Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-31T13:21:58.446Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Problem of Micro-Explanation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

T.R. Girill*
Affiliation:
Lawrence University

Extract

A scientific explanation is prima facie micro-reductive if the explanans refers to the behavior or properties of the micro-parts of something mentioned in the explanandum. Entity x is appropriately regarded as a micro-part of y whenever the following individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions are satisfied:

  1. (i) x is spatio-temporally contained in y

  2. (ii) for any other part of y, either

    1. a) x is spatio-temporally discrete from it, or

    2. b) x and it are assigned to different “levels”, such that parts from only one level are used in any given micro-explanation,

  3. (iii) x and y. share at least one quantitative, additive property such that

    1. a) the amount of this property attributed to x is less than the amount attributed to y, and

    2. b) the former amount arithmetically contributes to the latter.

Type
Part II. Explanation
Copyright
Copyright © 1976 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Brittan, Gordon G. Jr. “Explanation and Reduction.” Journal of Philosophy 67 (1970): 446-456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Causey, Robert L. “Uniform Micro-Reductions'” Synthese 25 (1972): 176-218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleve, Fleix M. The Giants of Pre-Sophistic Greek Philosophy. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1965.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Girill, T.R. “Identity, Causality, and the Regressiveness of Micro-Explanations.” Dialectica 28 (1974): 223-238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Girill, T.R. “Micro-Parts.” Contributed Papers of the Fifth International Congress of Logic, Methodology, and the Philosophy of Science. London, Ontario, Canada: 1975.Google Scholar
Heisenberg, Werner. “Gedanken der antiken Naturphilosophie in der modernen Physik.” Die Antike: Zeitschrift fur Kunst und Kultur des klassichen Altertums 13 (1973): 118-124.Google Scholar
Heisenberg, Werner. Physics and Philosophy. New York: Harper and Row, 1958.Google Scholar
Herbert, Donald. Mr. Wizard's Science Secrets. New York: Popular Mechanics Corporation, 1952.Google Scholar
Frederic, Keffer. “The Magnetic Properties of Materials.” Scientific American 217 (1967): 228-235.Google Scholar
Livesey, Dereck L. Atomic and Nuclear Physics. Waltham, Mass.: Blaisdell Pub. Co., 1966.Google Scholar
Lucretuis, . De Rerum Natura ca. 55 B.C. . trans. Latham, R.E., Baltimore: Penguine Books, 1951.Google Scholar
Melsen, Andrew G. van. From Atomos to Atom. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1952.Google Scholar
Post, Heinz. “The Problem of Atomism.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (1975): 19-26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reitz, John R. and Milford, Frederick J. Foundations of Electromagnetic Theory. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley Pub. Co., 1960.Google Scholar
Scott, William T. The Physics of Electricity and Magnetism. New York: John Wiley, 1966.Google Scholar
Stallo, J.B. Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics. New York: Appleton and Co., 1882.Google Scholar