Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T01:18:27.382Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Simone Weil on the Injustice of Rights-Based Doctrines

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Abstract

This paper explores Simone Weil's objections to a philosophy grounded on human rights. Weil thinks impersonal justice cannot be expressed in terms of personal rights. Rights, for Weil, are personal possessions; they are claimed or borne by some subject or person (me, you, her or them). The right or the just, however, is not susceptible to possession. When one substitutes a personal pronoun for the definite article before the word right (my right or their right instead of the right), justice is articulated in the manner of liberal contractualism but is biased against a notion of impersonal justice which Weil champions. The incompatibility of Weil's understanding of justice and a rights-based notion of justice is the subject-matter investigated in this article.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 McCloskey, H. J., “Rights,” Philosophical Quarterly, 15 (1965), 115–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar argues that rights should be understood as entitlements to something rather than claims against someone. But see Feinberg, J., Rights, Justice and the Bound of Liberty (Princeton: University Press, 1980), 151–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar for a refutation of this position.

2 For a defense of welfare-rights see Gerwirth, A., “The Basis and Content of Human RightsGoogle Scholar and Okin, S. M., “Liberty and Welfare: Some Issues in Human Rights Theory” in Human Rights, Nomos 23, ed. Pennock, J. R. and Chapman, J. W. (New York: University Press, 1981)Google Scholar. Option-rights are championed by Nozick, R., Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974)Google Scholar and more moderately by Hart, H. A., The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon, 1963).Google Scholar

3 Weil, S., “Human Personality” in Selected Essays 1934–43, trans. Rees, R. (London: Oxford University Press, 1963), p. 9.Google Scholar

4 Pufendorf, S., Of the Law of Nature and Nations, trans. Kennet, B. (London: Sare, 1717), I.i.16.Google Scholar

5 “Human Personality,” pp. 2122.Google Scholar

6 Ibid., pp. 22–3, 28–9; Waiting for God, trans. Craufurd, E. (New York: Putnam, 1951), p. 120.Google Scholar

7 “Human Personality,” p. 20.Google Scholar

8 Locke, J., The Second Treatise, sec. 27Google Scholar, in Two Treatises of Government, ed. Laslett, P. (New York: Mentor, 1965), pp. 328–29.Google Scholar

9 Andrew, E.Inalienable Right, Alienable Property and Freedom of Choice: Locke and Nozick on the Alienation of Labour,” Canadian Journal of Political Science 18 (1985), 329–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 First and Last Notebooks, trans. Rees, R. (London: Oxford University Press, 1970), p. 346.Google Scholar

11 The Need for Roots, trans. Wills, A. (Boston: Beacon, 1960), p. 5.Google Scholar

12 “Human Personality,” pp. 1920.Google Scholar

13 The Need for Roots, pp. 278.Google Scholar

14 Maritain, J., The Rights of Man and the Natural Law (London: Bles, 1958)Google Scholar and Mounier, E.'s Personalism (Notre Dame Press, 1970)Google Scholar, are representative of the personalist doctrine criticized by Weil.

15 Finnis, J., Natural Law and Human Rights (Cambridge: University Press 1980)Google Scholar, recognizes the decisive change from premodern natural law doctrines of “the right” to modern rights doctrine (p. 206). In asserting absolute rights, Finnis rejects the modern tendency to liberate rights from subjection to the common good, rejects the conceptual opposition of law and rights, and rejects the interpretation of rights as liberties or options (which protect choices rather than guide conduct).

16 “Human Personality,” pp. 1920Google Scholar; Waiting for God, p. 139.Google Scholar

17 Waiting for God, p. 139.Google Scholar

18 Ibid., p. 140.

19 Pufendorf, , Of the Law of Nature and Nations, II, vi. 6.Google Scholar

20 Passmore, J., “Civil Justice and Its Rivals” in Justice, ed. Kamenka, E. and Tay, A. E. S. (London: Edward Arnold, 1979), p. 47.Google Scholar

21 Waiting for God, p. 144.Google Scholar

22 Ibid., pp. 146–48; “Human Personality,” p. 28.Google Scholar

23 Ibid., p. 21.

25 Spinoza, B., A Theological-Political Treatise, chap. 19, in The Chief Works, trans. Elwes, R. H. M. (New York: Dover, 1951), 1:237, 264.Google Scholar

26 Waiting for God, p. 156Google Scholar; The Need for Roots, pp. 228–29.Google Scholar

27 Hobbes, T., De Cive in The English Works, ed. Molesworth, W. (London: John Bohm, 1839), 2:62Google Scholar. Also see Leviathan, chap. 15.

28 First and Last Notebooks, p. 19.Google Scholar

29 Ibid., p. 6.

30 Ibid., p. 17; The Need for Roots, pp. 180–81.Google Scholar

31 The Need for Roots, p. 3.Google Scholar

33 Feinberg, , Rights, p. 139.Google Scholar

34 Aiken, H. D., “Rights, Human and Otherwise,” The Monist, 52 (1968), 507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

35 Shrag, F., “Children: Their Rights and Needs” in Whose Child? ed. Aiken, W. and LaFollette, H. (Totowata, N.J.: Littlefield, Adams, 1980), pp. 237–38.Google Scholar

36 The Need for Roots, p. 3.Google Scholar

37 Ibid., pp. 3–4.

38 “Human Personality,” p. 21.Google Scholar

39 House of Representatives, Committee on Human Rights and International Organizations, Human Rights in Nicaragua, 15 09 1983, pp. 108–10.Google Scholar

40 Ibid., pp. 120–32.

41 “Human Personality.” p. 17.Google Scholar

42 Ibid., p. 18.

43 Narveson, J., “Human Rights: Which, If Any, Are There?”Google Scholar in Pennock, and Chapman, , Human Rights, p. 193.Google Scholar

44 The Need for Roots, p. 179.Google Scholar

45 Hobbes, T., Leviathan (Oxford: Blackwell, 1960), pp. 142–43.Google Scholar

46 The Need for Roots, p. 161.Google Scholar

47 “Plan for an Organization of Front-line Nurses” in The Simone Weil Reader, ed. Panichas, G. (New York: Dorset, 1981), pp. 96105.Google Scholar

48 The Need for Roots, p. 164.Google Scholar

49 Locke, , Second Treatise, sec. 168.Google Scholar

50 Ibid., sec. 208, 230.

51 The Need for Roots, p. 228.Google Scholar

52 Locke, J., A Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. Gough, J. W. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1966), pp. 139Google Scholar; cf. 135, 138, 154.

53 The Need for Roots, p. 127.Google Scholar

54 Kant, I., The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, trans. Ladd, J. (New York: Liberal Arts, 1965), pp. 8489.Google Scholar

55 The Need for Roots, p. 4.Google Scholar

56 Ecrits de Londres (Paris: Gallimard, 1957), p. 170. My translation.Google Scholar

57 Ibid., p. 171.

58 Feinberg, , Rights, p. 151.Google Scholar

59 Weil, S., The Notebooks, trans. Wills, A. (New York: Putnam, 1956), p. 152.Google Scholar

60 Boxhill, B., “Self-respect and Protest,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6 (1976), 69.Google Scholar

61 See Lichtheim, G., “Simone Weil” in Collected Essays (New York: Viking Press, 1973), pp. 467–68Google Scholar; O'Brien, C. C., “Patriotism and the Need for Roots” in Simone Weil: Interpretations of a Life, ed. White, G. A. (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1981), pp. 9598, 110.Google Scholar

62 O'Brien, , “Patriotism,” p. 96.Google Scholar

63 The Need for Roots, p. 33.Google Scholar

64 Ibid., pp. 28–29.

65 Ibid., p. 32.

66 Ibid., p. 30.

67 Ibid., p. 28.

68 Ibid., p. 23.

69 Ibid., p. 26.

70 Ibid., pp. 39; cf. 26–27.

71 Ibid., pp. 38–39.

72 Ibid., p. 39.

73 Ibid., pp. 80, 85.