Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T15:55:45.566Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Law, Religion, and the COVID-19 Crisis

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2022

Mark L. Movsesian*
Affiliation:
Frederick A. Whitney Professor and Co-director, Center for Law and Religion, St. John's University
Get access
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This essay explores judicial responses to legal restrictions on worship during the COVID-19 pandemic and draws two lessons, one comparative and one relating specifically to U.S. law. As a comparative matter, courts across the globe have approached the problem in essentially the same way, through intuition and balancing. This has been the case regardless of what formal test applies, the proportionality test outside the United States, which expressly calls for judges to weigh the relative costs and benefits of a restriction, or the Employment Division v. Smith test inside the United States, which rejects judicial line-drawing and balancing in favor of predictable results. Judges have reached different conclusions about the legality of restrictions, of course, but doctrinal nuances have made little apparent difference. With respect to the United States specifically, the pandemic has revealed deep divisions about religion and religious freedom, among other things—divisions that have inevitably influenced judicial attitudes toward restrictions on worship. The COVID-19 crisis has revealed a cultural and political rift that makes consensual resolution of conflicts over religious freedom problematic, and perhaps impossible, even during a once-in-a-century pandemic.

Type
State-of-the-Field Essay
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

A Revealing Episode

For nearly two years, now, a big story in law and religion, in the United States and throughout the world, has been the COVID-19 crisis. No one anticipated this. In the United States at the start of 2020, lawyers and scholars were preoccupied with other issues, such as whether local governments could exclude religious schools from public scholarship programs,Footnote 1 and whether religious believers could claim exemptions from public accommodations laws that prohibit discrimination based on sexual orientation and gender identity.Footnote 2 In Europe, jurists disputed whether states could legally restrict ritual animal slaughter by observant Jews and Muslims.Footnote 3 Those debates have not ended. But a central issue on the law-and-religion agenda, one that has drawn academic, judicial, and popular attention, has turned out to be something completely different: whether, and to what extent, government can legally restrict collective worship during a public health emergency.

It might seem premature to draw lessons from a crisis still underway. At this writing, in late summer 2021, it remains unclear how the pandemic will continue to unfold. Governments have rescinded most of the restrictions they placed on collective worship during the pandemic's first year and the “flurry” of judicial decisions has ceased, at least for now.Footnote 4 Perhaps COVID-19 will ultimately fade from memory, much like the 1918 flu epidemic, and leave little trace on the law of church and state.Footnote 5 But the rise of the Delta variant suggests COVID-19 will be with us for some time. Moreover, enough case law exists to merit some early observations. Although crises can distort legal doctrine, they can also clarify, and that is the case here.Footnote 6 As in other contexts, in law, the COVID-19 pandemic has revealed dynamics that already existed and trends that were already underway.Footnote 7

In this essay, I draw two early lessons from the COVID-19 crisis, one comparative and one relating specifically to United States law.Footnote 8 A comparative approach is appropriate in this context. Sometimes, legal problems differ in ways that make comparisons tricky; determining whether the problems sufficiently resemble one another can be vexing.Footnote 9 In this crisis, however, courts faced the same problem: how to reduce the spread of the novel coronavirus without infringing the right to corporate worship. They did so, moreover, in an emergency setting where conclusive evidence was unavailable and the consequences, quite literally, a matter of life and death.Footnote 10 If any legal problems merit comparative analysis, this would seem to be one.

A comparative analysis of courts' responses to restrictions on worship during the COVID-19 pandemic offers something of a surprise. With respect to restrictions on religious freedom, scholars often highlight the differences between the proportionality test that courts outside the United States favor and the U.S. approach under Employment Division v. Smith, a 1990 Supreme Court decision on the scope of the First Amendment's Free Exercise Clause.Footnote 11 Proportionality analysis expressly calls for judges to weigh the relative costs and benefits of a restriction,Footnote 12 while Smith rejects judicial balancing in favor of legislative supremacy and predictable results.Footnote 13 During the pandemic, however, whatever formal test they have applied, courts have approached the problem in essentially the same way, through intuition and balancing. Smith has failed to prevent judicial assessments of pros and cons, as critics long predicted it would.Footnote 14

Across the globe, the legality of COVID-19–related restrictions has depended ultimately on judges' weighing of the competing interests at stake.Footnote 15 This necessarily has entailed “value judgments” about the importance of religious exercise, compared to things like grocery shopping and dining out, and the need to accommodate some religious believers.Footnote 16 Judges have weighed things differently; some have upheld restrictions and others have not. The important comparative point, though, is that doctrinal nuances in U.S. and foreign law have made little apparent difference.Footnote 17 The pandemic thus reveals affinities between proportionality analysis and the U.S. approach, at least in times of crisis.

With respect to the United States, specifically, the crisis suggests a further lesson, not about affinities but about divisions. Scholars debate the extent to which ideological and political commitments affect judging generally.Footnote 18 In the COVID-19 crisis, however, judicial disagreements have closely tracked judges' partisan identities.Footnote 19 At the Supreme Court, Democratic-appointed justices consistently have ruled against religious plaintiffs in COVID-19–related cases. Republican-appointed justices, with one exception, consistently have ruled for religious plaintiffs, and the appointment of Justice Barrett to replace the late Justice Ginsburg during the pandemic decisively shifted the Court in their favor.Footnote 20 As Zalman Rothschild writes, when the Court's “political make-up shifted, so did its stance on COVID-19–related restrictions on religious institutions.”Footnote 21

These partisan divisions should come as no surprise. No completely neutral basis exists for deciding whether a government has restricted religious exercise more than necessary to achieve public health goals. At some point, “the relatively pure science runs out,” and decisions require “normatively contested moral and political judgments.”Footnote 22 Judges, like the rest of us, naturally strike the balance based on “priors”—commitments and intuitions about the comparative virtues and importance of religious exercise, for believers and for society.Footnote 23 Those priors deeply divide Americans, and our divisions increasingly express themselves in partisan terms.Footnote 24 In this environment, judges appointed by Republican presidents naturally tend to favor the claims of religious plaintiffs, while judges appointed by Democratic presidents naturally tend to disfavor them.

The “pandemic,” in journalist Lawrence Wright's words, has “exposed many different fractures” in U.S. society, not only concerning religion.Footnote 25 Deep divisions exist about the good faith of elites, the competence and benevolence of government, the credibility of scientific opinion, and many other factors. All these divisions have influenced the ways in which citizens—and judges—have evaluated restrictions on communal worship. But varying opinions on the value of religion and religious freedom have had a central role in the COVID-19–related legal cases. In the United States, the COVID-19 crisis has revealed a cultural and political rift that makes consensual resolution of conflicts over religious freedom problematic, and sometimes impossible, even during a once-in-a-century pandemic.Footnote 26

Outside the United States: The Proportionality Test

Outside the United States, courts have decided COVID-19–related cases under the so-called proportionality test,Footnote 27 “the common method worldwide for adjudicating constitutional rights.”Footnote 28 Proportionality analysis involves “a limitation phase and a justification phase.”Footnote 29 In the limitation phase, the court asks whether the law in question “infringes or interferes with a right.”Footnote 30 If the answer is yes, the court moves to the justification phase, which asks whether “the interference is justified in virtue of being proportionate to the aim or value of the law.”Footnote 31 To decide whether a measure is justified, the court employs a three- or four-part test that asks, in one form or another, whether the law in question “(1) pursues a legitimate purpose, (2) actually advances that purpose, (3) restricts the right no more than is necessary to achieve the purpose, and (4) restricts the right in a proportionate way.”Footnote 32 In practice, these requirements overlap, and the last two are the most significant, especially the necessity requirement, which in formal terms resembles the least-restrictive-means requirement in U.S. law.Footnote 33 Indeed, according to Justin Collings and Stephanie Barclay, “many proportionality courts frequently end their analysis at the necessity step.”Footnote 34

Courts in many countries have applied proportionality analysis to COVID-19–related restrictions, including Canada, France, Germany, Greece, and Scotland, with mixed results.Footnote 35 Some courts have found restrictions justified; others have not.Footnote 36 Sometimes the same court has found restrictions justified at one stage of the pandemic but not at later stages, as more information about COVID-19 has become available.Footnote 37 The French Council of State and German Federal Constitutional Court are good examples of this phenomenon.Footnote 38 The details of specific restrictions presumably made some difference to the outcomes in these cases, as did the fact that various national legal systems, each with its own understanding of proportionality and its own rules “for the exercise of emergency powers,” were involved.Footnote 39 But the main reason for the different results was surely the proportionality test itself, which relies so prominently on judicial line-drawing and balancing.Footnote 40 Judges applying the proportionality test naturally weighed risks and benefits differently.

A good example comes from Scotland. In Reverend Dr William J U Philip and Others,Footnote 41 the Outer House of the Court of Session ruled that a ban on public worship violated the proportionality test under constitutional principles and under Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rights, which confers a right to manifest one's religion in public, including through worship.Footnote 42 In January 2021, during an outbreak of a virus variant, Scottish officials ordered places of worship in the country to close temporarily, except for a few limited purposes, including funerals, marriage ceremonies (comprising no more than 5–6 people), and “essential voluntary services” like “food banks,” “blood donation sessions,” and “vaccination centers.”Footnote 43 The order effectively prevented “any form of communal worship” in Scotland, either “indoors or outdoors.”Footnote 44 The closure also extended to movie theaters, sports stadiums, and conference centers, again with a few exceptions, and to most retail establishments, though not to “essential” businesses like “food retailers, pharmacies, funeral directors,” and “bicycle shops.”Footnote 45

The Scottish authorities and the claimants agreed that the ban on public worship interfered with the claimants' right to manifest their religion.Footnote 46 The proportionality analysis thus moved to the justification phase, which Lord Braid described as follows: “(i) whether the objective being pursued is sufficiently important to justify the limitation of a protected right; (ii) whether the measure is rationally connected to the objective; (iii) whether a less intrusive measure could have been used without unacceptably compromising the achievement of the objective; and (iv) whether, balancing the severity of the measure's effect on the rights of the persons to whom it applies against the importance of the objective, to the extent that the measure will contribute to its achievement, the former outweighs the latter.”Footnote 47

No debate existed on the first two questions. The parties agreed that the government's objective, “reduction in risk for the protection of health and preservation of life,” was legitimate and sufficiently important in principle to justify limiting the right to worship.Footnote 48 Moreover, a rational connection existed between that objective and the government's decision to ban many public gatherings. “It is not irrational to conclude,” Lord Braid wrote, “that the more people stay at home, the less the virus will be passed on.”Footnote 49

Lord Braid concluded, however, that the total ban on communal worship was not necessary to achieve the government's aim. Several factors influenced his decision, including the authorities' apparent concession that the risk of transmission in public worship was relatively small and their failure even to consider less restrictive measures, such as keeping the density of occupants low and providing good ventilation.Footnote 50 The most important consideration, he suggested, was the fact that the authorities had allowed some exceptions to the ban on public gatherings, thus acknowledging, at least implicitly, that meetings could “be safe if suitable mitigation measures [were] adopted.”Footnote 51 If it was not too risky, for example, to open movie theaters as jury centers as long as people observed mitigation requirements, why was it too risky to open places of worship?Footnote 52 The existence of exceptions showed that the government could equally achieve its aims through a measure less intrusive than an outright ban.Footnote 53

Lord Braid dismissed deferring to public health authorities because “a scientific judgment [was] involved”Footnote 54 and the authorities possessed “expertise and experience” he lacked.Footnote 55 The “science” was “not in dispute.”Footnote 56 Everyone agreed that COVID-19 was “an extremely serious and highly transmissible disease which can result in serious illness and death,” and that mitigation measures like “social distancing, face masks, hand washing and good ventilation” could “reduce the risk of transmission.”Footnote 57 The ban on communal worship failed the necessity test, not because anyone questioned the science, but because the authorities had not explained why, given the scientific consensus, some public gatherings could proceed safely with mitigation measures but communal worship could not. This inconsistency undercut whatever deference the court might have given to the authorities' expertise and experience.

Lord Braid's decision that the ban was not necessary could have ended the proportionality analysis—as we have seen, courts frequently stop at this point—but he continued to step four, the balancing stage, “for completeness and in case I am wrong.”Footnote 58 Regarding the risk avoided, only a relatively small number of persons with COVID-19 infections apparently had attended religious services, “in comparison with other activities.”Footnote 59 A total ban on communal worship, therefore, would not likely contribute “to a material reduction” in the risk of COVID-19 transmission.Footnote 60 Moreover, the existence of exceptions in other circumstances undercut the benefit of a “‘bright-line’” rule respecting religious gatherings.Footnote 61 By contrast, the authorities had underestimated the importance of the right to manifest one's religion, especially compared with other activities they had determined to be “essential” and allowed to continue.Footnote 62 True, the ban was only temporary (though it had stretched on for months) and believers could participate in online worship.Footnote 63 Some believers evidently found this arrangement unobjectionable.Footnote 64 But online worship was at best “an alternative to, not a substitute for,” communal in-person worship—“worship-lite,” Lord Braid called it—and, as a result of the ban, some important ceremonies could not occur at all, including communion, baptism, and confession.Footnote 65 Even though the question was “finely balanced,” the burdens of a total ban on communal worship outweighed the benefits.Footnote 66

As this summary shows, intuitive judgments had a central role in Philip. Consider the necessity determination. Whether a public-health measure goes too far is not a question with a categorical answer. It is a judgment call depending on many factors, including the nature of the risk, the relative importance of the activities restricted, and, crucially, the credibility of public-health officials who might, because of their professional commitments, dismiss religious viewpoints.Footnote 67 For Lord Braid, the temporary ban on communal worship was excessive, given the risks involved, and in the circumstances, he felt he could evaluate the evidence himself and need not give public-health officials the benefit of the doubt. The point is not that he was wrong. The point is a judge with contrary views could just as plausibly have drawn the lines differently. “Narrower tailoring,” as Cass Sunstein observes, “is almost always imaginable.”Footnote 68

Intuitive judgments also figured centrally in step four, which expressly required Lord Braid to weigh competing benefits and burdens. His conclusion in this respect depended on intuitive and contested assumptions, for example, that in-person, communal worship is equally important during a pandemic as obtaining food and that temporarily requiring believers to avail themselves of online services imposed an unacceptable cost (“worship-lite”). Even many believers did not share those assumptions. In Scotland, as in many other places, many religious communities supported temporary restrictions on gathering.Footnote 69 Again, Lord Braid's conclusion was certainly plausible. But a judge with different assumptions, applying the same proportionality analysis, could just as plausibly have reached the opposite conclusion—as some U.K. judges did, with respect to other COVID-19–related restrictions.Footnote 70

The U.S. Cases: General Applicability under Smith

The U.S. COVID-19 cases likewise have turned on judicial line drawing and balancing. This might come as a surprise, since, as a formal matter, U.S. law does not rely on the proportionality test. In practice, though, during the COVID-19 crisis, U.S. courts have acted very much like their foreign counterparts. Under the pressure of the pandemic, as Collings and Barclay observe, the legal “framework” has not mattered much.Footnote 71 The “priors” of individual judges—their normative commitments and intuitions about the comparative virtues and importance of religious exercise—have mattered more.Footnote 72 And those, quite evidently, have differed greatly.

More than thirty years ago, the Supreme Court announced a test that was supposed to preclude judicial balancing in religious freedom cases. Under Employment Division v. Smith, a neutral, generally applicable law that only incidentally burdens religious exercise is presumptively constitutional.Footnote 73 Such a law receives only minimal, “rational basis” review, which is virtually impossible to fail.Footnote 74 Only where a law is not neutral and generally applicable—that is, where the law substantially burdens religious conduct more than analogous nonreligious conduct—does “strict scrutiny” apply.Footnote 75 In those circumstances, the state must show that the law serves a compelling governmental interest and does so only as far as necessary.Footnote 76 The state must show that it could not equally achieve its interest in a way that burdens religious exercise to a lesser degree.Footnote 77

The Smith Court evidently believed that the neutral-and-generally-applicable test would limit occasions for judicial balancing and promote predictability.Footnote 78 During the COVID-19 crisis, the opposite has occurred. The neutrality requirement has not posed much problem.Footnote 79 With a couple of possible exceptions, U.S. authorities have not targeted religion during the pandemic, though some have acted with comparative “indifference,”Footnote 80 as in New York City, where Mayor de Blasio downplayed the importance of worship in comparison with political protests.Footnote 81 General applicability has proved troublesome, however.Footnote 82 The requirement has puzzled scholars for decades and the pandemic has intensified the tensions.Footnote 83 Whether public-health measures like COVID-19 restrictions are generally applicable is not an objective matter, but a question of judgment that turns on implicit balancing—an assessment of the “comparative risks and importance of certain activities.”Footnote 84 In the COVID-19 crisis, with so many unknowns and so much at stake, judges have found it impossible to reach consensus.

Consider the shifting decisions of the Supreme Court. Early in the pandemic, in South Bay United Pentecostal Church v. Newsom (South Bay I), by a vote of 5–4, the Court refused to enjoin a California measure limiting “attendance at places of worship to 25% of building capacity or a maximum of 100 attendees.”Footnote 85 Like the Court's other COVID-19–related cases, South Bay I was part of the Court's “shadow docket”—an emergency application for injunctive relief—and the Court did not issue an opinion.Footnote 86 Nonetheless, it is clear that the general applicability requirement divided the justices.Footnote 87 For example, Chief Justice Roberts, who voted with the majority, noted that California had imposed similar or stricter restrictions on “comparable secular gatherings, including lectures, concerts, movie showings, spectator sports, and theatrical performances, where large groups of people gather in close proximity for extended periods.”Footnote 88 Consequently, the California measure merited only minimal review, especially during a public health emergency that counseled deference to expert opinion.Footnote 89 By contrast, Justice Kavanaugh's dissent argued that the measure was not generally applicable, since “comparable secular businesses [were] not subject to” the cap, “including factories, offices, supermarkets, retail stores, pharmacies, shopping malls, pet grooming shops, bookstores, florists, hair salons, and cannabis dispensaries.”Footnote 90 Two months later, in Calvary Chapel v. Sisolak,Footnote 91 the Court again divided 5–4 in refusing to enjoin a Nevada restriction on places of worship, with the dissenters again protesting that the restriction did not apply to comparable “activities that involve extended, indoor gatherings of large groups of people,” including casinos.Footnote 92

A few months after that, though, in Roman Catholic Diocese of Brooklyn v. Cuomo,Footnote 93 the Court, by a vote of 5–4, enjoined a New York measure that looked very much like the ones it had permitted in South Bay I and Calvary Chapel. The measure divided the state into color-coded zones. In “red” zones, where the danger of contagion was high, the state restricted attendance at places of worship to 10 persons; in “orange” zones, where the risk of contagion was somewhat less, to 25.Footnote 94 Once again, the Justices disagreed about general applicability. For the members of the majority, New York had imposed stricter limits on places of worship than comparable, nonreligious gatherings. For example, Justice Gorsuch noted that the state allowed people to gather for long periods in laundromats and hardware stores, among other places.Footnote 95 By contrast, the dissenters argued that the proper comparator for religious services was the set of activities involving “large groups of people gathering, speaking, and singing in close proximity indoors for extended periods”—theaters and concert halls, for example.Footnote 96 By that measure, New York had treated religious and nonreligious activities alike. Indeed, New York had treated religious activities better than it had their secular counterparts.Footnote 97

The debate continued in two subsequent cases. In South Bay Pentecostal Church v. Newsom (South Bay II), a divided Court enjoined California's ban on indoor worship services.Footnote 98 Justice Gorsuch argued in a concurrence that the prohibition was not generally applicable, since most retail stores continued to operate at 25 percent capacity.Footnote 99 By contrast, Justice Kagan's dissent argued that the proper comparator was the set of secular gatherings California had banned along with religious services—political meetings, for example—and criticized the majority for “displac[ing] the judgments of experts about how to respond to a raging pandemic.”Footnote 100 Finally, in Tandon v. Newsom, the Court enjoined, 5–4, California's ban on at-home religious gatherings of more than three households.Footnote 101 The majority maintained that California had treated “comparable secular activities” better than at-home religious gatherings, since it had allowed retail stores, movie theaters, and restaurants, among other locations, to admit more than three households at a time.Footnote 102 In dissent, Justice Kagan again disagreed, arguing that the “obvious comparator” was not retail operations, but at-home, nonreligious gatherings, which California had also limited to no more than three households.Footnote 103 Viewed in that light, the restriction applied generally to religious and secular activities.

The Court has thus found it impossible to stick to a consistent position regarding the general applicability requirement and COVID-19–related restrictions on places of worship. This is not surprising. Whatever the Smith Court hoped, general applicability has always depended on judicial line drawing, and “in a pandemic, the line-drawing problems are challenging.”Footnote 104 Notwithstanding scoffing by some on both sides, finding the right comparator for religious services in these cases was “not straightforward.”Footnote 105 In terms of risk of contagion, places of worship are not entirely like factories, restaurants, shopping malls, and casinos, but not entirely unlike them, either.Footnote 106 Whether worship services were “close enough” to activities the state had permitted was a question without a categorical answer. Deference to public health authorities could not resolve things, because it, too, depended on judicial line drawing.Footnote 107 All agreed the Court should defer to the experts to some extent. But how far?

It seems apparent that the justices drew the lines in these cases, based not so much on the similarity or dissimilarity between places of worship and other locations, but on whether the authorities had fairly excluded worship services from the set of activities they had permitted.Footnote 108 This necessarily entailed implicit balancing and “value judgments” about the importance of religious exercise, compared to things like grocery shopping and dining out, and the need to accommodate some religious believers.Footnote 109 These matters greatly divide conservative and progressive Americans, including conservative and progressive justices. Notably, the Court switched its position, from acquiescing in the restrictions in South Bay I and Calvary Chapel to forbidding them in Roman Catholic Diocese, South Bay II, and Tandon, after Justice Barrett, a conservative, replaced Justice Ginsburg, a progressive, thus altering the philosophical balance on the Court. I have more to say about this below.

Strict Scrutiny and Proportionality: Intuition and Balancing

The decisions in Roman Catholic Diocese, South Bay II, and Tandon made clear that the Court would subject COVID-19–related restrictions on communal worship to strict scrutiny. As a formal matter, strict scrutiny differs from proportionality analysis, for example, with respect to the “framing” of the right in question.Footnote 110 Strict scrutiny applies only to “fundamental” rights, while the proportionality test applies to rights more generally.Footnote 111 Moreover, strict scrutiny requires that the state have a “compelling” interest to justify its measure, not merely a “legitimate” one.Footnote 112 Finally, strict scrutiny does not formally call for judicial balancing.Footnote 113 The proportionality test, by contrast, expressly requires a court to weigh the relative costs and benefits of a measure (though “many” courts “frequently” skip this step in practice and may “smuggl[e]” balancing into the necessity requirement).Footnote 114

Nonetheless, one should not overstate the dissimilarities, and, in the COVID-19 crisis, at least, the two tests have worked out essentially the same.Footnote 115 The framing of the right has not made a difference in this context, since all concede the fundamental character of the right to worship. Similarly, no one doubts the state has a compelling interest in reducing the spread of COVID-19. Proportionality's necessity requirement outside the United States has performed a similar function to strict scrutiny's least-restrictive means test inside the United States.Footnote 116 In Philip, recall, Lord Braid described the necessity requirement in words a U.S. judge could have used to describe U.S. law. The question, Lord Braid wrote, was “whether a less intrusive measure could have been used without unacceptably compromising the achievement of the [state's] objective.”Footnote 117

Finally, whatever the formalities, in practice strict scrutiny often operates as a balancing test, requiring courts to make “all-things-considered” judgments about the relative weight of competing social goods, especially where a measure would “reduce risks of harm rather than eliminate them.”Footnote 118 That is what has happened in the COVID-19 context. Judges applying strict scrutiny have weighed whether a limitation on collective worship is “justifiable in light of the benefits likely to be achieved and the available alternatives.”Footnote 119 And they have done so based on “priors”—intuitions about things like the importance of collective worship, the need to “follow the science,” and the competence and goodwill of regulatory authorities.

Consider South Bay II.Footnote 120 The Court did not address strict scrutiny in its per curiam opinion, but, writing separately, Justice Gorsuch did, and a majority agreed with the heart of his analysis.Footnote 121 Gorsuch characterized strict scrutiny as a balancing test opposing the interests of religious believers to those of the public more generally. In such cases, he wrote, “courts nearly always face an individual's claim of constitutional right pitted against the government's claim of special expertise in a matter of high importance involving public health and safety.”Footnote 122 Here, California had a compelling interest in stopping the spread of COVID-19, but religious believers had a right to worship, and California had not sufficiently explained why it could not honor that right and still achieve its stated objectives.Footnote 123 For example, the state could have required places of worship to adopt the social distancing measures it had mandated for “many secular settings.”Footnote 124 It could have restricted occupancy, imposed reasonable time limits, or given places of worship the option of offering regular COVID-19 testing.Footnote 125 Any of these alternatives would have constrained believers' free exercise rights less than a total ban and still allowed California to reach its stated public health goals.

Justice Gorsuch appeared unperturbed by the fact that public health experts evidently disagreed that narrower measures would equally reduce the spread of COVID-19. “Of course we are not scientists,” he conceded, but judges should not defer to experts where constitutional rights were at stake.Footnote 126 He did not put it this way, exactly, but he obviously believed that balancing the interests of some religious believers and the public at large was a matter for the courts, not epidemiologists. Besides, public health experts had burned their credibility by “moving the goalposts on pandemic-related sacrifices for months, adopting new benchmarks that always seem to put restoration of liberty just around the corner.”Footnote 127

Like Lord Braid in Philip, in South Bay II, Justice Gorsuch balanced competing social goods and concluded that the costs of the state's measure, in terms of the restriction on believers' rights, outweighed the benefits, in terms of reducing the spread of disease. And, like Lord Braid, he did so based on intuitions—“naked judicial instinct,” Justice Kagan complained in dissent—that many would not share.Footnote 128 To give just one example, Justice Gorsuch's opinion turned on the assumption that temporarily banning indoor gathering substantially burdened believers. As in Scotland, however, many congregations in California easily adjusted to restrictions on in-person worship.Footnote 129 “Given California's mild climate,” Justice Kagan protested, forbidding indoor gathering did “not amount to a ban” on worship.Footnote 130 Believers could continue to worship outdoors; in fact, “[w]orship services” had “taken place outdoors throughout this winter.”Footnote 131

Justice Kagan also expressed dismay at the Court's dismissal of experts' conclusions on the measures necessary to reduce contagion. “[I]t is alarming,” she wrote, “that the Court second-guesses the judgment of expert officials,” since, “[t]o state the obvious, judges do not know what scientists and public health experts do.”Footnote 132 The Court had substituted “judicial edict” for “science-based policy.”Footnote 133 But whether, and how far, to defer to experts is itself a judgment call that depends on one's confidence in the experts' consistency and good faith, as well as one's assessment of the gravity of the risk and the costs deference imposes on important rights like free exercise.Footnote 134 On those matters, Justices Gorsuch and Kagan evidently disagreed. Both made plausible arguments. The point is that judges applying strict scrutiny in the same case easily can reach different conclusions if they start with different priors about fundamental matters.

In short, in the COVID-19 crisis, doctrinal differences have had relatively little significance. Under either the proportionality test outside the United States, or Employment Division v. Smith inside the United States, courts have decided cases based mostly on intuition and balancing. Undoubtedly, the pressure of the crisis explains much. In a public-health emergency, where speed is essential and hard information difficult to obtain, intuitive assessments may be the best one can do. But crises often clarify, and the COVID-19 pandemic has done so. Notwithstanding formal differences, in their case-by-case character and reliance on individual judgment, proportionality analysis and strict scrutiny have shown themselves in this episode to be more alike than different.Footnote 135 In some circumstances, where debate exists about the importance of the right in question or the strength of the state's interest, proportionality and strict scrutiny may cash out differently. But the COVID-19 crisis has revealed that the two tests share significant affinities.

Judicial Partisanship and Cultural Divisions in the United States

What has the pandemic revealed about U.S. law, specifically? Here, the story is not one of affinity but division. The Court's inconsistent decisions in the COVID-19–related cases reflect a cultural and partisan divide respecting religion and religious freedom. True, that is not the only fissure that exists in the United States today. The COVID-19 crisis has revealed other disagreements as well, for example, about the competence of government, the credibility of scientific experts, and other matters. And the pandemic did not create our religious divide, which has been growing for decades, and which has influenced the Court's response to other legal questions as well.Footnote 136 But the current public health crisis, affecting hundreds of millions of Americans simultaneously, has intensified our religious divide and made it impossible to ignore.Footnote 137 In the crisis, the lack of a “shared baseline” with respect to religious freedom has become quite manifest.Footnote 138

Where cultural consensus exists on an issue, balancing tests like strict scrutiny work reasonably predictably. Results differ in specific cases, but judges tend to weigh rights and interests in foreseeable ways that widely conform to social expectations.Footnote 139 Where consensus does not exist, however, balancing tests become more problematic.Footnote 140 In that context, outcomes turn on the personal worldviews of the judges who happen to hear a case—and given the lack of consensus, those worldviews may vary considerably. In the absence of shared cultural understanding, judges inevitably rely on their “own moral backgrounds” and commitments and weigh interests differently.Footnote 141 As a result, judicial balancing becomes “unpredictable” and legal doctrine “incoherent.”Footnote 142 One would expect this to be the case especially in an emergency, where access to reliable information is uncertain and the potential consequences severe, and where the sense of crisis swamps the effect of professional training that might otherwise encourage greater judicial detachment.Footnote 143

The shifting results in the Court's COVID-19–related cases reflect this dynamic. The historical U.S. consensus on the beneficence of religion—the traditional idea that “religion is valuable and . . . legal rules should be crafted for the purpose of protecting that value”Footnote 144—no longer exists. Americans have not become uniformly irreligious; rather, they have become polarized, and the polarization expresses itself, more and more, in partisan terms.Footnote 145 Increasingly, Republicans are the party of traditional believers, especially conservative Christians, while Democrats are the party of Nones and secular Americans.Footnote 146 Some exceptions exist. Black Christians strongly identify as Democrats, for example, as do the relatively small number of Americans who consider themselves part of the “Religious Left.”Footnote 147 Overall, though, the religious/secular divide between the two parties appears consistently in social surveys.

This partisan divide affects judicial appointments—and, through them, judicial decisions.Footnote 148 As Devins and Baum show in a recent study, “presidents increasingly choose [judicial] nominees who . . . adhere strongly to their parties' dominant ideological tendency,”Footnote 149 so that “credible [judicial] candidates from either party are likely to reflect the ideological gap that separates” Democrats from Republicans.Footnote 150 In the free exercise context, one would expect Democratic presidents to nominate judges who sympathize with the secularism that increasingly defines that party and Republican presidents to nominate judges who sympathize with the GOP's pro-religious orientation. Presidents have a handily differentiated set of candidates from which to choose. Legal elites today are as divided as the rest of the country, if not more, and competing progressive and conservative networks exist to help identify the right people to fill vacancies on the bench.Footnote 151 Consequently, presidents of both parties can readily select judicial candidates likely to sympathize with their parties' core commitments.

The lack of a cultural baseline thus has made judicial decisions on religious freedom more subjective and dependent on judges' partisan identities. Americans today “lack a common measure for weighing the importance of practicing one's religion against other important concerns,”Footnote 152 and, as a result, a test like strict scrutiny, which depends so heavily on judges' priors, leads inevitably to politically polarized results. Exactly that pattern has appeared in the U.S. COVID-19–related legal cases.Footnote 153 A study by Zalman Rothschild of more than 100 such cases in the federal courts reveals that not a single Democratic-appointed judge has ruled in favor of religious plaintiffs in any of them.Footnote 154 By contrast, “66% of Republican-appointed judges” have done so, and “82% of Trump-appointed judges.”Footnote 155 This partisan breakdown has held true at the Supreme Court as well as in the lower courts.Footnote 156 Democratic-appointed justices consistently have ruled against religious plaintiffs in COVID-19–related cases. Republican-appointed justices, with one exception, consistently have ruled for religious plaintiffs, and, as we have seen, the appointment of Justice Barrett to replace the late Justice Ginsburg during the pandemic decisively shifted the Court in their favor.Footnote 157

Again, the COVID-19 crisis did not create this situation. The polarization I describe has been growing for decades—an aspect of our ongoing culture wars.Footnote 158 The crisis has highlighted those divisions, however. How could it be otherwise? The pandemic has presented difficult questions in a context of great uncertainty and consequence and has required judges to make quick decisions without the benefit of regular briefing or argument. And it has done so in a context of deep social and political dissensus on the value and scope of religious freedom. In this environment, it is not surprising that judges would fall back on their priors and decide cases differently from one another. Indeed, a consensual resolution in this setting hardly seems possible.Footnote 159 It is not a wonder that judicial balancing in the COVID-19–related cases has been so partisan and controversial. The wonder would be if that were not the case.

Conclusion

In an essay in April 2021, Javier Martínez-Torrón wrote about what legal scholars can learn from the COVID-19 pandemic. The most important lessons, he suggested, do not relate to “concrete” particulars—the details of specific restrictions and the holdings of specific cases.Footnote 160 Like all pandemics, this one will eventually end, and paying too much attention to the finer points of courts' responses to it would be a mistake. Rather, scholars should concentrate on what the COVID-19–related legal cases reveal about the law more generally, about “already familiar” questions that “manifest with special clarity in moments of crisis.”Footnote 161 Most of all, scholars should focus “on what this pandemic teaches us about ourselves, that is, about our societies, our conception of political organization, [and] our understanding . . . of fundamental rights, including freedom of religion or belief.”Footnote 162

In this essay, I have drawn two such lessons, one comparative and one relating specifically to U.S. law. As a comparative matter, the crisis suggests significant affinities between the proportionality test courts outside the United States favor and the U.S. approach under Employment Division v. Smith. Doctrinal differences have not had much practical significance, at least during the crisis. Both in the United States and abroad, courts ultimately have struck a balance between the competing interests at stake, those of some religious believers and those of the public more generally, and have relied on intuition and normative commitments about the comparative importance of religious exercise. With respect to the United States, specifically, the COVID-19–related legal cases reveal a cultural and political divide that makes consensual resolution of conflicts over religious freedom increasingly problematic, and perhaps impossible, even during a once-in-a-century pandemic.

Acknowledgments

I thank Silas Allard, Justin Collings, Marc DeGirolami, Adelaide Madera, Javier Martínez-Torrón, John McGinnis, Andrea Pin, Zalman Rothschild, and my colleagues at a faculty workshop at St. John's Law School for helpful comments on earlier drafts. I thank Jordan Pamlanye, St. John's Law School Class of ’22, for research assistance.

References

1 E.g., Espinoza v. Montana Department of Revenue, 140 S. Ct. 2246 (2020).

2 E.g., Fulton v. City of Philadelphia, 141 S. Ct. 1868 (2021); Masterpiece Cakeshop v. Colorado Civil Rights Commission, 138 S. Ct. 1719 (2018); cf. Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1753–54 (2020).

3 E.g., Judgment of 17 Dec. 2020, Centraal Israëlitisch Consistorie van België et al., C-336/19, ECLI:EU:C:2020:1031, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/document/document.jsf?text=&docid=235717&pageIndex=0&doclang=en&mode=req&dir=&occ=first&part=1&cid=16882268.

4 Zalman Rothschild, Free Exercise Partisanship, 107 Cornell Law Review (forthcoming 2022) (manuscript at 16) (manuscript on file with author).

5 See Alfred W. Crosby, America's Forgotten Pandemic: The Influenza of 1918, at 305 (2d ed. 2003).

6 Cf. Skeel, David A. Jr., Institutional Choice in an Economic Crisis, 2013 Wisconsin Law Review 629, 645Google Scholar (suggesting that “legally problematic responses to a crisis” can “cause lasting distortions to the law”).

7 See Note, Constitutional Constraints on Free Exercise Analogies, 134 Harvard Law Review 1782, 1785 (2021) [hereinafter Constitutional Constraints].

8 In the interests of space, I focus on cases from the United States and Europe, but “a steady stream of cases from around the world” have considered these issues as well. Hill, Mark, Coronavirus and the Curtailment of Religious Liberty, 9 Laws 1, 4 (2020)Google Scholar. For more on the situation in Africa, see id. at 5, 6. For a discussion of government responses in Asia and Oceania, see generally Guo, Xioming, An Academic Summary of the International Conference Series on “The Role of the Proportionality Principle in the Pandemic Prevention and Control, 29 Journal of Human Rights 535 (2020)Google Scholar. For a discussion of some COVID-19–related restrictions in Latin America, see Javier Martínez-Torrón, COVID-19 and Religious Freedom: Some Comparative Perspectives, 10 Laws 39, at 6 (Brazil), at 12 (Chile) (2021).

9 See, e.g., Brand, Oliver, Conceptual Comparisons: Towards a Coherent Methodology of Comparative Legal Studies, 32 Brooklyn Journal of International Law 405, 418 (2007)Google Scholar.

10 See Cassell v. Snyders, 990 F.3d 539, 549 (7th Cir. 2021) (noting that governments have “been forced to act with imperfect knowledge” when devising strategy during the COVID-19 pandemic). Cf. Adelaide Madera, Some Preliminary Remarks on the Impact of COVID-19 on the Exercise of Religious Freedom in the United States and Italy, 16 Stato, Chiese e Pluralismo Confessionale 70, 77 (2020) (observing that the COVID-19 crisis required the Italian government “to undertake . . . a complex balancing of many fundamental freedoms with the urgent need to protect public health and safety and to do so very quickly”).

11 Employment Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990). For contrasts between the two approaches, see, for example, Justin Collings and Stephanie Hall Barclay, Taking Justification Seriously: Proportionality, Strict Scrutiny, and the Substance of Religious Liberty, Boston College Law Review (forthcoming 2022) (manuscript at 6) (on file with author) (suggesting that the two approaches are not “interchangeable when it comes to protecting religious exercise”). See also Jamal Greene, Foreword: Rights as Trumps, 132 Harvard Law Review 28, 34–35 (2018) (distinguishing proportionality analysis from U.S. “categoricalism”).

12 See, e.g., Paul Yowell, Constitutional Rights and Constitutional Design 16 (2018) (describing the proportionality test). For more on the proportionality test, see infra text accompanying notes 27–34.

13 Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 13) (arguing that Smith “openly and energetically eschewed any meaningful form of interest-balancing”). In Smith, the U.S. Supreme Court held that a religiously neutral and generally applicable law could permissibly restrict the exercise of religion, so long as the law had a rational basis. Smith, 494 U.S. at 881–82. For more on the Smith approach, see infra text accompanying notes 73–77.

14 See, e.g., Marc O. DeGirolami, The Tragedy of Religious Freedom 150, 160–65 (2013) (arguing that Smith does not provide the predictability proponents claim).

15 Cf. Yowell, supra note 12, at 9 (noting how constitutional-rights adjudication in U.S. courts typically attempts to “strike the right balance between collective and individual interests”); Leading Case, Espinoza v. Montana Department of Revenue, 140 S. Ct. 2246 (2020), 134 Harvard Law Review 470, 477 (2020) (noting that many of the Supreme Court's religion clause cases “boil down to raw interest-balancing exercises”).

16 Note, Constitutional Constraints, supra note 7, at 1790. See also Josh Blackman, The “Essential” Free Exercise Clause, 44 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 637, 686 (2021).

17 See Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 3–4) (“religious liberty depends less on which framework is adopted than on how that framework is employed”) (emphasis in original).

18 Compare Kahan, Dan M. et al. , “Ideology” or “Situation Sense”? An Experimental Investigation of Motivated Reasoning and Professional Judgment, 164 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 349, 354–55 (2016)Google Scholar (arguing that professional training and experience help judges overcome “political predispositions”) and Gregory C. Sisk and Michael Heise, Ideology “All the Way Down”? An Empirical Study of Establishment Clause Decisions in the Federal Courts, 110 Michigan Law Review 1201, 1204 (2012) (arguing that judges’ politics and ideology play a major role in Establishment Clause cases). For more on the topic, see generally Klonick, Kate, The New Governors: The People, Rules, and Processes Governing Online Speech, 131 Harvard Law Review 1598, 1643–44 (2018)Google Scholar.

19 See Rothschild, supra note 4 (manuscript at 3).

20 See Blackman, supra note 16, at 638. Lee Epstein and Eric Posner maintain that even before Barrett's appointment, the Roberts Court was already ruling “in favor of religious organizations, including mainstream Christian organizations, more frequently than its predecessors,” and they predict that her appointment “may accelerate” this “trend.” Lee Epstein and Eric A. Posner, The Roberts Court and the Transformation of Constitutional Protections for Religion: A Statistical Portrait, Supreme Court Review (forthcoming) (manuscript at 18), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3825759.

21 Rothschild, supra note 4 (manuscript at 44).

22 Wright, R. George, Free Exercise and the Public Interest After Tandon v. Newsom, 2021 University of Illinois Law Review Online 189, 194Google Scholar.

23 Howard Kislowicz, Judging Religion and Judges’ Religions, 33 Journal of Law & Religion 42, 47 (2018) (citation omitted).

24 See Lilliana Mason, Uncivil Agreement: How Politics Became Our Identity 14 (2018).

25 Lawrence Wright, The Plague Year: America in the Time of Covid 85 (2021).

26 Cf. Wright, supra note 22, at 194 (noting that “normative judgments” about restrictions to mitigate the spread of COVID-19 “must be made in the context of a culture that has been increasingly fracturing, if not fragmenting, on relevant moral and political issues, for decades”).

27 See Hill, supra note 8, at 3. For more on proportionality analysis and the COVID-19 epidemic worldwide, see generally Guo, supra note 8.

28 Yowell, supra note 12, at 9. See also id. at 16; Greene, supra note 11, at 58.

29 Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 17).

30 Yowell, supra note 12, at 15.

31 Id. at 16.

32 Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 17). See also Greene, supra note 11, at 59 (observing that “[t]ypical proportionality formulations comprise either three or four ordered steps in the analysis”).

33 Paul Yowell observes that “[i]n strict scrutiny, courts ask whether there are less restrictive alternatives in determining whether the government measure is ‘narrowly tailored’—similarly to the necessity component of the European proportionality inquiry, which is sometimes phrased in terms of ‘minimal impairment.’” Yowell, supra note 12, at 23.

34 Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 21).

35 See, e.g., George Androutsopoulos, The Right of Religious Freedom in Light of the Coronavirus Pandemic: The Greek Case, 10 Laws 1 (2021) (Greece); Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 34–38) (Canada); id. at 39–40 (Germany); Fornerod, Anne, Freedom of Worship during a Public Health State of Emergency in France, 10 Laws 1 (2021) (France)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Martínez-Torrón, supra note 8, at 12 (Scotland).

36 See, e.g., Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 25) (noting French Council of State's “rulings in favor of religious claimants”); id. at 39 (discussing a ruling by the German Federal Constitutional Court that certain COVID-19–related restrictions were not disproportionate).

37 Cf. Martínez-Torrón, supra note 8, at 11 (noting that “within the same country, the courts’ approach has sometimes changed depending on the moment that the claim was decided”).

38 On the French Council of State, see, for example, Fornerod, supra note 35, at 3. On the German Federal Constitutional Court, see Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 39–40).

39 Hill, supra note 8, at 4. Courts applying the proportionality test under the case law of the European Court of Human Rights would also need to consider the margin of appreciation doctrine. For more on that doctrine, see, for example, Jim Murdoch, Protecting the Right to Freedom of Conscience under the European Convention on Human Rights 41–43 (2012), at https://www.echr.coe.int/LibraryDocs/Murdoch2012_EN.pdf.

40 A debate exists on how much role balancing as such should have in proportionality analysis, see Greene, supra note 11, at 58, and as I explain in the text, courts frequently skip the final step of the analysis. But balancing is formally a fundamental part of the test, and even the “necessity” step can involve balancing, as courts try to determine whether the marginal benefit of a restriction, in terms of the legislature's stated aim, outweighs the damage to a claimant's rights. See Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 21).

41 [2021] CSOH 32.

42 Id. ¶ 127; see also id. ¶ 90 (quoting Article 9).

43 Id. ¶¶ 16–17.

44 Id. ¶ 17.

45 Id. ¶ 19.

46 Id. ¶ 96.

47 Id. ¶ 100.

48 Id. ¶ 101.

49 Id. ¶ 102.

50 Id. ¶ 112.

51 Id. ¶ 114.

52 See id.

53 Id. ¶ 115.

54 Id. ¶ 106.

55 Id. ¶ 111.

56 Id.

57 Id.

58 Id. ¶ 118.

59 Id. ¶ 119.

60 Id.

61 See id. ¶ 125.

62 Id. Debates about which activities were “essential” also took place in other countries applying the proportionality test. Martínez-Torrón, supra note 8, at 6 (Spain and Brazil).

63 See Philip et al., [2021] CSOH 32 ¶ 121.

64 See id. ¶ 123.

65 Id. ¶ 121; id. ¶ 62 (“worship-lite”).

66 Id. ¶ 126.

67 For an interesting discussion of why public-health professionals might systematically undervalue religious viewpoints when making decisions, see Drakeman, Donald L., Some Second Thoughts about the Humanities, 56 Zygon 732, 736–39 (2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar (book review). “At present,” Drakeman observes, “many of the most influential public health professionals are consciously ignoring religiously based input.” Id. at 739.

68 Cass R. Sunstein, Our Anti-Korematsu, Harvard Public Law Working Paper No. 21–21 (manuscript at 5) (2020), at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3756853.

69 Philip et al., [2021] CSOH 32 ¶ 123. Martínez-Torrón observes that religious communities were especially deferential to government restrictions early in the crisis, but less so as time passed. Martínez-Torrón, supra note 8, at 9–11.

70 See, e.g., Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 28–29).

71 See id. (manuscript at 3–4).

72 Kislowicz, supra note 23, at 47 (citation omitted).

73 494 U.S. 872, 879–82 (1990).

74 See Kent Greenawalt, 1 Religion and the Constitution 31 (2006).

75 See Fallon, Richard H. Jr., Strict Judicial Scrutiny, 54 UCLA Law Review 1267, 1269 (2007)Google Scholar.

76 See Michael W. McConnell et al., Religion and the Constitution 115 (4th ed. 2016).

77 See id.

78 See Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 14) (arguing that Smith “openly and energetically eschewed any meaningful form of interest-balancing”); see also McConnell et al., supra note 76, at 146; Kent Greenawalt, Religion and the Rehnquist Court, 99 Northwestern University Law Review 145, 152–53 (2004).

79 See Jiwoon Kong, Note, Safeguarding the Free Exercise of Religion during the COVID-19 Pandemic, 89 Fordham Law Review 1589, 1609 (2021).

80 See Sunstein, supra note 68, at 5–6 (“‘selective sympathy and indifference’”) (citation omitted). On one possible example of hostility, see Agudath Israel of America v. Cuomo, 980 F.3d 222, 229 (2nd Cir. 2020) (Park, J., dissenting) (discussing New York Governor Andrew Cuomo's remarks about ultra-Orthodox Jews).

81 See Soos v. Cuomo, 470 F.Supp.3d 268, 276 (N.D.N.Y. 2020).

82 See Note, Constitutional Constraints, supra note 7, at 1788.

83 See id. at 1785; cf. James M. Oleske, Jr., Free Exercise (Dis)honesty, 2019 Wisconsin Law Review 689, 691 (noting that “inconsistencies and uncertainties have plagued the Court's free exercise jurisprudence for decades”).

84 Blackman, supra note 16, at 686.

85 South Bay United Pentecostal Church v. Newsom (South Bay I), 140 S. Ct. 1613, 1613 (2020) (Roberts, C.J., concurring in denial of application for injunctive relief).

86 See Blackman, supra note 16, at 681–82; see also Jim Oleske, Tandon Steals Fulton's Thunder: The Most Important Free Exercise Decision Since 1990, SCOTUSblog, April 15, 2021, https://www.scotusblog.com/2021/04/tandon-steals-fultons-thunder-the-most-important-free-exercise-decision-since-1990/ (discussing the Court's disposition of emergency “challenges to COVID limits”). On the shadow docket generally, “a range of orders and summary decisions that defy [the Court's] normal procedural regularity,” see Baude, William, Foreword: The Supreme Court's Shadow Docket, 9 N.Y.U. Journal of Law & Liberty 1, 1 (2015)Google Scholar.

87 Rothschild, Zalman, Free Exercise's Lingering Ambiguity, 11 California Law Review Online 282, 289–90 (2020)Google Scholar. This is so even though the justices “did not directly engage” with Smith. Id. at 289.

88 South Bay I, 140 S. Ct. at 1613 (Roberts, C.J.).

89 Id.

90 Id. at 1614 (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting from denial of application for injunctive relief).

91 Calvary Chapel v. Sisolak, 140 S. Ct. 2603 (2020).

92 Id. at 2605 (Alito, J., dissenting from denial of application for injunctive relief).

93 Roman Catholic Diocese of Brooklyn v. Cuomo, 141 S. Ct. 63 (2020) (per curiam).

94 Id. at 66.

95 Id. at 69 (Gorsuch, J., concurring).

96 Id. at 79 (Sotomayor, J., dissenting).

97 Id. at 80.

98 South Bay Pentecostal Church v. Newsom (South Bay II), 141 S. Ct. 716 (2021). The majority declined to enjoin other restrictions, in part because the record was not sufficiently clear. See id. at 717 (Barrett, J., concurring in the partial grant of application for injunctive relief).

99 Id. at 717 (Statement of Gorsuch, J.).

100 Id. at 720 (Kagan. J., dissenting).

101 141 S. Ct. 1294 (2021) (per curiam).

102 Id. at 1297.

103 Id. at 1298 (Kagan, J., dissenting).

104 Sunstein, supra note 68, at 14.

105 Id. at 3; see also id. at 14. Questions about whether permitted nonreligious gatherings were comparable to prohibited religious gatherings occupied courts outside the United States as well. See Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 25–27).

106 See Elim Romanian Pentecostal Church v. Pritzker, 962 F.3d 341, 346 (7th Cir. 2020) (“[i]t would be foolish to pretend that worship services are exactly like any of the possible comparisons”); see also Rothschild, supra note 4 (manuscript at 45 & n.222).

107 Questions about how much deference to give public health authorities occupied courts outside the United States as well. See Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 34–40).

108 Cf. Rothschild, supra note 4 (manuscript at 47) (arguing that “the real constitutional question” that divided the justices in South Bay I “was whether it could be said that California was discriminating against religion by having different standards for church gatherings and certain secular gatherings”).

109 Note, Constitutional Constraints, supra note 7, at 1790; see also Blackman, supra note 16, at 686.

110 Greene, supra note 11, at 57.

111 Id.

112 Compare McConnell et al., supra note 76, at 115 (strict scrutiny), with Yowell, supra note 12, at 16 (proportionality).

113 See Oleske, supra note 83, at 740–41.

114 Collings and Barclay, supra note 11 (manuscript at 21).

115 On the similarity between the two tests generally, see Yowell, supra note 12, at 20–21.

116 Cf. id. at 23 (arguing generally for the similarity of the least-restrictive means and necessity requirements).

117 Reverend Dr William J U Philip and Others, [2021] CSOH 32, ¶ 100.

118 Fallon, supra note 75, at 1272; see also Helfand, Michael A., Religious Institutionalism, Implied Consent, and the Value of Voluntarism, 88 Southern California Law Review 539, 581 (2015)Google Scholar; Sepinwall, Amy J., Conscience and Complicity: Assessing Pleas for Religious Exemptions in Hobby Lobby's Wake, 82 University of Chicago Law Review 1897, 1907 (2015)Google Scholar.

119 Fallon, supra note 75, at 1272.

120 South Bay II, 141 S. Ct. 716 (2021).

121 Id. at 717 (Statement of Gorsuch, J.). Justices Thomas and Alito joined Gorsuch's statement in full. Justices Barrett and Kavanaugh agreed with Gorsuch's analysis of the ban on indoor worship but disagreed with his conclusion that California's ban on singing during indoor services also violated the First Amendment, because, in their view, the record on that question was unclear. Id. (Barrett, J., concurring in the partial grant of application for injunctive relief).

122 Id. at 718 (Statement of Gorsuch, J.).

123 See id.

124 Id. at 718–19.

125 Id. at 719, 720.

126 Id. at 718.

127 Id. at 720.

128 Id. at 723 (Kagan, J., dissenting).

129 See supra text accompanying note 64 (discussing Philip et al.), text accompanying note 69 (same).

130 South Bay II, 141 S. Ct. at 721 (Kagan, J., dissenting).

131 Id.

132 Id. at 723.

133 Id.

134 Cf. Caroline Mala Corbin, Religious Liberty in a Pandemic, 70 Duke Law Journal Online 1, 27 (2020) (noting that a court's rigorousness in applying strict scrutiny might “depend on its assessment of the gravity of the pandemic”).

135 On similarities between proportionality and strict scrutiny generally, see Yowell, supra note 12, at 9, 20–21.

136 See Paul Horwitz, The Lobby, Hobby Moment, 128 Harvard Law Review 154, 158–59 (2014)Google Scholar (noting how the cultural consensus in favor of religious accommodations has dissolved and the effect this has had on legal decisions).

137 See Mark Storslee, The COVID-19 Church-Closure Cases and the Free Exercise of Religion, 37 Journal of Law & Religion (this issue) (observing that “(the COVID-19–related cases) further aggravated an already politicized debate about the Free Exercise Clause”).

138 Storslee, Mark, Religious Accommodation, the Establishment Clause, and Third-Party Harm, 86 University of Chicago Law Review 871, 937 (2019)Google Scholar.

139 Cf. Braman, Donald & Kahan, Dan M., Legal Realism as Psychological and Cultural (Not Political) Realism, in How Law Knows 93, 114 (Sarat, Austin et al. , eds., 2007)Google Scholar (observing that where “values and norms” are “widely shared,” most judges “will find no difficulty reaching agreement”).

140 See id. at 103 (observing that “in cases that are the focus of competition between cultural groups in society at large . . . the evidence suggests that cultural cognition leads [judges] in different directions”).

141 Kislowicz, supra note 23, at 42.

142 Brownstein, Alan, Continuing the Constitutional Dialogue: A Discussion of Justice Stevens's Establishment Clause and Free Exercise Jurisprudence, 106 Northwestern University Law Review 605, 638 (2012)Google Scholar.

143 On how professional experience and training may diminish the effects of judges’ political and ideological commitments, see Kahan et al., supra note 18, at 354–55.

144 Andrew Koppelman, Neutrality and the Religion Analogy, in Religious Exemptions 165, 165 (Kevin Vallier & Michael Weber, eds., 2018).

145 See, e.g., Mason, supra note 24, at 14, 33, 37.

146 See Movsesian, Mark L., Cakeshop, Masterpiece and the Future of Religious Freedom, 42 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 711, 747–48 (2019)Google Scholar; see also Sisk and Heise, supra note 18, at 1205, 1233–36.

147 See, e.g., Pew Research Center, Faith among Black Americans 120 (Feb. 16, 2021) (“Black adults from all religious backgrounds are strongly Democratic.”); Frank Newport, The Religious Left Has a Numbers Problem, Gallup's Polling Matters, June 4, 2019, https://news.gallup.com/opinion/polling-matters/258032/religious-left-numbers-problem.aspx (noting the comparatively weak “influence of the religious left within the Democratic party”) (emphasis omitted).

148 In a recent study, Epstein and Posner maintain that the Roberts Court's greater solicitude for religious organizations “largely” results from “the appointment by Republican presidents of Supreme Court justices who favor religious rights and liberties.” Epstein and Posner, supra note 20 (manuscript at 4).

149 Neal Devins and Lawrence Baum, The Company They Keep: How Partisan Divisions Came to the Supreme Court 13 (2019).

150 Id. at 121. But cf. Perino, Michael A., Law, Ideology, and Strategy in Judicial Decision Making: Evidence from Securities Fraud Actions, 3 Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 497, 508 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar (noting that with respect to lower-court appointments, “Presidents frequently use their nominating powers to push partisan or personal, rather than ideological, agendas”) (citation omitted).

151 See Devins and Baum, supra note 149, at 112 (noting the “more pronounced” divisions among elites than exist “in the general population”); id. at 117 (noting “the emergence of distinct career paths for conservatives and liberals” among legal elites).

152 Storslee, supra note 138, at 937.

153 Cf. Sisk and Heise, supra note 18, at 1238 (observing that partisan differences have also begun to “percolat[e]” into the Court's Establishment Clause jurisprudence).

154 Rothschild, supra note 4 (manuscript at 3).

155 Id.

156 Id. (manuscript at 43–44).

157 See Blackman, supra note 16, at 638.

158 On the United States’ culture wars generally, see James Davison Hunter, Culture Wars: The Struggle to Define America (1992).

159 See Wright, supra note 22, at 194. In the Establishment Clause context, Micah Schwartzman and Nelson Tebbe have identified what they describe as a pattern of “appeasement” by progressive justices, who offer conservative justices “unilateral concessions for the purpose of avoiding further conflict.” Micah Schwartzman and Nelson Tebbe, Establishment Clause Appeasement, 2019 Supreme Court Review 271, 272. Whatever the situation in the Establishment Clause context, such a pattern has not appeared so far in the COVID-19–related cases.

160 Martínez-Torrón, supra note 8, at 2.

161 Id.

162 Id.