Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-20T13:42:22.143Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Injustice of Enforced Equal Access to Transplant Operations: Rethinking Reckless Claims of Fairness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

This essay does not directly address organ transplantation or even issues of justice, fairness, or equality in access to organs for transplantation. Instead, it engages a higher-order question: the justice of coercively and globally imposing any particular contentfull view of justice, fairness, and/or equality (i.e., a view grounded in a particular ranking of primary human goods and/or right-making conditions) under circumstances that would violate peaceable, consensual choice. It is argued that state coercion, as in the prohibition of the sale of organs or the coercive imposition of equal access to transplantations or health care, is unjust when there are insufficient grounds to establish with certainty the canonical normative character of the particular account of justice, fairness, or equality, as well as the warrant for the use of coercive force to impose such an account.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

In this essay, “coercion” is used to identify the unjustified use of force to place a person in a state to which he does not consent. Coercion is to be contrasted with manipulation, which identifies the peaceable offering of a benefit to which the person benefiting has no claim. This benefit induces that person to consent to being in a state into which he would not enter, were it not for the offer of this benefit. For two explorations of the difference between coercion and manipulation, see Nozick, R., “Coercion,” in Morgenbesser, S. et al., eds., Philosophy, Science, and Method (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1969): 440–72; see also Rudinow, J., “Manipulation,” Ethics 88 (1978): 338-47.Google Scholar
Not only does the American Constitution set significant barriers against majoritarian tyrannies, but Anglo-American constitutional history, with its recognition of the rights of Englishmen, sets boundaries that are accepted as background that limit conditions on legislation. For example, though there is no constitutional prohibition (although membership in the European Union has complicated matters) against establishing by law an inquisition to fight heresy in the United Kingdom, the background constitutional history recognizes this as improper. For an account of the cultural commitments that framed British restraint in order to establish a limited constitutional monarchy in the absence of a written constitution, see the account given by A. V. Dicey (1835–1922). Dicey, A. V., Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1982).Google Scholar
This essay does not address or explore those areas of human interaction where seemingly innocent persons can, in fact, be aggressors, such as when an individual decides against a vaccination that can put others at unconsented-to risks, as in a pandemic.Google Scholar
The presence of robust moral diversity has not only defined the past but our present as well. See, for example, Hunter, J. D., Culture Wars: The Struggle to Define America (New York: Basic Books, 1991) and Huntington, S. P., The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order (New York: Touchstone, 1996).Google Scholar
The difficulty of establishing the priority of the right over the good as well as of morality over prudent rationality was recognized by Kant, Kant. I., trans. Kemp Smith, N., Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (London: Macmillan, 1964): at 639, A811-B839.Google Scholar
In order dramatically to bring across the contrast between prudential rationality and moral rationality, one might consider the following choice. If one acts in one particular way, he saves himself and his family and friends from a prolonged and painful death by torture and securely wins power and financial resources. If one acts in a different fashion, he and his family and friends experience a prolonged and painful death by torture, but he must be responsible for an innocent person's painless death. Prudential rationality would dictate that one would choose the first and moral rationality the second. By invoking the postulates of pure, practical reason, Kant recognizes a deep secular irrationality in acting morally in such circumstances.Google Scholar
For an account of English culture's loss of recognition of the existence of God, see Wilson, A. N., God's Funeral (New York: W. W. Norton, 1999).Google Scholar
At the Battle of Jena on August 6, 1806, Napoleon defeated the last Western emperor, Francis II, sovereign of the Holy Roman Empire, and brought an end to the occidental Christian empire. This was among the great watersheds in history. Although some have even argued that this event marked the end of history, it constituted the high point, as well as nearly the end, of Enlightenment aspirations. For a critique of those who regard the event as marking the end of history, see Grier, P. T., “The End of History, and the Return of History,” The Owl of Minerva 21, no. 2 (Spring 1990): 131144. Depending on one's perspective, the empire in the East ended either on Tuesday, May 29, 1453, when Mohammed I defeated the last Roman Emperor Constantine XI, or with the martyrdom of St. Nicholas II, the last czar, on July 17, 1918. The result in Western Europe was the emergence of a Sozialstaat with a thick constitutional commitment to claim rights.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, R., Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989): at 59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M., “Modern Moral Philosophy,” Ethics 33 (January, 1958): 119, at 6.Google Scholar
The principle of totality was developed by Thomas Aquinas. See Summa Theologica II-II q 65, a.1. A view of this sort was even embraced by Immanuel Kant. See Metaphysical Principles of Virtue, in Königlich Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, , ed., Kants gesammelte Schriften vol. 6 (Berlin: 1907): at 423.Google Scholar
If the rich forbid competent adults to sell their organs, they exploit the poor because (1) they restrict the range of free choice open to the poor, and (2) they impose a view of proper action on the poor against their will, which may in many circumstances cause the poor to suffer more, so that the rich can feel moral satisfaction in the constraints they have imposed.Google Scholar
Clement of Alexandria, “The Stromata,” Book 2, Chapter IV, in Roberts, A. and Donaldson, J., eds., Ante-Nicene Fathers vol. 2 (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson Publishers, 1994): at 350.Google Scholar
Laertius, D., Lives of Eminent Philosophers, IX.88, and Empiricus, S., Outlines of Pyrrhonism, I.164.Google Scholar
Cherry, M. J., Kidney for Sale by Owner (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2005).Google Scholar
Taylor, J. S., Stakes and Kidneys: Why Markets in Human Body Parts Are Morally Imperative (Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2005).Google Scholar
For a defense of the existence of a moral truth accessible through noetic (a form of mystical) knowledge, see Engelhardt, H. T. Jr., The Foundations of Christian Bioethics (Lisse, the Netherlands: Swets & Zeitlinger, 2000): Chapter 4.Google Scholar
Substantively controversial claims regarding forbearance rights are for the most part associated with controversies as to whether particular individuals should be recognized as persons (e.g., as in the case of disputes with regard to the morality of abortion, as well as the killing of embryos in order to harvest embryonic stem-cell lines).Google Scholar
Though there are great variations in the character and extent of welfare rights, in all polities, there are legal prohibitions of theft, rape, and murder. Cardinal forbearance rights, not material rights, appear to be universally recognized as necessary for the rule of law (i.e., for a Rechtsstaat).Google Scholar
For an exploration of the challenges of justifying a more than minimal state, see Nozick, R., Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974). See also Engelhardt, H. T. Jr., The Foundations of Bioethics 2nd ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996): Chapters 1–4.Google Scholar
In this essay, the term moral stranger is used to identify persons who previously do not either (1) possess in common sufficient basic premises and rules of evidence to solve their controversies through sound rational argument, or (2) acknowledge a person or institution in authority to resolve their disputes. For a further analysis of this use of moral stranger, see Engelhardt, supra note 17, at 6–9 and 69–84.Google Scholar
Hegel correctly understands that persons exist in the world as embodied beings. First and foremost, they own themselves, their conceptual innovations, and those objects that they transform by bringing them within their power. In the face of disputes with regard to what should count as morally defensible holdings in property, persons must be presumed to be rightful owners of what they possess under the law until proven otherwise. After all, possession is indeed something like 9/10ths of the law. Second, one must note that whatever difficulties beset private ownership also plague claims of corporate and state ownership. For a further discussion of some of these issues, see id., at 154–162. See also Hegel, G. W. F., Philosophy of Right, § 39–71. As Hegel correctly stresses, property is the embodiment of personality. See § 51.Google Scholar
What is advanced here is not intended to provide a comprehensive, historical presentation of American constitutional history. The claim is much more modest – namely, to place the phenomenon of the American Constitution within the recognition of the moral limits of secular, political authority.Google Scholar
The American Revolution and the writing of the American Constitution occurred prior to the French Revolution. However, the horrors of the French Revolution had a considerable impact on the framing of early American sentiments. For an account of the French Revolution's bloody actions, see Davies, M., For Altar and Throne: The Rising in the Vendée (St. Paul, MN: Remnant Press, 1998); Latreille, A., L'Eglise catholique et la révolution français 2 vols. (Paris: Hachette, 1948); Mathiez, A., Les Origines des Cultes Révolutionnaires (Geneva: Slatkine, 1904/1977); Secher, R., A French Genocide: The Vendée (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2003); and Vovelle, M., The Revolution Against the Church, trans. José, A. (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1988/1991).Google Scholar
Engelhardt, H. T. Jr., “Giving, Selling, and Having Taken: Conflicting Views of Organ Transfer,” Indiana Health Law Review 1 (2004): 3149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar