Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T06:33:23.248Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rational Choice and Its Limits

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

This Article asks the fundamental question of whether the concept of a market-oriented (economic) order can be reconciled with the idea of democracy from the perspective of rational choice approaches to the law. Europe has been facing great economic challenges for the past years—sovereign debt; fiscal and monetary policy; financial market regulation; trade and investment agreements. Some observers argue that prioritizing an economic rationale in the policy response to these challenges comes at the expense of democracy by undermining its most vital preconditions (such as equality and solidarity), while their antagonists state that in fact democratic decision-making is undermining financial stability and long-term welfare of societies. This Article will establish that both positions contribute important insights and yet display too narrow a field of vision. Combining the arguments puts the cart before the horse: Democratic decision-making undermines, among other things, financial stability—and thus long-term welfare of societies—because it follows a logic that is primarily economic.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2016 by German Law Journal, Inc. 

References

1 In some sense, this can be understood as a variant of the question whether a market economy is helpful (if not a precondition) for a democratic order; for a recent example of such an argument see Carl Christian von Weizsäcker, Die normative Ko-Evolution von Marktwirtschaft und Demokratie, 65 Ordo 13 (2014).Google Scholar

2 See Towfigh, Emanuel & Petersen, Niels, Economic Methods for Lawyers 1831 (2015).Google Scholar

3 See generally Downs, Anthony, An Economic Theory of Democracy (1957).Google Scholar

4 See generally Samuel Issacharoff et al., The Law of Democracy: Legal Structure of the Political Process (4th ed. 2012).Google Scholar

5 Towfigh, Emanuel V., Das Parteien-Paradox: Ein Beitrag zur Bestimmung des Verhältnisses von Demokratie und Parteien 55 et seq. (2015).Google Scholar

6 See generally Samuel Issacharoff & Pildes, Richard H., Politics as Markets: Partisan Lockups of the Democratic Process, 50 Stan. L. Rev. 643 (1998).Google Scholar

7 See Ortiz, Daniel R., Duopoly Versus Autonomy: How the Two-Party System Harms the Major Parties, 100 Colum. L. Rev. 753, 754 (2000) (“[W]e might well view voters in modern mass democracy more as political consumers than as political principals.”).Google Scholar

8 See generally Levinson, Daryl J., Market Failures and Failures of Markets, 85 Va. L. Rev. 1745 (1999).Google Scholar

9 Ian Goldin & Tiffany Vogel, Global Governance and Systemic Risk in the 21st Century: Lessons from the Financial Crisis, 1 Global Pol. 4, 11 (2010).Google Scholar

11 See generally Axelrod, Robert R., The Complexity Of Cooperation: Agent-Based Models of Competition and Collaboration (1997).Google Scholar

12 Goldin & Vogel, supra note 9, at 11.Google Scholar

13 See generally Axelrod, supra note 11.Google Scholar

14 Goldin & Vogel, supra note 9, at 12.Google Scholar

15 Beschluss [Resolution], Bundesrat Drucksachen [BR] 485/12 (Ger.).Google Scholar

16 Miller, Geoffrey P. & Gerald Rosenfeld, Intellectual Hazard: How Conceptual Biases in Complex Organizations Contributed to the Crisis of 2008, 33 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 807, 808 (2009).Google Scholar

17 See Pompian, Michael M., Behavioral Finance and Wealth Management 83 (2012).Google Scholar

18 Miller & Rosenfeld, supra note 16, at 816.Google Scholar

19 Id. at 808.Google Scholar

20 See generally id. Google Scholar

21 B. Guy Peters, Jon Pierre & Tiina Randma-Liiv, Global Financial Crisis, Public Administration and Governance: Do New Problems Require New Solutions?, 11 Pub. Org. Rev. 13, 14 (2011).Google Scholar

23 Miller & Rosenfeld, supra note 16, at 837–39.Google Scholar

24 Ansgar Belke, Politische Konjunkturzyklen in Theorie und Empirie: Eine kritische Analyse der Zeitreihendynamik in Partisan-Ansätzen (1996); Nordhaus, William D., The Political Business Cycle, 42 Rev. Econ. Stud. 169, 187–89 (1975).Google Scholar

25 Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups (1971).Google Scholar

26 Levinson, supra note 8, at 1745.Google Scholar

27 See generally Geoffrey Brennan & Buchanan, James M., Is Public Choice Immoral? The Case for the ‘Nobel’ Lie, 74 Va. L. Rev. 179 (1988).Google Scholar

28 For a more extensive set of arguments, especially with view to the field of politics, see Towfigh, supra note 5, at 149–80 (2015).Google Scholar

29 Brennan & Buchanan, supra note 27, at 182.Google Scholar

30 simon Gächter, Conditional Cooperation: Behavioral Regularities from the Lab and the Field and Their Policy Implications, in Economics and Psychology: A Promising New Cross-Disciplinary Field 19, 30–33 (Frey, Bruno S. & Alois Stutzer eds., 2007); Urs Fischbacher et al., Are People Conditionally Cooperative? Evidence from a Public Goods Experiment, 71 Econ. Letters 397 (2001); Frey, Bruno S. & Stephan Meier, Social Comparisons and Pro-Social Behavior: Testing “Conditional Cooperation” in a Field Experiment, 94 Am. Econ. Rev. 1717, 1720 (2004); Claudia Keser & Frans van Winden, Conditional Cooperation and Voluntary Contributions to Public Goods, 102 Scandinavian J. of Econ. 23, 23–24 (2000); cf. Ernst Fehr & Urs Fischbacher, The Nature of Human Altruism, 425 Nature 785, 788 (2003).Google Scholar

31 See generally Varda Liberman et al., The Name of the Game: Predictive Power of Reputations versus Situational Labels in Determining Prisoner's Dilemma Game Moves, 30 Personality & Soc. Psychol. Bull. 1175 (2004).Google Scholar

32 See generally Gneezy, Uri & Rustichini, Aldo, A Fine Is a Price, 29 J. Legal Stud. 1 (2000).Google Scholar

33 Gneezy & Rustichini, supra note 32, at 14.Google Scholar

34 Frey, Bruno S. & Felix Oberholzer-Gee, Fair Siting Procedures: An Empirical Analysis of Their Importance and Characteristics, 15 J. Pol'y Analysis & Mgmt 353, 359 (1996).Google Scholar

35 See Titmuss, Richard Morris, The Gift Relationship from Human Blood to Social Policy (1997); Carl Mellström & Magnus Johannesson, Crowding Out in Blood Donation: Was Titmuss right?, 6 J. Eur. Econ. Ass'n 845, 852–57 (2008); see also Engel, Christoph, Verhaltenswissenschaftliche Analyse: eine Gebrauchsanweisung für Juristen, in Recht und Verhalten 363, 385 (Christoph Engel et al. eds., 2007). See generally Ostrom, Elinor, Collective Action and the Evolution of Social Norms, 14 J. Econ. Persp. 137 (2000).Google Scholar

36 Nina Mazar et al., The Dishonesty of Honest People: A Theory of Self-Concept Maintenance, 45 J. Mktg. Res. 633, 635 (2008).Google Scholar

37 See Falk, Armin & Szech, Nora, Morals and Markets, 340 Sci. 707 (2013); see also Luetge, Christoph & Rusch, Hannes, The Systematic Place of Morals in Markets, 341 Sci. 714 (2013) (criticizing Falk and Szech's conclusions drawn from the mice experiment); Armin Falk & Nora Szech, Response, 341 Sci. 714 (2013) (responding to Luetge and Rush's criticisms).Google ScholarPubMed

38 The subjects did not know the mice were surplus mice from other laboratory experiments and therefore moribund, and that the experiment was not so much about active killing, but rather about extending the lifespan or saving the mice's lives. In the post-experimental de-briefing, the subjects were informed about this fact. See Falk & Szech, supra note 37, at 707.Google Scholar

39 A number of additional treatments were run to ensure robustness of the observations. See Falk & Szech, supra note 37, at 709–10.Google Scholar

40 See generally Jeannette Brosig-Koch et al., Still Different After All These Years: Solidarity Behavior in East and West Germany, 95 J. Pub. Econ. 1373 (2011); Axel Ockenfels & Joachim Weimann, Types and Patterns: an Experimental East-West-German Comparison of Cooperation and Solidarity, 71 J. Pub. Econ. 275 (1999).Google Scholar

41 See generally Frank, Robert H. et al., Does Studying Economics Inhibit Cooperation?, 7 J. Econ. Persp. 159 (1993).Google Scholar

42 See Bowles, Samuel, Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of Markets and Other Economic Institutions, 36 J. Econ. Literature 75 (1998) (“Markets and other economic institutions do more than allocate goods and services: they also influence the evolution of values, tastes, and personalities.”); Carl Christian von Weizsäcker, Adaptive Preferences and Institutional Stability, 170 J. institutional & theoretical econ. 27, 28 et seq. (2014).Google Scholar

43 See generally Carter, John R. & Irons, Michael D., Are Economists Different, and If So, Why?, 5 J. Econ. Persp. 171 (1991); Frank, Robert H. et al., Do Economists Make Bad Citizens?, 10 J. Econ. Persp. 187 (1996); Frank et al., supra note 41, at 159; Yezer, Anthony M. et al., Does Studying Economics Discourage Cooperation? Watch What We Do, Not What We Say or How We Play, 10 J. Econ. Persp. 177 (1996). For an overview, see Hole, Astri Drange, How do Economists Differ from Others in Distributive Situations?, 38 Nordic J. Pol. Econ. 1 (2013).Google Scholar