domains, see, for example, Baron Reference Baron1995, Reference Baron2005; Stocker Reference Stocker1973. This is also the mainstream view in epistemology. The standard view holds that personal and doxastic justification ascriptions are logically equivalent. See Alston Reference Alston1989; Kvanvig and Menzel Reference Kvanvig and Menzel1990. Littlejohn hinted at a similar distinction for epistemic justification in earlier works (2012, 7-8). However, his more recent endorsement of a knowledge norm of belief doesn’t square well with the distinction. As it has been noticed, a knowledge norm tends to collapse the categories of propositional, doxastic, and personal justification: if a belief is propositionally justified, it amounts to knowledge; but knowledge that p implies also doxastic and personal justification in believing that p.

38 I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing to my attention this possible reply.

40 Gardner Reference Gardner2007, 78, 95.

41 One may object here that the phrase ‘fully defensible’ is also ambiguous between a sense concerning specific standards (e.g., ‘fully defensible’ with respect to the conformity of the act to the norm, ‘fully defensible’ with respect to the intention of the agent, and so on). Notice, however, that this is not how ‘fully defensible’ is used in the present literature. When philosophers in the present debate talk of a fully defensible act (attitude, omission …), they just mean an act that cannot be challenged as inappropriate under any normative respect. Since defensibility under a specific respect allows criticizability along some other respects, this kind of defensibility is different from the relevant notion of ‘full defensibility’ used in the literature. If one doesn’t like the phrase ‘fully defensible,’ one is free to substitute it with a different phrase, e.g., ‘that cannot be challenged as inappropriate under any normative respect.’ The point doesn’t change: full justification requires that a φ cannot be challenged under any normative respect. But meeting a particular standard is not sufficient to avoid being challenged under any normative respect. So, conformity to particular standards is not sufficient for full justification.

42 A further distinction is that between ex-ante and ex-post justification, i.e., between what an agent is justified in doing and what she justifiably does. There are various ways of cashing out this distinction. For example, we can conceive ex-ante justification as the justification an agent would have if she φ-ed on the basis of the sufficient reasons she has. Importantly, this distinction is completely orthogonal to the debate between those who take justification as a matter of mere conformity to norms and those who think that justification requires conformity for sufficient undefeated reasons. From S’s ex-ante justification to φ, nothing follows about whether S φ-s in conformity to norms. Both these views are concerned with ex-post justification. Thanks to Daniel Whiting for bringing this potential worry to my attention.

43 The different applications of the words ‘justified’ and ‘right’ in ordinary language provide a further clue that the two properties are not coextensive, and thus that justification doesn’t supervene on mere norm conformity.

44 Littlejohn Reference Littlejohn2013, §VII; Williamson forthcoming, 2005b.

45 This premise presupposes that it is possible to conform to a norm without doing it for sufficient undefeated reasons. See Hawthorne and Srinivasan Reference Hawthorne, Srinivasan, Christensen and Lackey2013 for an argument that this is possible for every norm.

46 For reasons of space, I will not be concerned here with the specific formulation of the norm and I will not discuss specific advantages and problems of the adoption of a similar norm. For an overview and references, see McHugh and Whiting Reference McHugh and Whiting2014 and Fassio Reference Fassio2015.

47 As would a knowledge-based model. See Littlejohn Reference Littlejohn, Reisner and Steglich-Petersen2011, 127, 2017, 2018.

48 This feature of the view perfectly fits with infallibilist accounts of knowledge, such as those defended by upholders of the knowledge-based model. A similar view has been defended by Schnee Reference Schnee2016 for basic perceptual reasons to believe. Schnee’s defences of this view from specific criticisms can be applied more broadly to address problems in the present more general model. Let me also stress that a reason can guarantee the truth of a proposition without necessarily entailing its truth. The support of epistemic reasons can be contingently infallible. Thanks to Julien Dutant for bringing this important detail to my attention.

49 These conclusions follow from an account of epistemic reasons, according to which believing for sufficient undefeated reasons entails knowing. However, in the face of potential counterexamples familiar from the post-Gettier literature (e.g., fake barn cases; see Whiting Reference Whiting2015), one may prefer accounts where this entailment does not hold. These accounts would allow for justified beliefs falling short of knowledge in the problematic cases. While these cases are contentious, I am open to revising the present account, as the reader thinks more appropriate. My personal view is that a specific ‘externalist’ understanding of the notion of defeat can accommodate the problematic cases. An analogy with the legal domain can illustrate the point: I think there is a sense of ‘sufficient undefeated reason’ according to which a subject complying with a law due to environmental luck doesn’t count as conforming to the law for undefeated reasons.

50 Versions of this argument are in Littlejohn Reference Littlejohn2013; Williamson forthcoming, 2005b. For further discussion and criticism of this argument, see Fassio forthcoming.

51 Here I have in mind in particular the model developed by Wedgwood Reference Wedgwood2002, Reference Wedgwood2013. Other philosophers defend a truth norm of belief (e.g., Boghossian Reference Boghossian2003; Engel Reference Engel and Gillies2004, Reference Engel2013; Millar Reference Millar2004; Shah Reference Shah2003; Shah and Velleman Reference Shah and Velleman2005; Whiting Reference Whiting2010), but they do not provide equally detailed accounts of how the norm relates to other normative notions, such as justification and rationality.

52 See, for example, Whiting Reference Whiting2014 and Sylvan (manuscript) for accounts of apparent reasons along these lines.

References

Alston, W. 1989 Epistemic Justification. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alston, W. 2005 Beyond Justification: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alvarez, M. 2010 Kinds of Reasons: An Essay in the Philosophy of Action. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J.L. 1956A Plea for Excuses.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57 : 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, M. 1995 Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Baron, M. 2005Justifications and excuses.” Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 2 (2): 387406.Google Scholar
Bird, A. 2007Justified Judging.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (1): 81110.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P.A. 2003The Normativity of Content.” Philosophical Issues 13 (1): 3145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Botterell, A. 2009A Primer on the Distinction between Justification and Excuse.” Philosophy Compass 4 (1): 172196.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2013 Rationality Through Reasoning. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2000 Practical Reality . Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2009 “Reasons and Rationality,” in Spheres of Reason, edited by Robertson, S. Oxford University Press, pp. 93112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duff, R.A. 2004Rethinking Justifications.” Tulsa Law Review 39 (4): 829850.Google Scholar
Duff, R.A. 2007Excuses, Moral and Legal: A Comment on Marcia Baron’s ‘Excuses, Excuses.’” Criminal Law and Philosophy 1 (1): 4955.Google Scholar
Dutant, J., and Dorsch, F. Forthcoming “Introduction,” in The New Evil Demon, edited by Dutant, J. and Dorsch, F. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Engel, P. 2004 “Truth and the Aim of Belief,” in Laws and Models in Science, edited by Gillies, D. King’s College Publications, pp. 7797.Google Scholar
Engel, P. 2013Doxastic Correctness.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87 (1): 199216.Google Scholar
Fassio, D. 2015The Aim of Belief,” in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved December 1, 2018, from https://www.iep.utm.edu/beli-aim/.Google Scholar
Fassio, D. Forthcoming “On the Generality Argument for the Knowledge Norm.” Synthese.Google Scholar
Finkelstein, C. 1996Self-Defense as a Rational Excuse.” Faculty Scholarship. Paper 1255: 621649.Google Scholar
Fletcher, G. 1975The Right Deed for the Wrong Reason: A Reply to Mr. Robinson.” UCLA Law Review 23 (2): 293321.Google Scholar
Fletcher, G. 1978 Rethinking Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2007 Offences and Defences: Selected Essays in the Philosophy of Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Glüer, K., and Pagin, P. 1999Rules of Meaning and Practical Reasoning.” Synthese 117 (2): 207227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glüer, K., and Wikforss, Å. 2009Against Content Normativity.” Mind 118 (469): 3170.Google Scholar
Graham, P.A. 2010In Defense of Objectivism about Moral Obligation.” Ethics 121 (1): 88115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansson, S.O. 2001 The Structure of Values and Norms. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J., and Srinivasan, A. 2013Disagreement Without Transparency: Some Bleak Thoughts,” in The Epistemology of Disagreement: New Essays, edited by Christensen, D. and Lackey, J. Oxford University Press, pp. 930.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. 2011 Underivative Duty: British Moral Philosophers from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolodny, N. 2007How Does Coherence Matter?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107 (1): 229263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, J., and Menzel, C. 1990The Basic Notion of Justification.” Philosophical Studies 59 (3): 235261.Google Scholar
LaFave, W., and Scott, A. 1986 Substantive Criminal Law. West Group.Google Scholar
Lewis, D.K. 1983 Philosophical Papers. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. 2011 “Reasons and Belief’s Justification,” in Reasons for Belief, edited by Reisner, A. and Steglich-Petersen, A. Cambridge University Press, pp. 111130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littlejohn, C. 2012 Justification and the Truth-Connection. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littlejohn, C. 2013The Russellian Retreat.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113 (3): 293320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littlejohn, C. 2014The Unity of Reason,” in Epistemic Norms: New Essays on Action, Belief, and Assertion, edited by Littlejohn, C. and Turri, J. Oxford University Press, pp. 135154.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. 2017How and Why Knowledge is First,” in Knowledge First, edited by Carter, A., Gordon, E., and Jarvis, B. Oxford University Press, pp. 1945.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. 2018Evidence and Its Limits,” in Normativity: Epistemic and Practical, edited by McHugh, C., Way, J., and Whiting, D. Oxford University Press, pp. 115136.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. Forthcoming “A Plea for Epistemic Excuses,” in The New Evil Demon Problem, edited by Dutant, J. and Dorsch, F. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lord, E. 2015Acting for the Right Reasons, Abilities, and Obligation,” in Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Volume 10), edited by Schafer-Landau, R. Oxford University Press, pp. 2652.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1978Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 52 (1): 1329.Google Scholar
McGlynn, A. 2014 Knowledge First? Palgrave Macmillian.Google Scholar
McHugh, C., and Whiting, D. 2014The Normativity of Belief.” Analysis 74 (4): 698713.Google Scholar
Midgley, G.C.J. 1958Linguistic Rules.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 59: 271290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millar, A. 2004 Understanding People: Normativity and Rationalizing Explanation. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G.E. 2005 Ethics: The Nature of Moral Philosophy. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulligan, K. 1998From Appropriate Emotions to Values.” The Monist 81 (1): 161188.Google Scholar
Ogien, R., and Tappolet, C. 2009 Les concepts de l’éthique. Hermann.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2011 On What Matters (Volume 1). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2006Normative Guidance,” in Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Volume 1), edited by Shafer-Landau, R. Oxford University Press, pp. 334.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1975 Practical Reason and Norms. Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1999 Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, P. 1996Competing Theories of Justification: Deeds vs. Reasons,” in Harm and Culpability, edited by Smith, A. and Simester, A. Oxford University Press, pp. 4570.Google Scholar
Ross, W.D. 2002 The Right and the Good. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T.M. 1998 What We Owe to Each Other. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T.M. 2014 Being Realistic About Reasons. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schnee, I. 2016Basic Factive Perceptual Reasons.” Philosophical Studies 173 (4): 11031118.Google Scholar
Searle, J.R. 1969 Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N. 2003How Truth Governs Belief.” Philosophical Review 112 (4): 447482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N., and Velleman, J.D. 2005Doxastic Deliberation.” Philosophical Review 114 (4): 497534.Google Scholar
Simion, M., Kelp, C., and Ghijsen, H. 2016Norms of Belief.” Philosophical Issues 26 (1): 374392.Google Scholar
Skorupski, J. 2010 The Domain of Reasons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, J.C., and Hogan, B. 2011 Criminal Law (13th edition). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 2016 Between Probability and Certainty. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stocker, M. 1973Act and Agent Evaluations.” Review of Metaphysics 27 (1): 4261.Google Scholar
Strawson, P.F. 1962Freedom and Resentment.” Proceedings of the British Academy 48: 125.Google Scholar
Sullivan, G.R. 1990Bad Thoughts and Bad Acts.” Criminal Law Review 559561.Google Scholar
Sutton, J. 2007 Without Justification. Mit Press.Google Scholar
Sylvan, K. n.d. Rationality and Justification: Reasons to Divorce? Retrieved December 1, 2018, from http://www.kurtlsylvan.com/uploads/3/5/4/0/3540497/rationalityandjustification_reasonstodivorce.pdf.Google Scholar
Thomson, J.J. 1991Self-Defense.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (4): 283310.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2002The Aim of Belief.” Philosophical Perspectives 16 (1): 267297.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2013Doxastic Correctness.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87 (1): 217234.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. 2010Should I Believe the Truth?Dialectica 64 (2): 213224.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. 2014Keep Things in Perspective: Reasons, Rationality, and the A Priori.” Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy 8 (1): 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, D. 2015Knowledge Is NOT Belief for Sufficient (Objective and Subjective) Reason.” Logos and Episteme 6 (2): 237243.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1981 “Internal and External Reasons,” in Moral Luck. Cambridge University Press, pp. 101113.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000 Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2005aContextualism, Subject-Sensitive Invariantism and Knowledge of Knowledge.” Philosophical Quarterly 55 (219): 213235.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2005b “Knowledge, Context, and the Agent’s Point of View,” in Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning, and Truth, edited by Preyer, G. and Peter, G. Oxford University Press, pp. 91114.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2008 “Why Epistemology Cannot be Operationalized,” in Epistemology: New Essays, edited by Smith, Q. Oxford University Press, pp. 277300.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. Forthcoming “Justifications, Excuses, and Sceptical Scenarios,” in The New Evil Demon, edited by Dutant, J. and Dorsch, F.D. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Worsnip, A. 2016Moral Reasons, Epistemic Reasons, and Rationality.” Philosophical Quarterly, 66 (263): 341361.Google Scholar
Zelaniec, W. 2013 “Create to Rule. Essays on Constitutive Rules.” LED Edizioni Universitarie di Lettere Economia Diritto.Google Scholar