Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-v5vhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-16T10:01:00.815Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Aquinas’ Fifth Way

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

John Owens*
Affiliation:
Good Shepherd College, Auckland, New Zealand

Abstract

Aquinas’ fifth way for demonstrating the existence of God shows a confidence in its argument that is not generally shared by the contemporary reader. Natural entities that lack awareness (or perhaps self-awareness) act in an end-directed manner; this implies a fundamental relation to goals they do not consciously choose; this in turn points to the existence of a governing mind. The article tries to make sense of this argument against the background of philosophical naturalism that is assumed by much contemporary thought. It addresses the question of what kinds of end-directed activity fall under the scope of the argument, and why Aquinas thinks that these imply a governing mind. The article notes the unusual structure of the argument, suggesting that it should be understood (as should all of the five ways) as an attempt to wake the reader up to something so fundamental that it is usually overlooked. The main difficulty for the contemporary reader is to recover an Aristotelian sense of what it means for something to exist. If readers can achieve this, they may come to appreciate why an argument that seems enormously controversial in the present day seemed reasonably obvious to Aquinas.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2020 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 “But God, Who is at the summit of perfection, does not agree with any other being, not only in species but not even in genus, nor in any other universal predicate.” De Spirit. Creat. VIII. Aquinas, Thomas, On Spiritual Creatures, trans. FitzPatrick, Mary C. in collaboration with Wellmuth, John J. (Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 1949), 92Google Scholar.

2 “The fifth way is based on the guidedness of nature. An orderedness of actions to an end is observed in all bodies obeying natural laws (corpora naturalia), even when they lack awareness (cognitione carent). For their behaviour hardly ever varies, and will practically always turn out well (optimum); which shows that they truly tend (ex intentione) to a goal, and do not merely hit it by accident. Nothing however that lacks awareness (quae non habent cognitionem) tends to a goal, except under the direction of someone with awareness and with understanding (ab aliquo cognoscente et intelligente); the arrow, for example, requires an archer. Everything in nature (omnes res naturales), therefore, is directed to its goal by someone with understanding (intelligens), and this we call ‘God’.” 1a, 2, 3. Aquinas, St. Thomas, Summa Theologiae, Vol. 2, Existence and Nature of God, trans. McDermott, Timothy O.P. (London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1964), 16-17Google Scholar.

3 Richard Connell describes the five ways as “sketches,” and points to a failure in some authors to “read anything more than the arguments in the Summa.” Connell, Richard J., “Preliminaries to the Five Ways,” Thomistic Papers IV, ed. Kennedy, Leonard A. C.S.B. (Houston, Texas: Center for Thomistic Studies, 1988), 129-168, 131-2Google Scholar.

4 Other English translations cope by translating cognitio as “intelligence” at the start of the argument, and as “knowledge” at the end, when Aquinas introduces the phrase ab aliquo cognoscente et intelligente. For a recent example, see Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Questions on God, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, ed. Brian Davies and Brian Leftow (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 26.

5 In their commentary on the First Way, Heather and James McRae make the general point that the demonstration is aimed at the believer rather than the unbeliever. “(T)he question is not ‘will this argument convert an atheist?’” McRae, Heather Thornton and McRae, James, “A Motion to Reconsider: A Defense of Aquinas’ Prime Mover Argument,” in Revisiting Aquinas’ Proofs for the Existence of God, ed. Arp, Robert (Leiden: Brill, 2016), 29-47, 44CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Commentary On Aristotle's Physics, Bk. II, L. 13, Par. 259.

7 William Newton includes “the moon revolves in a regular path around the earth” as evidence of end-directed natural activity. He argues that multi-entity “chance” happenings can reflect an original end-directedness, in that each part has its regular way of acting. Cf. Newton, William, “A Case of Mistaken Identity: Aquinas's Fifth Way and Arguments of Intelligent Design,” New Blackfriars, Vol. 96, 2014, 569-578, 572CrossRefGoogle Scholar. But the phenomenon referred to can surely be explained without appeal to end-directedness, at least for a contemporary mind. Aristotle's discussions of teleology do not usually refer to “external” or “accidental” teleology, where something is directed to the good of something else.

8 For example, in a book that criticizes the notion of miracles, Dawkins sets out to show that reality, understood as “the facts of the real world as understood through the methods of science” is nonetheless “magical.” Dawkins, Richard, The Magic of Reality (London: Black Swan, 2012), 21Google Scholar.

9 Stevenson, R. L., Travels With A Donkey In The Cevennes (London: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1925), 43Google Scholar.

10 “(E)very act is fitted to the subject whose act it is. Necessarily, then, different subjects of movement are moved differently, even with respect to a motion by the one movent.” 1a, 103, 5 ad 2. Aquinas, St Thomas, Summa Theologiae, Vol. 14, Divine Government, trans. O'Brien, T. C. (London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1975), 23Google Scholar.

11 Ibid.

12 Aristotle, Phys. 199b32. Aquinas Commentary On Aristotle's Physics, II, 14, n.8.

13 Gotthelf, Allan, Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle's Biology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 27CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 “All created things, therefore, stand in relation to God as products of art to the artist.” SCG II, 24. Aquinas, Thomas, Contra Gentiles, On the Truth of the Catholic Faith, Vol. II, trans. Anderson, James F. (South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975), 72Google Scholar.

15 Steve Grand's statement is much quoted: “Matter flows from place to place, and momentarily comes together to be you.” Grand, Steve, Creation: Life and How to Make It (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 2000), 30Google Scholar. (Grand himself does not in fact interpret the statement in a reductionist way).

16 Aristotle, On Coming-To-Be and Passing-Away, I, i, 314b7-8. See Aristotle, , “On Coming-To-Be and Passing-Away,” in Aristotle: On Sophistical Refutations; On Coming-To-Be and Passing-Away; On The Cosmos, trans. Forster, E. S. and Furley, D. J. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1955), 159-329, 167Google Scholar.

17 On the Soul, 415b14.

18 “(A) bedstead or a garment or the like, in the capacity which is signified by its name and in so far as it is craft-work, has within itself no such inherent trend towards change, though owing to the fact of its being composed of earth or stone or some mixture of substances, it incidentally has within itself the principles of change which inhere primarily in these materials.” Phys. II, i, 192b16-20. Aristotle, , Physics: Books 1-4, trans. Wicksteed, Philip H. and Cornford, Francis M. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957), 107-9Google Scholar.

19 On the Soul, 415b1-10.

20 1a, 44, 3. Aquinas, St. Thomas, Summa Theologiae, Vol. 8, Creation, Variety and Evil, trans. Gilby, Thomas O. P. (London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1967), 17Google Scholar.

21 “The natural necessity inherent in things that are fixed on one set course is itself an imprint, as it were, from God's guidance of them to their end, even as the trueness of the arrow's flight towards the target is an imprint from the archer and not from the arrow itself…” Ia, 103, 1 ad 3. Aquinas, Divine Government, 7.

22 On Coming-To-Be and Passing-Away, I, i, 314b7-8. Aristotle, Aristotle: On Sophistical Refutations; On Coming-To-Be and Passing-Away; On The Cosmos, 167.

23 1a, 103, 5. Aquinas, Divine Government, 21.

24 1a, 103, 5 ad 1. Aquinas, Divine Government, 23.

25 1a, 103, 5 ad 1. The ‘Summa Theologica’ of St. Thomas Aquinas, Part 1, 3rd Number, QQ. LXXV-CXIX, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (London: R. & T. Washbourne, 1912), 374.

26 1a, 103, 7. Aquinas, Divine Government, 29. Aristotle has a similar, though more restricted statement, in talking of the theory of Empedocles: “the theory does away with the whole order of Nature, and indeed with Nature's self.” Phys. II, viii, 199b15. Aristotle, Physics: Books 1-4, 177.

27 C. S. Lewis, A Grief Observed (London: Faber and Faber, 1961), 25.

28 The philosophical biologist Michael Ghiselin holds that Darwin inaugurated a new ontology, where “(i)ndividuals, not classes, were the ultimate reality.” He notes that this shows “the rejection of essentialism” and implies that “essences shall not be treated as ideas in the mind of God…” Ghiselin, Michael T., “The Darwinian Revolution as Viewed by a Philosophical Biologist,” Journal of the History of Biology, Vol. 38, 2005, 123-136, 127, 131CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

29 Lewis, A Grief Observed, 25-26.

30 Taylor, Richard, “The Case for Materialism,” in Philosophy: Contemporary Perspectives on Perennial Issues, ed. Klemke, E. D., Kline, A. David, and Hollinger, Robert (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1994), 179-89Google Scholar.

31 “My central thesis, is, first, that we are our bodies – there is no additional metaphysical element such as a mind or soul or spirit. But … this ‘physicalist’ position need not deny that we are intelligent, moral, and spiritual. We are, at our best, complex physical organisms, imbued with the legacy of thousands of years of culture, and, most importantly, blown by the Breath of God's Spirit; we are Spirited bodies.” Murphy, Nancey, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), ixCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Fichte, J. G., “On the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World-Governance,” in J. G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (1798-1800), trans. Bowman, Curtis, eds. Estes, Yolanda and Bowman, Curtis (Ashgate, Burlington, VT, 2010), 21-29, 27Google Scholar.