Skip to main content
    • Aa
    • Aa

Improving global accountability: The ICC and nonviolent crimes against humanity

  • EAMON ALOYO (a1)
  • DOI:
  • Published online: 17 September 2013

Scholars have proposed a number of different ways to improve global accountability, but none has adequately addressed how individuals who commit widespread or systematic nonviolent wrongs can be held to account. I argue that for moral reasons individuals should be held accountable for nonviolent crimes against humanity and that an existing legal institution, the International Criminal Court (ICC), has the authority to prosecute such crimes. The ICC’s prosecutor should start exercising this legal authority because widespread or systematic nonviolent harms can be just as morally wrong as violent ones. What matters on my account is the gravity of a wrong, not whether it was committed violently or nonviolently. I situate these arguments in contemporary discussions of accountability, and provide evidence that individuals can cause widespread or systematic nonviolent harms that meet the legal definition of a crime against humanity in the Rome Statute, the ICC’s foundational document.

Corresponding author
Linked references
Hide All

This list contains references from the content that can be linked to their source. For a full set of references and notes please see the PDF or HTML where available.

Andrew Altman , and Christopher Wellman . 2004. ‘‘A Defense of International Criminal Law.’’ Ethics 115(1):3567.

Charles R Beitz . 2009b. The Idea of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Alex Bellamy . 2009. Responsibility to Protect: The Global Effort to End Mass Atrocities. Cambridge: Polity Press.

Craig T Borowiak . 2007. ‘‘Accountability Debates: The Federalists, The Anti-Federalists, and Democratic Deficits.’’ The Journal of Politics 69(4):9981014.

Craig T Borowiak . 2011. Accountability and Democracy: The Pitfalls and Promise of Popular Control. New York: Oxford University Press.

Allen Buchanan . 1999. ‘‘Recognitional Legitimacy and the State System.’’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 28(1):4678.

Vittorio Bufacchi . 2005. ‘‘Two Concepts of Violence.’’ Political Studies Review 3(2):193204.

Thomas Christiano . 2011. ‘‘An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy.’’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 39(2):142–76.

C. A. J Coady . 1986. ‘‘The Idea of Violence.’’ Journal of Applied Philosophy 3(1):319.

Roberta Cohen . 2009. ‘‘The Burma Cyclone and the Responsibility to Protect.’’ Global Responsibility to Protect 1(2):253–7.

Robert Dahl . 1999. ‘‘Can International Organizations Be Democratic?’’ In Democracy’s Edges, edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón , 1936. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Christian Davenport . 2007. State Repression and the Domestic Democratic Peace. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Mark A Drumbl . 2007. Atrocity, Punishment, and International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Frances D’Souza . 1994. ‘‘Democracy as a Cure for Famine.’’ Journal of Peace Research 31(4):369–73.

Robert Goodin . 2007. ‘‘Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives.’’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 35(1):4068.

Carol C Gould . 2004. Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ruth Grant , and Robert O. Keohane . 2005. ‘‘Accountability and Abuses of Power in World Politics.’’ American Political Science Review 99(1):2943.

Hunjoon Kim , and Kathryn Sikkink . 2010. ‘‘Explaining the Deterrence Effect of Human Rights Prosecutions for Transitional Countries.’’ International Studies Quarterly 54(4):939–63.

David Marcus . 2003. ‘‘Famine Crimes in International Law.’’ American Journal of International Law 97(2):245–81.

Larry May . 2006b. ‘‘Humanity, International Crime, and the Rights of Defendants.’’ Ethics & International Affairs 20(3):373–82.

Larry May . 2007. War Crimes and Just War. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Martin Mennecke . 2007. ‘‘Punishing Genocidaires: A Deterrent Effect or Not?’’ Human Rights Review 8(4):319–39.

Gerhard Øverland . 2013. ‘‘602 and One Dead: On Contribution to Global Poverty and Liability to Defensive Force.’’ European Journal of Philosophy 21(2):279–99.

Thomas Plümper , and Eric Neumayer . 2009. ‘‘Famine Mortality, Rational Political Inactivity, and International Food Aid.’’ World Development 37(1):5061.

Thomas Pogge . 1992. ‘‘Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty.’’ Ethics 103(1):4875.

Jennifer Rubenstein . 2007. ‘‘Accountability in an Unequal World.’’ The Journal of Politics 69(3):616–32.

William Schabas . 2007. An Introduction to the International Criminal Court, 3rd edn.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Peter Singer . 2011. Practical Ethics, 3rd edn.New York: Cambridge University Press.

S. I Skogly . 2001. ‘‘Crimes against Humanity – Revisited: Is There a Role for Economic and Social Rights?’’ The International Journal of Human Rights 5(1):5880.

Jack Snyder , and Leslie Vinjamuri . 2004. ‘‘Trials and Errors: Principle and Pragmatism in Strategies of International Justice.’’ International Security 28(3):544.

William Talbott . 2005. Which Rights Should Be Universal? New York: Oxford University Press.

William Talbott . 2010. Human Rights and Human Well-Being. New York: Oxford University Press.

Richard Vernon . 2002. “What Is Crime against Humanity?Journal of Political Philosophy 10(3):231–49.

Leif Wenar . 2008. ‘‘Property Rights and the Resource Curse.’’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 36(1):232.

Recommend this journal

Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this journal to your organisation's collection.

Global Constitutionalism
  • ISSN: 2045-3817
  • EISSN: 2045-3825
  • URL: /core/journals/global-constitutionalism
Please enter your name
Please enter a valid email address
Who would you like to send this to? *