Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-17T10:14:00.669Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Ethics of Interpretation in Political Theory and Intellectual History

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 December 2018

Abstract

Scholars studying classic political texts face an important decision: Should these texts be read as artifacts of history or as sources for still-valid insights about politics today? Competing historical and “presentist” approaches to political thought do not have a methodological dispute—that is, a disagreement about the most effective scholarly means to an agreed-upon end. They instead have an ethical dispute about the respective value of competing activities that aim at different purposes. This article examines six ethical arguments, drawn primarily from the work of Quentin Skinner, in favor of the historical approach. It concludes that while both intellectual history and presentist theory are ethically justifiable, the best justification of the former enterprise is that it can help us achieve the purposes of the latter.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank all those who provided feedback on this piece, including those who attended presentations at Oxford, Princeton, Cornell, the National University of Singapore, and Texas A&M, as well as the editors and reviewers who have gone above and beyond the requirements of their professional duties.

References

1 Wolf, Susan, Meaning in Life and Why It Matters (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2012), 43Google Scholar. Wolf herself insists that both the locus and judgment of value must be objective, but discourse ethics allows for the substitution of intersubjective justifiability for objectivity.

2 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971),  441Google Scholar.

3 See Moriarty, Jeffrey, “Rawls, Self-Respect and the Opportunity for Meaningful Work,” Social Theory and Practice 35, no. 3 (2009): 441–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 For a book-length defense of this claim, see Veltman, Andrea, Meaningful Work (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Green, Jeffrey Edward, “On the Difference between a Pupil and a Historian of Ideas,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 6 (2012): 84110CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Baumgold, Deborah, “Political Commentary on the History of Political Theory,” American Political Science Review 75 (1981): 928–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 See Green, Political Theory as Both Philosophy and History: A Defense against Methodological Militancy,” Annual Review of Political Science 18 (2015): 425–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Easton, David, “The Decline of Modern Political Theory,” Journal of Politics 13 (1951): 42CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Gunn, J. A. W., “After Sabine, After Lovejoy: The Languages of Political Thought,” Journal of History and Politics 6 (1988): 5Google Scholar.

9 Skinner, Quentin, Visions of Politics, vol. 1, Regarding Method (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), viiGoogle Scholar.

10 Haddock, Bruce, “Contingency and Judgment in History of Political Philosophy: A Phenomenological Approach,” in Political Philosophy versus History? Contextualism and Real Politics in Contemporary Political Thought, ed. Floyd, Jonathan and Stears, Marc (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 66Google Scholar.

11 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:89.

12 When interpreting these authors, my own approach will be presentist rather than historical. While this could be criticized as viciously circular or lauded as admirably consistent, I take it mostly as proof that the sort of ethical choices I am describing are unavoidable, even in an essay about these very choices.

13 Skinner, , “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas,” History and Theory 8 (1969): 48CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Truth and Method, rev. ed., ed. Winsheimer, Joel and Marshall, Donald G. (New York: Continuum, 1989), 296Google Scholar. For a rejection of Skinner's approach as impossible for Gadamerian reasons, see Keane, John, “On the ‘New’ History: Quentin Skinner's Proposal for a New History of Political Ideology,” Telos 47 (1981): 174–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For more on the incompatibility of Gademerian and Skinnerian approaches, see Boucher, David, Texts in Contexts: Revisionist Methods for Studying the History of Ideas (Boston: Martinus Nijhoff, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, esp. 181. Skinner has sometimes attempted to incorporate Gadamer's ideas into his own hermeneutic theory, although it is not clear if this can be successful; see Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:15–16.

15 See, among many others, Bevir, Mark, “Are There Any Perennial Problems in Political Theory?,” Political Studies 42 (1994): 662–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lamb, Robert, “Quentin Skinner's Revised Historical Contextualism: A Critique,” History of the Human Sciences 22 (2009): 5173CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Paul Kelly, “Rescuing Political Theory from the Tyranny of History,” in Floyd and Stears, Political Philosophy versus History?, 13–37.

16 Hirsch, E. D., Validity in Interpretation (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1967)Google Scholar and Hirsch, , The Aims of Interpretation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976)Google Scholar. Hirsch's terminology is unfortunately misleading, since his concept of “significance” seems like a better candidate for what is colloquially meant by “meaning” (i.e., “what this means to us”) than what he calls “meaning.” For a subtler analysis of the multiple meanings of “meaning,” see Martinich, Aloysius, “Four Senses of ‘Meaning’ in the History of Ideas: Quentin Skinner's Theory of Historical Interpretation,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 3 (2009): 225–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Furthermore, if Paul Ricoeur is correct that every text contains a surplus of meaning, then there are far more ways of understanding a text than just the two described by Hirsch; see Ricoeur, , Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, ed. and trans. Thompson, John B. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:87.

18 Skinner, , “A Reply to My Critics,” in Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and His Critics, ed. Tully, James (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988), 256Google Scholar.

19 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:52–53.

20 See McFate, Sean, The Modern Mercenary: Private Armies and What They Mean for World Order (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015)Google Scholar.

21 Dworkin, Ronald, Justice for Hedgehogs (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011), 99190Google Scholar.

22 Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation, 7.

23 Nietzsche, Friedrich, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,” in Untimely Meditations, ed. and trans. Hollingdale, R. J. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983)Google Scholar.

24 Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation, 90.

25 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:65.

26 Ibid.

27 Many of the most important contributions to this literature are collected in Fischer, John Martin, ed. The Metaphysics of Death, Stanford Series in Philosophy (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar. For an application of these ideas to research ethics specifically, see Wilkinson, T. M., “Last Rights: The Ethics of Research on the Dead,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 19 (2002): 3141CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

28 Belliotti, Raymond Angelo, Posthumous Harm: Why the Dead Are Still Vulnerable (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2012), 34Google Scholar.

29 See Partridge, Ernest, “Posthumous Interests and Posthumous Respect,” Ethics 91 (1981): 243–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Taylor, James Stacey, Death, Poshumous Harm, and Bioethics (New York: Routledge, 2012), 67CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Thucydides, , History of the Peloponnesian War, trans. Warner, Rex (New York: Penguin Books, 1972), 48Google Scholar.

31 On the former point, see Kelly, “Rescuing Political Theory,” 26 and Lamb, “Quentin Skinner's Revised Historical Contextualism,” 57–58. On the latter, see Green, “On the Difference between a Pupil and a Historian of Ideas,” 107–8.

32 Skinner, , “Conventions and the Understanding of Speech Acts,” Philosophical Quarterly 20 (1970): 134CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

33 Grover, Dorothy, “Posthumous Harm,” Philosophical Quarterly 39 (1989): 353CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 Machiavelli, Niccoló, The Prince, trans. Mansfield, Harvey, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 61Google Scholar.

35 In ibid., 107–11.

36 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:53

37 Weber, Max, “Science as a Vocation,” in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. Gerth, H. and Mills, C. Wright (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946)Google Scholar.

38 Dunn, John, “The Identity of the History of Ideas,” Philosophy 43 (1968): 89CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

39 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:182.

40 Ibid., 170–71.

41 That said, there are many within the discipline of history who have made precisely this attempt. For an influential defense of “dialogical history” along these lines, see LaCapra, Dominick, Rethinking Intellectual History: Texts, Contexts, Language (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1983)Google Scholar. It is important to note that many who self-identify as historians, or are employed as such, would nonetheless qualify as presentists according to the schema of ideal types used in this essay.

42 This paragraph draws on ideas first published in my review of J. G. A. Pocock, Political Thought and History: Essays on Theory and Method in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, November 6, 2009. Available online at https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/political-thought-and-history-essays-on-theory-and-method/.

43 Applebaum, Arthur, Ethics for Adversaries: The Morality of Roles in Public and Professional Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 Butterfield, Herbert, The Whig Interpretation of History (New York: Norton, 1965), 16Google Scholar.

45 Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1903), viiiGoogle Scholar.

46 Audi, Robert, The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004), 149Google Scholar.

47 Newman, John Henry, Discourses on the Scope and Nature of University Education (Dublin: James Duffy, 1852)Google Scholar.

48 Elton, G. R., The Practice of History (London: Fontana, 1969)Google Scholar.

49 See Davison, Scott A., On the Intrinsic Value of Everything (New York: Continuum, 2012)Google Scholar.

50 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:15–21.

51 Southgate, Beverly, What Is History For? (New York: Routledge, 2005), 76Google Scholar.

52 See Seung, T. K. and Bonevac, Daniel, “Plural Values and Indeterminate Rankings,” Ethics 102 (1992):799813CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

53 Cicero, , On Duties, ed. and trans. Griffin, M. T. and Atkins, E. M. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 60Google Scholar.

54 See Frazer, Michael L., “Utopophobia as a Vocation: The Professional Ethics of Ideal and Nonideal Political Theory,” Social Philosophy and Policy 33 (2016): 175–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar, which begins with the same passage from Cicero discussed here.

55 This is not to say that all—or even most—political theory succeeds in advancing the cause of justice. The majority of it probably has no effect on real politics at all, while some of it (as will be discussed later) may actually prove deleterious. That said, activities often fail to achieve their goals, and we can separate our judgment of the value of an aim from the success of any given effort to attain it.

56 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:6.

57 Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, 75–77. It is important to note that, contrary to popular belief, Skinner has never actually been an antiquarian, at least not in Nietzsche's sense. Antiquarians, Nietzsche says, piously preserve, and hence kill and mummify, the treasures of the past. See ibid., 72–75.

58 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:88.

59 Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, 76.

60 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:88.

61 Mill, John Stuart, “Bentham,” in Utilitarianism and On Liberty: Including Essay on Bentham and Selections from the Writings of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin, ed. Warnock, Mary (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2003), 64Google Scholar.

62 Karl Popper maintained that one of the many flaws of what he called “historicism” (most of which, admittedly, bear little or no resemblance to anything Skinner would ever defend) was its tendency to exaggerate “the somewhat spectacular differences between various historical periods.” See Popper, Karl, The Poverty of Historicism (New York: Routledge, 1997), 100Google Scholar.

63 Janaway, Christopher and Alexander, Peter, “History of Philosophy: The Analytical Ideal,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society: Supplementary Volumes 62 (1988): 182Google Scholar. Melissa Lane agrees, writing that “the history of some ideas will teach contingency, while the history of other ideas will teach continuity, and if that were not so then the piecemeal emergence of the present from the past could not have been possible, as it was”; Lane, Why History of Ideas at All?,” History of European Ideas 28 (2002): 39Google Scholar. See also Lane, “Constraint, Freedom and Exemplar: History and Theory without Teleology,” in Floyd and Stears, Political Philosophy versus History?, 128–50; Lawson, Stephanie, “Political Studies and the Contextual Turn: A Methodological/Normative Critique,” Political Studies 56 (2008): 592CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and the introduction and titular essay in King, Preston, Thinking Past a Problem: Essays on the History of Ideas (Portland, OR: Frank Cass, 2000)Google Scholar.

64 Skinner, Quentin, “Some Problems in the Analysis of Political Thought and Action,” Political Theory 23 (1974): 281Google Scholar.

65 “Quentin Skinner on Meaning and Method,” interview by Teresa Bejan, The Art of Theory, 2011. Online at http://www.artoftheory.com/quentin-skinner-on-meaning-and-method/.

66 See, for example, Lamb, Recent Developments in the Thought of Quentin Skinner and the Ambitions of Contextualism,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 3 (2009): 246–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Lane, Doing Our Own Thinking for Ourselves: On Quentin Skinner's Genealogical Turn,” Journal of the History of Ideas 73 (2012): 7182CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

67 Skinner, Visions of Politics, 1:vi.

68 Skinner, Quentin, Liberty before Liberalism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 112Google Scholar.

69 Van Gelderen, Martin and Skinner, Quentin, eds., Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002)Google Scholar.

70 Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism, 117.

71 See Edling, Max and Mörkenstam, Uld, “Quentin Skinner: From Historian to Political Scientist,” Scandinavian Political Studies 18 (1995): 119–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

72 Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism, 118.

73 Palonen, Kari, “The History of Concepts as a Style of Political Theorizing: Quentin Skinner's and Reinhart Koselleck's Subversion of Normative Political Theory,” European Journal of Political Theory 1 (2002): 91106CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

74 Bartelson, Jens, “Philosophy and History in the Study of Political Thought,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 1 (2007): 111–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 See Pettit, Philip and Marti, Jose Luis, A Political Philosophy in Public Life: Civic Republicanism in Zapatero's Spain (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010)Google Scholar.

76 Skinner, Quentin, “A Genealogy of the Modern State,” Proceedings of the British Academy, no. 162 (2009): 325–70Google Scholar. I owe the observation of the explicit prescriptivism of this conclusion, and its tension with what Skinner says in the introduction to the piece, to Lane, “Doing Our Own Thinking for Ourselves,” 81–82.

77 Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, 71.

78 Dunn, “The Identity of the History of Ideas,” 98.

79 Green, “On the Difference between a Pupil and a Historian of Ideas.” For a similar argument against a rigid division of intellectual labor, see Leslie, Margaret, “In Defense of Anachronism,” Political Studies 18 (1970): 441–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

80 Dunn, John, The History of Political Theory and Other Essays (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 26Google Scholar.

81 Leslie, “In Defense of Anachronism,” 443.

82 Shapiro, Ian, The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005)Google Scholar.

83 This is the thesis of Frazer, “Utopophobia as a Vocation,” where I argue that political theorists have a professional responsibility to offer a valuable service to their fellow citizens and must not get lost in the construction of useless utopias.