Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
Hostname: page-component-59b7f5684b-vh8gq Total loading time: 0.383 Render date: 2022-09-27T02:47:41.183Z Has data issue: true Feature Flags: { "shouldUseShareProductTool": true, "shouldUseHypothesis": true, "isUnsiloEnabled": true, "useRatesEcommerce": false, "displayNetworkTab": true, "displayNetworkMapGraph": false, "useSa": true } hasContentIssue true

A STRONG REFLECTION PRINCIPLE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 November 2017

Abstract

This article introduces a new reflection principle. It is based on the idea that whatever is true in all entities of some kind is also true in a set-sized collection of them. Unlike standard reflection principles, it does not re-interpret parameters or predicates. This allows it to be both consistent in all higher-order languages and remarkably strong. For example, I show that in the language of second-order set theory with predicates for a satisfaction relation, it is consistent relative to the existence of a 2-extendible cardinal (Theorem 7.12) and implies the existence of a proper class of 1-extendible cardinals (Theorem 7.9).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Bernays, P. (1976). On the problem of schemata of infinity in axiomatic set theory. In Müller, G. H., editor. Sets and Classes: On the Work by Paul Bernays. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Vol. 84. North-Holland: Amsterdam, pp. 121172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boolos, G. (1984). To be is to be a value of a variable (or to be some values of some variables). Journal of Philosophy, 81(8), 430449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boolos, G. (1989). Iteration again. Philosophical Topics, 17, 521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J. P. (2004). E pluribus unum: Plural logic and set theory. Philosophia Mathematica, 12(3), 193221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M. & Kanamori, A. (2009). Handbook of Set Theory. Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Hamkins, J., Gitman, V., & Johnstone, T. (2015). Kelley-morse set theory and choice principles for classes. Available at: http://boolesrings.org/victoriagitman/files/2015/01/kelleymorse2.pdf (accessed June 24, 2016).
Kanamori, A. (2003). The Higher Infinite (second edition). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Koellner, P. (2009). On reflection principles. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 157(2–3), 206219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linnebo, O. (2007). Burgess on plural logic and set theory. Philosophia Mathematica, 15, 7993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linnebo, O. & Rayo, A. (2012). Hierarchies ontological and ideological. Mind, 121(482), 269308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall R., M. V. (1989). Higher order reflection principles. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 54(2), 474489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinhardt, W. N. (1974). Remarks on reflection principles, large cardinals, and elementary embeddings. In Jech, T., editor. Axiomatic Set Theory. Providence: American Mathematical Society, pp. 189205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinhardt, W. N. (1980). Satisfaction definitions and axioms of infinity in a theory of properties with necessity operator. In Mathematical logic in Latin America. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Vol. 99. Amsterdam: North-Holland, pp. 267303.Google Scholar
Tait, W. W. (2003). Zermelo’s conception of set theory and reflection principles. In Schirn, M., editor, Philosophy of Mathematics Today. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 469483.Google Scholar
Tait, W. (2005). Constructing cardinals from below. In The Provenance of Pure Reason. Logic and Computation in Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 133154.Google Scholar
Uzquiano, G. (2003). Plural quantification and classes. Philosophia Mathematica, 11(3), 6781.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welch, P. (forthcoming). Global reflection principles. In Sober, E., Niiniluoto, I., and Leitgeb, H., editors. Proceedings of the CLMPS, Helsinki 2015. London: College Publications.
Williamson, T. (2013). Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
4
Cited by

Save article to Kindle

To save this article to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

A STRONG REFLECTION PRINCIPLE
Available formats
×

Save article to Dropbox

To save this article to your Dropbox account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Dropbox account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

A STRONG REFLECTION PRINCIPLE
Available formats
×

Save article to Google Drive

To save this article to your Google Drive account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Google Drive account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

A STRONG REFLECTION PRINCIPLE
Available formats
×
×

Reply to: Submit a response

Please enter your response.

Your details

Please enter a valid email address.

Conflicting interests

Do you have any conflicting interests? *