Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-qxdb6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T07:47:38.091Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Stationary reflections for uncountable cofinality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Péter Komjáth*
Affiliation:
Department of Computer Science, Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest 1088, Hungary

Extract

It was J. E. Baumgartner who in [1] proved that when a weakly compact cardinal is Lévy-collapsed to ω2 the new ω2 inherits some of the large cardinal properties; e.g. if S is a stationary set of ω-limits in ω2 then for some α < ω2, Sα is stationary in α. Later S. Shelah extended this to the following theorem: if a supercompact cardinal κ is Lévy-collapsed to ω2, then in the resulting model the following holds: if Sλ is a stationary set of ω-limits and cf(λ) ≥ ω2 then there is an α. < λ such that Sα is stationary in α, i.e. stationary reflection holds for countable cofinality (see [1] and [3]). These theorems are important prototypes of small cardinal compactness theorems; many applications and generalizations can be found in the literature. One might think that these results are true for sets with an uncountable cofinality μ as well, i.e. when an appropriate large cardinal is collapsed to μ++. Though this is true for Baumgartner's theorem, there remains a problem with Shelah's result. The point is that the lemma stating that a stationary set of ω-limits remains stationary after forcing with an ω2-closed partial order may be false in the case of μ-limits in a cardinal of the form λ+ with cf(λ) < μ, as was shown in [8] by Shelah. The problem has recently been solved by Baumgartner, who observed that if a universal box-sequence on the class of those ordinals with cofinality ≤ μ exists, the lemma still holds, and a universal box-sequence of the above type can be added without destroying supercompact cardinals beyond μ.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[1]Baumgartner, J. E., A new class of order types, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 9 (1976), pp. 187222.Google Scholar
[2]Baumgartner, J. E., unpublished manuscript on stationary reflection.Google Scholar
[3]Ben-David, S., On Shelah's compactness of cardinals, Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 31 (1978), pp. 3456.Google Scholar
[4]Jech, T., Set theory, Academic Press, New York, 1978.Google Scholar
[5]Komjáth, P., Miller's theorem revisited (to appear).Google Scholar
[6]Magidor, M., Reflecting stationary sets, this Journal, vol. 47 (1982), pp. 755771.Google Scholar
[7]Menas, T. K., Consistency results concerning supercompactness, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 223 (1976), pp. 6191.Google Scholar
[8]Shelah, S., Successors of singular cardinals, Logic Colloquium '78, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1979, pp. 357380.Google Scholar
[9]Solovay, R. M., Reinhardt, W. N. and Kanamori, A., Strong axioms of infinity and elementary embeddings, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 13 (1978), pp. 73116.Google Scholar