Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-14T17:24:32.431Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Morality Influences How People Apply the Ignorance of the Law Defense

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Abstract

In four empirical studies, we showed that laypeople apply the ignorance of the law defense differently depending on the perceived morality of the defendant's course of conduct at the time of the illegal act. Moral and neutral defendants who pled ignorance of the law were afforded leniency, whereas immoral defendants were sentenced as though they were not ignorant, even when defendants in all three conditions violated identical laws. These findings suggest that laypeople adopt a just deserts approach to criminal law, which influences their responsiveness to a criminal defendant's claim to be ignorant of the law. We discuss the implications of these findings for criminal law and argue that legal doctrine should reflect laypeople's moral intuitions.

Type
Articles of General Interest
Copyright
© 2007 Law and Society Association.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

We thank James Chu, Natasha Fedotova, and Manish Pakrashi for their assistance in conducting this research. The third author would also like to thank the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences for its support and hospitality during the year in which this article was written.

References

References

Alter, Adam L., et al. (2007) “Transgression Wrongfulness Outweighs Its Harmfulness as a Determinant of Sentence Severity,” 31 Law and Human Behavior 319–35.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Baron, R. M., & Kenny, D. A. (1986) “The Moderator-Mediator Variable Distinction in Social Psychological Research: Conceptual, Strategic, and Statistical Considerations,” 51 J. of Personality and Social Psychology 1173–82.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carlsmith, Kevin M., et al. (2002) “Why Do We Punish? Deterrence and Just Deserts as Motives for Punishment,” 83 J. of Personality and Social Psychology 284–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coffee, John C. Jr. (1991) “Does “Unlawful” Mean ‘Criminal’? Reflections on the Disappearing Tort/Crime Distinction in American Law,” 71 Boston University Law Rev. 193.Google Scholar
Darley, John M., et al. (2000) “Incapacitation and Just Deserts as Motives for Punishment,” 24 Law and Human Behavior 659–83.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davies, Sharon L. (1998) “The Jurisprudence of Willfulness: An Evolving Theory of Excusable Ignorance,” 48 Duke Law J. 341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald M. (1986) Law's Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press.Google Scholar
Finkel, Norman J. (2001) Not Fair! The Typology of Commonsense Unfairness. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, Erich (2003) “Flouting and Contempt for the Law.” Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1958) “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” 71 Harvard Law Rev. 593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, Henry M. Jr. (1958) “The Aims of the Criminal Law,” 23 Law & Contemporary Problems 401–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holmes, Oliver W. Jr. (1881) The Common Law. Cambridge, MA: Little, Brown.Google Scholar
Kahan, Dan M. (1997) “Ignorance of the Law Is an Excuse—but Only for the Virtuous,” 96 Michigan Law Rev. 127–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monin, Benoît, & Miller, Dale T. (2001) “Moral Credentials and the Expression of Prejudice,” 81 J. of Personality and Social Psychology 3343.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nadler, Janice (2005) “Flouting the Law,” 83 Texas Law J. 1399–441.Google Scholar
Nisbett, Richard E., & Wilson, Timothy D. (1977) “The Halo Effect: Evidence for the Unconscious Alteration of Judgments,” 35 J. of Personality and Social Psychology 450–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Packer, Herbert L. (1968) The Limits of the Criminal Sanction. Stanford, CA: Stanford Univ. Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parry, John T. (1997) “Culpability, Mistake, and Official Interpretations of Law,” 25 American J. of Criminal Law 178.Google Scholar
Robbins, Ira P. (1990) “The Ostrich Instruction: Deliberate Ignorance as a Criminal Mens Rea,” 81 J. of Criminal Law and Criminology 191234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Paul H., & Darley, John M. (1997) “The Utility of Desert,” 91 Northwestern University Law Rev. 453–99.Google Scholar
Robinson, Paul H., & Darley, John M. (1998) “Objectivist versus Subjectivist Views of Criminality: A Study in the Role of Social Science in Criminal Law Theory,” 18 Oxford J. of Legal Studies 409–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segev, Re'em (2006) “Justification, Rationality, and Mistake: Mistake of Law Is No Excuse? It Might Be a Justification!,” 25 Law and Philosophy 3179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiley, John S. (1999) “Not Guilty by Reason of Blamelessness: Culpability in Federal Criminal Interpretation,” 85 Virginia Law Rev. 1021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Cases Cited

Cheek v. United States, 498 U.S. 192 (1991).Google Scholar
Liparota v. United States, 471 U.S. 419 (1985).Google Scholar
Ratzlaf v. United States, 510 U.S. 135 (1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Staples v. United States, 511 U.S. 600 (1994).Google Scholar
United States v. Int'l Minerals & Chem. Corp., 402 U.S. 558 (1971).Google Scholar
United States v. Jewell, 532 F.2d 697 (9th Cir. 1976).Google Scholar
United States v. Murdock, 290 U.S. 389 (1933).Google Scholar
United States v. X-Citement Video, 513 U.S. 64 (1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar