Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-23T22:46:46.259Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How To Get About

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 May 2024

Abstract

The ‘Only connect!’ that serves as epigraph to Forster's Howards End tolerates a variety of interpretations; but the very idea of a connection, or a relating of one thing with another, is conceptually deep. One form of connection is when something is about a thing, representing or symbolizing that thing. When we think of someone, or discuss something, we connect to them, or to it.

In his Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein asks, ‘What makes my image of him into an image of him? […] Isn't my question like this: “What makes this sentence a sentence that has to do with him?”’ Wittgenstein thus notes the ramifications of his question: what makes her name hers? In virtue of what is this thought about them a thought about them? The issue he highlights has been with us since Plato's Cratylus and its history is unified by a presupposition: whatever makes it that (i) a bit of language (like a name or a sentence or any linguistic symbol) is about something is, fundamentally, also what makes it that (ii) a thought (or idea or image) is about a thing. The story of aboutness will be uniform, simplex, or so the presupposition has it.

But the history of the issue has been one of failure: we still don't adequately understand the nature of representation. I will propose and develop a perspective that rejects the presupposition and explains the failure: there is more than one way for a thing to be about something. Representation comes, ultimately, in varieties.

Type
Paper
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2024

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Carroll, Lewis, Through the Looking Glass and What Alice Found There (London: MacMillan, 1871).Google Scholar
Fine, Kit, Semantic Relationism (Oxford: Wiley, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry, Psychosemantics (Cambridge, MA: MIT, 1987).10.7551/mitpress/5684.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, E.M., Howards End (London: Edward Arnold, 1910).Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, ‘On Sense and Reference’, in Geach, P. and Black, M. (eds), Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (Oxford: Blackwell, 1952). First published in Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, Vol. 100 (1892).Google Scholar
Grice, H.P., ‘Meaning’, The Philosophical Review, 66:3 (1957), 377–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul, ‘A Puzzle About Belief’, in Margalit, A. (ed.), Meaning and Use (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979).Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul, Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard, 1980).Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard (ed.), The Linguistic Turn (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1967).Google Scholar
Schiffer, Stephen, Remnants of Meaning (Cambridge, MA: MIT, 1987).Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1953).Google Scholar