Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-25wd4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T08:22:59.572Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The exact consistency strength of the generic absoluteness for the universally Baire sets

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 January 2024

Grigor Sargsyan
Affiliation:
Institute of Mathematics of Polish Academy of Sciences, Poland; E-mail: gsargsyan@impan.pl
Nam Trang
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, University of North Texas, Denton, TX, USA; E-mail: Nam.Trang@unt.edu

Abstract

A set of reals is universally Baire if all of its continuous preimages in topological spaces have the Baire property. $\mathsf {Sealing}$ is a type of generic absoluteness condition introduced by Woodin that asserts in strong terms that the theory of the universally Baire sets cannot be changed by forcing.

The $\mathsf {Largest\ Suslin\ Axiom}$ ($\mathsf {LSA}$) is a determinacy axiom isolated by Woodin. It asserts that the largest Suslin cardinal is inaccessible for ordinal definable bijections. Let $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ be the statement that in all (set) generic extensions there is a model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ whose Suslin, co-Suslin sets are the universally Baire sets.

We show that over some mild large cardinal theory, $\mathsf {Sealing}$ is equiconsistent with $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$. In fact, we isolate an exact large cardinal theory that is equiconsistent with both (see Definition 2.7). As a consequence, we obtain that $\mathsf {Sealing}$ is weaker than the theory ‘$\mathsf {ZFC} +$ there is a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals’.

A variation of $\mathsf {Sealing}$, called $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$, is also shown to be equiconsistent with $\mathsf {Sealing}$ over the same large cardinal theory.

The result is proven via Woodin’s $\mathsf {Core\ Model\ Induction}$ technique and is essentially the ultimate equiconsistency that can be proven via the current interpretation of $\mathsf {CMI}$ as explained in the paper.

Type
Foundations
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© Institute of Mathematics of Polish Academy of Sciences and The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Soon after Cohen discovered forcing and established the consistency of the failure of the $\mathsf {Continuum\ Hypothesis\ (CH)}$ with $\mathsf {ZFC}$ , thus establishing the independence of $\mathsf {CH}$ from $\mathsf {ZFC}$ ,Footnote 1 many natural and useful set theoretic principles have been discovered to remove independence from set theory. Perhaps the two best known ones are $\mathsf {Shoenfield's\ Absoluteness\ Theorem}$ and $\mathsf {Martin's\ Axiom}$ .

As is well known, $\mathsf {Shoenfield's\ Absoluteness\ Theorem}$ , proved in [Reference Shoenfield45], asserts that there cannot be any independence result expressible as a $\Sigma ^1_2$ fact. In the language of real analysis, $\Sigma ^1_2$ sets of reals are projections of co-analytic sets.Footnote 2 Shoenfield’s theorem says that a co-analytic set is empty if and only if its natural interpretations in all generic extensions are empty.Footnote 3 What is so wonderful about $\mathsf {Shoenfield's\ Absoluteness}$ $\mathsf {Theorem}$ is that it is a theorem of $\mathsf {ZFC}$ . We will discuss $\mathsf {Martin's\ Axiom}$ and its generalization later on.

The goal of this paper is to establish an equiconsistency result between one Shoenfield-type generic absoluteness principle known as $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and a determinacy axiom that we abbreviated as $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ . $\mathsf {LSA}$ stands for the Largest-Suslin-Axiom. To state the main theorem, we need a few definitions.

A set of reals is universally Baire if all of its continuous preimages in topological spaces have the property of Baire. Let $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ be the collection of universally Baire sets.Footnote 4 Given a generic g, we let $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g=_{def}(\Gamma ^{\infty })^{V[g]}$ and ${\mathbb {R}}_g=_{def}{\mathbb {R}}^{V[g]}$ . ${\wp }(X)$ is the powerset of X. $\mathsf {AD}$ stands for the $\mathsf {Axiom\ of\ Determinacy}$ , and $\mathsf {AD}^+$ is a strengthening of $\mathsf {AD}$ due to Woodin. The reader can ignore the $+$ or can consult [Reference Woodin61, Definition 9.6].

Motivated by Woodin’s $\mathsf {Sealing\ Theorem}$ ([Reference Larson23, Theorem 3.4.17] and [Reference Woodin60, Sealing Theorem]), we define $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , a key notion in this paper. We say $V[g], V[h]$ are two successive generic extensions (of V) if $g, h$ are V-generic and $V[g]\subseteq V[h]$ .

Definition 1.1. $\mathsf {Sealing}$ is the conjunction of the following statements.

  1. 1. For every set generic g, $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, \mathbb {R}_g){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}^+$ and ${\wp }({\mathbb {R}}_g)\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, \mathbb {R}_g)=\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ .

  2. 2. For every two successive set generic extensions $V[g]\subseteq V[h]$ , there is an elementary embedding

    $$ \begin{align*} j: L(\Gamma^{\infty}_g, \mathbb{R}_g)\rightarrow L(\Gamma^{\infty}_h, \mathbb{R}_h) \end{align*} $$

such that for every $A\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ , $j(A)=A_h$ .Footnote 5

To introduce $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ , we first need to introduce the $\mathsf {Largest\ Suslin\ Axiom}$ $(\mathsf {LSA})$ . A cardinal ${\kappa }$ is $\mathsf {OD}$ -inaccessible if for every ${\alpha }<{\kappa }$ , there is no surjection $f: {\wp }({\alpha })\rightarrow {\kappa }$ that is definable from ordinal parameters. A set of reals $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}$ is ${\kappa }$ -Suslin if for some tree T on ${\kappa }$ , $A=p[T]$ .Footnote 6 A set A is Suslin if it is $\kappa $ -Suslin for some $\kappa $ ; A is co-Suslin if its complement $\mathbb {R}\backslash A$ is Suslin. A set A is Suslin, co-Suslin if both A and its complement are Suslin. A cardinal ${\kappa }$ is a Suslin cardinal if there is a set of reals A such that A is ${\kappa }$ -Suslin but A is not ${\lambda }$ -Suslin for any ${\lambda }<{\kappa }$ . Suslin cardinals play an important role in the study of models of determinacy as can be seen by just flipping through the Cabal Seminar Volumes ([Reference Kechris, Martin and Moschovakis15], [Reference Kechris, Martin and Steel16], [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel17], [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel18], [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel19], [Reference Kechris, Martin and Moschovakis20], [Reference Kechris and Moschovakis21]).

The $\mathsf {Largest\ Suslin\ Axiom}$ was introduced by Woodin in [Reference Woodin61, Remark 9.28]. The terminology is due to the first author. Here is the definition.

Definition 1.2. The $\mathsf {Largest\ Suslin\ Axiom}$ , abbreviated as $\mathsf {LSA}$ , is the conjunction of the following statements:

  1. 1. $\mathsf {AD}^+$ .

  2. 2. There is a largest Suslin cardinal.

  3. 3. The largest Suslin cardinal is $\mathsf {OD}$ -inaccessible.

In the hierarchy of determinacy axioms, which one may appropriately call the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Hierarchy}$ ,Footnote 7 $\mathsf {LSA}$ is an anomaly as it belongs to the successor stage of the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Hierarchy}$ but does not conform to the general norms of the successor stages of the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Hierarchy}$ . Prior to [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], $\mathsf {LSA}$ was not known to be consistent. In [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], the first author showed that it is consistent relative to a Woodin cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Nowadays, the axiom plays a key role in many aspects of inner model theory and features prominently in Woodin’s $\mathsf {Ultimate\ L}$ framework (see [Reference Woodin62, Definition 7.14] and Axiom I and Axiom II on page 97 of [Reference Woodin62]).Footnote 8

Definition 1.3. Let $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ be the statement: For all V-generic g, in $V[g]$ , there is $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}_g$ such that $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_g){\vDash } \mathsf {LSA}$ and $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ is the Suslin co-Suslin sets of $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ .

The following is our main theorem. We say that $\phi $ and $\psi $ are equiconsistent over theory T if there is a model of $T\cup \{\phi \}$ if and only if there is a model of $T\cup \{\psi \}$ .

Theorem 1.4. $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ are equiconsistent over the theory ‘there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary’.

In Theorem 1.4, ‘ $T_1$ and $T_2$ are equiconsistent’ is used in the following stronger sense: there is a well-founded model of $T_1$ if and only if there is a well-founded model of $T_2$ .

Remark 1.5. It is our intention to consider $\mathsf {Sealing}$ under large cardinals. The reason for doing this is that universally Baire sets do not in general behave nicely when there are no large cardinals in the universe. One may choose to drop clause 1 from the definition of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ . Call the resulting principle $\mathsf {Weak\ Sealing}$ . If there is an inaccessible cardinal ${\kappa }$ which is a limit of Woodin cardinals and strong cardinals, then $\mathsf {Weak\ Sealing}$ implies $\mathsf {Sealing}$ . This is because one may arrange so that $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ is the derived model after Levy collapsing ${\kappa }$ to be $\omega _1$ (see Theorem 1.10). We do not know the consistency strength of $\mathsf {Weak\ Sealing}$ or $\mathsf {Sealing}$ in the absence of large cardinals. But one gets that $\mathsf {Weak\ Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {Sealing}$ are equiconsistent over the large cardinal hypothesis in Theorem 1.4.

Based on the above theorems, it is very tempting to conjecture that $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ are equivalent over ‘there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary’. However, [Reference Sargsyan and Trang41] shows that this conjecture is false. The following variation of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , called $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ , is also isolated by Woodin.

Definition 1.6. $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ is the conjunction of the following:

  1. 1. For any set generic g, $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g) {\vDash } \mathsf {AD}^+$ , and $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g = {\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g)$ .

  2. 2. For any set generic g, in $V[g]$ , suppose $\delta $ is Woodin. Whenever G is $V[g]$ -generic for either the $\mathbb {P}_{<\delta }$ -stationary tower or the $\mathbb {Q}_{<\delta }$ -stationary tower at $\delta $ , then

    $$ \begin{align*} j(\Gamma^{\infty}_g) = \Gamma^{\infty}_{g*G}, \end{align*} $$
    where $j: V[g] \rightarrow M \subset V[g*G]$ is the generic elementary embedding given by G.

Theorem 1.7. $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {Sealing}$ are equiconsistent over ‘there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary’.

Remark 1.8.

  1. 1. The proof of Theorems 1.4 and 1.7 shows that over the large cardinal assumption stated in Theorem 1.4, $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ and $\mathsf {Sealing}$ are equiconsistent relative to the following consequence of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and of $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ (cf. Proposition 4.1):

    $\mathsf {Sealing}^{-}$ : ‘for any set generic g, $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g = {\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g)$ and there is no $\omega _1$ -sequence of distinct reals in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g)$ ’.

  2. 2. As mentioned above, [Reference Sargsyan and Trang41] shows that $\mathsf {LSA-over-UB}$ is not equivalent to $\mathsf {Sealing}$ (over some large cardinal theory). However, the equivalence of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ , other weak forms of these theories may still hold (over the large cardinal theory of Theorem 1.4). See Conjecture 13.4.

  3. 3. Woodin has observed that assuming a proper class of Woodin cardinals which are limits of strong cardinals, $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ implies $\mathsf {Sealing}$ .

Before giving the proof, in the next few sections, we will explain the context of Theorem 1.4.

Generic Absoluteness

As was mentioned in the opening paragraph, the discovery of forcing almost immediately initiated the study of removing independence phenomenon from set theory. Large cardinals were used to establish a plethora of results that generalize $\mathsf {Shoenfield's\ Absoluteness\ Theorem}$ to more complex formulas than $\Sigma ^1_2$ . In another direction, new axioms were discovered that imply what is forced is already true. These axioms are called forcing axioms, and $\mathsf {Martin's\ Axiom}$ is the first one.

Forcing axioms assert that analogues of the $\mathsf {Baire\ Category\ Theorem}$ hold for any collection of $\aleph _1$ -dense sets. A consequence of this is that the $\aleph _1$ -fragment of the generic object added by the relevant forcing notion exists as a set in the ground model, implying that what is forced by the $\aleph _1$ -fragment of the generic is already true in the ground model. $\mathsf {Martin's\ Axiom}$ and its generalizations do not follow from $\mathsf {ZFC}$ . Many axioms of this type have been introduced and extensively studied. Perhaps the best known ones are $\mathsf {Martin's\ Axiom}$ ([Reference Martin and Solovay24]), the $\mathsf {Proper\ Forcing\ Axiom}$ ( $\mathsf {PFA}$ , see [Reference Baumgartner3]) and $\mathsf {Martin's\ Maximum}$ (see [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah7]).

The general set theoretic theme described above is known as generic absoluteness. The interested reader can consult [Reference Audrito and Viale2], [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah7], [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah8], [Reference Hauser9], [Reference Larson23], [Reference Steel54], [Reference Todorcevic56], [Reference Viale58], [Reference Wilson59], [Reference Woodin61] and the references appearing in those papers. We will not be dealing with forcing axioms in this paper, but $\mathsf {PFA}$ will be used for illustrative purposes.

The largest class of sets of reals for which a Shoenfield-type generic absoluteness can hold is the collection of the universally Baire sets. We will explain this claim below. The story begins with the fact that the universally Baire sets have canonical interpretations in all generic extensions, and in a sense, they are the only ones that have this property. The next paragraph describes exactly how this happens. The proofs appear in [Reference Feng, Magidor and Woodin6], [Reference Larson23] and [Reference Steel47].

In [Reference Feng, Magidor and Woodin6], it was shown by Feng, Magidor and Woodin that a set of reals A is universally Baire if and only if for each uncountable cardinal ${\kappa }$ , there are trees T and S on ${\kappa }$ such that $p[T]=A$ and in all set generic extensions $V[g]$ of V obtained by a poset of size $<{\kappa }$ , $V[g]{\vDash } p[T]={\mathbb {R}}-p[S]$ . The canonical interpretation of A in $V[g]$ is just $A_g=_{def}(p[T])^{V[g]}$ , where T is chosen on a $\kappa $ that is bigger than the size of the poset that adds g. It is not hard to show, using the absoluteness of well-foundedness, that $A_g$ is independent of the choice of $(T, S)$ .

Woodin showed that if A is a universally Baire set of reals and the universe has a class of Woodin cardinals, then the theory of $L(A, {\mathbb {R}})$ cannot be changed. He achieved this by showing that if there is a class of Woodin cardinals, then for any universally Baire set A and any two successive set generic extensions $V[g]\subseteq V[h]$ , there is an elementary embedding $j:L(A_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)\rightarrow L(A_h, {\mathbb {R}}_h)$ .Footnote 9

Moreover, if sufficient generic absoluteness is true about a set of reals, then that set is universally Baire. More precisely, suppose $\phi $ is a property of reals. Let $A_{\phi }$ be the set of reals defined by $\phi $ . If sufficiently many statements about $A_{\phi }$ are generically absolute, then it is because $A_{\phi }$ is universally Baire (see the $\mathsf {Tree\ Production\ Lemma}$ in [Reference Larson23] or in [Reference Steel47]).Footnote 10 Thus, the next place to look for absoluteness is the set of all universally Baire sets.

Is it possible that there is no independence result about the set of universally Baire sets? $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , introduced in the preamble of this paper, is the formal version of the English sentence asserting that much like individual universally Baire sets, much like integers, the theory of universally Baire sets is immune to forcing. It is stated in the spirit of Woodin’s aforementioned theorem for the individual universally Baire sets.

Although the definition of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ is very natural and its statement is seemingly benign, $\mathsf {Sealing}$ has drastic consequences on the $\mathsf {Inner\ Model\ Program}$ , which is one of the oldest set theoretic projects and is also the next set theoretical theme that we introduce.

The Inner Model Program and The Inner Model Problem

The goal of the Inner Model Program ( $\mathsf {IMP}$ ) is to build canonical L-like inner models with large cardinals. The problem of building a canonical inner model for a large cardinal axiom $\phi $ is known as the $\mathsf {Inner\ Model\ Problem}$ ( $\mathsf {IMPr}$ ) for $\phi $ . There are several expository articles written about $\mathsf {IMP}$ and $\mathsf {IMPr}$ . The reader who wants to learn more can consult [Reference Jensen12], [Reference Sargsyan32], [Reference Schimmerling42].

In [Reference Neeman31], Neeman, assuming the existence of a Woodin cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals, solved the $\mathsf {IMPr}$ for a Woodin cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals and for large cardinals somewhat beyond. Neeman’s result is the best current result on $\mathsf {IMPr}$ . However, this is only a tiny fragment of the large cardinal paradise, and also, its solution is specific to the hypothesis (we will discuss this point more).

Dramatically, $\mathsf {Sealing}$ implies that $\mathsf {IMP}$ , as is known today, cannot succeed as if ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a model that conforms to the norms of modern inner model theory and has some very basic closure properties; then ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash }$ ‘there is a well-ordering of reals in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})$ ’. As $\mathsf {AD}$ implies the reals cannot be well ordered, ${\mathcal {M}}$ cannot satisfy $\mathsf {Sealing}$ . Thus, we must have the following.Footnote 11

Sealing Dichotomy

Either no large cardinal theory implies $\mathsf {Sealing}$ or the $\mathsf {Inner\ Model\ Problem}$ for some large cardinal cannot have a solution conforming to the modern norms.

Intriguingly, Woodin, assuming the existence of a supercompact cardinal and a class of Woodin cardinals, has shown that $\mathsf {Sealing}$ holds after collapsing the powerset of the powerset of a supercompact cardinal to be countable (for a proof, see [Reference Larson23, Theorem 3.4.17]). Because we are collapsing the supercompact to be countable, it seems that Woodin’s result does not imply that $\mathsf {Sealing}$ has dramatic effect on $\mathsf {IMP}$ , or at least this impact cannot be seen in the large cardinal region below supercompact cardinals, which is known as the short extender region.

As part of proving Theorem 1.4 and Theorem 1.7, we will establish the following.

Theorem 1.9. $\mathsf {Sealing}$ is consistent relative to a Woodin cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals. So is $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ .

One consequence of Theorem 1.9 is that $\mathsf {Sealing}$ is within the short extender region. Although Theorem 1.9 does not illustrate the impact of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , its exact impact on $\mathsf {IMP}$ in the short extender region can also be precisely stated. But to do this, we will need extenders.

Extender detour

Before we go on, let us take a minute to introduce extenders, which are natural generalization of ultrafilters. In fact, extenders are just a coherent sequence of ultrafilters. As was mentioned above, the goal of $\mathsf {IMP}$ is to build canonical L-like inner models for large cardinals. The current methodology is that such models should be constructed in Gödel’s sense from extenders, the very objects whose existence large cardinal axioms assert. Perhaps the best way to introduce extenders is via the elementary embeddings that they induce.

Suppose M and N are two transitive models of set theory and $j:M\rightarrow N$ is a nontrivial elementary embedding. Let $\kappa =\mathrm {crit }(j)$ and let ${\lambda }\in [{\kappa }, j({\kappa }))$ be any ordinal. Set

$$ \begin{align*} E_j=\{(a, A)\in [{\lambda}]^{<\omega}\times {\wp}([{\kappa}]^{\vert{a}\vert})^M: a\in j(A)\}. \end{align*} $$

$E_j$ is called the $({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ -extender derived from j. $E_j$ is really an M-extender as it measures the sets in M. As with more familiar ultrafilters, one can define extenders abstractly without using the parent embedding j and then show that each extender, via an ultrapower construction, gives rise to an embedding. Given a $({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ -extender E over M, we let $\pi _E: M\rightarrow Ult(M, E)$ be the ultrapower embedding. A computation that involves chasing the definitions shows that E is the extender derived from $\pi _E$ . Similar computations also show that ${\kappa }=\mathrm {crit }(\pi _E)$ and $\pi _E({\kappa })\geq {\lambda }$ . It is customary to write $\mathrm {crit }(E)$ for ${\kappa }$ and $lh(E)={\lambda }$ .Footnote 12 It is also not hard to see that for each $a\in [{\lambda }]^{<\omega }$ , $E_a$ is an ultrafilter concentrating on $[{\kappa }]^{\vert {a}\vert }$ , and that if $a\subseteq b$ , then $E_b$ naturally projects to $E_a$ .

The motivation behind extenders is the fact that extenders capture more of the universe in the ultrapower than one can achieve via the usual ultrapower construction. In particular, under large cardinal assumptions, one can have $({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ -extender E such that $V_{\lambda }\subseteq Ult(V, E)$ . Because of this, all large cardinal notions below superstrong cardinals can be captured by extenders.

The extenders as we defined them above are called short extenders, where shortness refers to the fact that all of its ultrafilters concentrate on its critical point. Large cardinal notions such as supercompactness and hugeness cannot be captured by such short extenders as embeddings witnessing supercompactness give rise to measures that do not concentrate on the critical point of the embedding. However, one can capture these large cardinal notions by using the so-called long extenders. We do not need them in this paper, and so we will not dwell on them.

The large cardinal region that can be captured by short extenders is the region of superstrong cardinals. A cardinal ${\kappa }$ is called superstrong if there is an embedding $j:V\rightarrow M$ with $\mathrm {crit }(j)={\kappa }$ and $V_{j({\kappa })}\subseteq M$ . Superstrong cardinals are close to the optimal cardinal notions that can be expressed via short extenders.

Currently, to solve $\mathsf {IMPr}$ for a large cardinal, one attempts to build a model of the form $L[\vec {E}]$ , where $\vec {E}$ is a carefully chosen sequence of extenders. The reader interested in learning more about what $L[\vec {E}]$ should be can consult [Reference Steel53]. This ends our detour.

The Core Model Induction

What is a solution to the $\mathsf {IMPr}$ for a given large cardinal? In the short extender region, $\mathsf {IMPr}$ for a large cardinal notion, such as superstrong cardinals, has a somewhat precise meaning. One is essentially asked to build a model of the form $L[\vec {E}]$ which has a superstrong cardinal and $\vec {E}$ is a fine extender sequence as defined in [Reference Steel53, Definition 2.4]. However, one may do this construction under many different hypotheses.

As was mentioned above, Neeman solved the $\mathsf {IMPr}$ for a Woodin cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals assuming the existence of such a cardinal. One very plausible precise interpretation of $\mathsf {IMPr}$ is exactly in this sense. Namely, given a large cardinal axiom $\phi $ , assuming large cardinals that are possibly stronger than $\phi $ , build an ${\mathcal {M}}=L[\vec {E}]$ such that ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \exists {\kappa } \phi ({\kappa })$ .

Our interpretation of $\mathsf {IMPr}$ is influenced by John Steel’s view on Gödel’s Program (see [Reference Steel54]). In a nutshell, the idea is to develop a theory that connects various foundational frameworks, such as Forcing Axioms, Large Cardinals and Determinacy Axioms, with one another.Footnote 13 In this view, $\mathsf {IMPr}$ is the bridge between all of these natural frameworks, and $\mathsf {IMPr}$ needs to be solved under a variety of hypotheses, such as $\mathsf {PFA}$ or failure of Jensen’s $\square $ principles. Our primary tool for solving $\mathsf {IMPr}$ in large cardinal-free contexts is the $\mathsf {Core\ Model\ Induction}$ ( $\mathsf {CMI}$ ), which is a technique invented by Woodin and developed by many set theorists during the past 20–25 years.Footnote 14

In the earlier days, $\mathsf {CMI}$ was perceived as an inductive method for proving determinacy in models such as $L(\mathbb {R})$ . The goal was to prove that $L_{\alpha }({\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}$ by induction on ${\alpha }$ . In those earlier days, which is approximately the period 1995–2010, the method worked by establishing intricate connections between large cardinals, universally Baire sets and determinacy.Footnote 15 The fundamental work done by Jensen, Neeman, Martin, Mitchell, Steel and Woodin were, and still are, at the heart of current developments of $\mathsf {CMI}$ . The following is a non-exhaustive list of influential papers: most papers in the Cabal Seminar Volumes that discuss scales or playful universes ([Reference Kechris, Martin and Moschovakis15], [Reference Kechris, Martin and Steel16], [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel17], [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel18], [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel19], [Reference Kechris, Martin and Moschovakis20], [Reference Kechris and Moschovakis21]), [Reference Jensen11], [Reference Martin and Steel25], [Reference Martin and Steel26], [Reference Mitchell and Steel28], [Reference Neeman30], [Reference Steel49]. Several fundamental papers were written implicitly developing this view of $\mathsf {CMI}$ . For example, the reader can consult [Reference O’Neal Ketchersid22], [Reference Steel46] and [Reference Steel and Schindler48]. As $\mathsf {CMI}$ evolved, it became more of a tool for deriving maximal determinacy models from non-large cardinal hypotheses.

In a seminal work, Woodin has developed a technique for deriving determinacy models from large cardinals. The theorem is known as the $\mathsf {Derived\ Model\ Theorem}$ . A typical situation works as follows. Suppose ${\lambda }$ is a limit of Woodin cardinals and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\lambda })$ is generic. Let ${\mathbb {R}}^*=\cup _{{\alpha }<{\lambda }}{\mathbb {R}}^{V[g\cap Coll(\omega , {\alpha })]}$ . Working in $V(\mathbb {R}^*)$ ,Footnote 16 let $\Gamma =\{A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}: L(A, {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}\}$ . Then we have the following.

Theorem 1.10 (Woodin, [Reference Steel47])

$L(\Gamma , {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}$ .

In Woodin’s theorem, $\Gamma $ is maximal as there are no more (strongly) determined sets in the universe that are not in $\Gamma $ . If one assumes that ${\lambda }$ is a limit of strong cardinals, then $\Gamma $ above is just $(\Gamma ^{\infty })^{V({\mathbb {R}}^*)}$ .

The aim of $\mathsf {CMI}$ is to do the same for other natural set theoretic frameworks, such as forcing axioms and combinatorial statements. Suppose T is a natural set theoretic framework and $V{\vDash } T$ . Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable cardinal. One way to perceive $\mathsf {CMI}$ is the following.

( $\mathsf {CMI}$ at ${\kappa }$ ) Saying that one is doing $\mathsf {Core\ Model\ Induction}$ at ${\kappa }$ means that for some $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , {\kappa })$ Footnote 17, in $V[g]$ , one is proving that $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}^+$ .

( $\mathsf {CMI}$ below ${\kappa }$ ) Saying that one is doing $\mathsf {Core\ Model\ Induction}$ below ${\kappa }$ means that for some $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\kappa })$ Footnote 18, in $V[g]$ , one is proving that $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}^+$ .

In both cases, the aim might be less ambitious. It might be that one’s goal is to just produce $\Gamma \subseteq \Gamma ^{\infty }$ such that $L(\Gamma , {\mathbb {R}})$ is a determinacy model with desired properties.

$\mathsf {CMI}$ can even help proving versions of the $\mathsf {Derived\ Model\ Theorem}$ . Here is an example. We use the setup introduced for stating the $\mathsf {Derived\ Model\ Theorem}$ (Theorem 1.10). Suppose $A\in V({\mathbb {R}}^*)$ is a set of reals such that for some ${\alpha }<{\lambda }$ , there is a $<{\lambda }$ -universally Baire set $B\in V[g\cap Coll(\omega , {\alpha })]$ such that $A=B_g$ . The tools developed during the earlier period of $\mathsf {CMI}$ can be used to show that $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}^*){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}$ . The point here is just that $\mathsf {CMI}$ is the most general method for proving derived model types of results. In the $\mathsf {Derived\ Model\ Theorem}$ , the presence of large cardinals makes $\mathsf {CMI}$ unnecessary, but in other cases, it is the only method we currently have. One can also attempt to prove the full $\mathsf {Derived\ Model\ Theorem}$ via $\mathsf {CMI}$ , but this seems harder, and some of the main technical difficulties associated with other non-large cardinal frameworks resurface.

The goal, however, is not to just derive a determinacy model from natural set theoretic frameworks but to establish that the determinacy model has the same set theoretic complexity as V has.

Let M be the maximal model of determinacy derived from V. One naturalFootnote 19 way of saying that M has the same complexity as V is by saying that the large cardinal complexity of V is reflected into M, and one particularly elegant way of saying this is to say that ${\mathrm {HOD}}^M$ , the universe of the hereditarily ordinal definable sets of M, acquires these large cardinals. A typical conjecture that we can now state in this language is as follows.

Conjecture 1.11. Assume the $\mathsf {Proper\ Forcing\ Axiom}$ and suppose ${\kappa }\geq \omega _2$ . Let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , {\kappa })$ . Then ${\mathrm {HOD}}^{L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)}{\vDash }$ ‘there is a superstrong cardinal’.

A less ambitious conjecture would be that $\mathsf {PFA}$ implies that whenever $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , {\kappa })$ is V-generic, there is a set of reals $A\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ such that ${\mathrm {HOD}}^{L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_g)}{\vDash }$ ‘there is a superstrong cardinal’. However, we believe that the stronger conjecture is also true. One can change $\mathsf {PFA}$ to any other natural framework that is expected to be stronger than superstrong cardinals.Footnote 20 As we brought up ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ , it is perhaps important to discuss its use in $\mathsf {CMI}$ .

HOD analysis and covering

Conjecture 1.11 is a product of many decades of work that goes back to the UCLA’s Cabal Seminar, where the study of playful universes originates (see, for example, [Reference Becker and Moschovakis4] and [Reference Moschovakis29]). Our attempt is to avoid a historical introduction to the subject, and so we will avoid the long history of studying ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ and its playful inner models assuming determinacy.

Nowadays, we know that ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ of many models satisfying $\mathsf {AD}$ is an L-like model carrying many large cardinals,Footnote 21 and the problem of showing that ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ of every model of $\mathsf {AD}$ is an L-like model is one of the central open problems of descriptive inner model theory (see [Reference Sargsyan32] and [Reference Steel55]).

The current methodology for proving that ${\mathrm {HOD}}^{L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})}$ has the desired large cardinals is via a failure of a certain covering principle involving ${\mathrm {HOD}}^{L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})}$ . Recall that under determinacy, $\Theta $ is defined to be the least ordinal that is not a surjective image of the reals. Set ${\mathcal { H}}^-={\mathrm {HOD}}^{L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})}|\Theta $ .

To define the aforementioned covering principle, we first need to extend ${\mathcal { H}}^-$ to a model ${\mathcal { H}}$ in which $\Theta $ is the largest cardinal. This is a standard construction in inner model theory. We simply let ${\mathcal { H}}$ be the union of all hod mice extending ${\mathcal { H}}$ whose countable submodels have iteration strategies in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})$ . This sentence perhaps means little to a general reader. It turns out, however, that in many situations, it is possible to describe ${\mathcal { H}}$ without any reference to inner model theoretic objects.

Here is one such example. Suppose ${\kappa }$ is a measurable cardinal which is a limit of strong cardinals and suppose we are doing $\mathsf {CMI}$ below ${\kappa }$ . Let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\kappa })$ be our generic. We also make the assumption that all sets of reals produced by the $\mathsf {CMI}$ below $\kappa $ are universally Baire.Footnote 22 Let $j:V\rightarrow M$ be any embedding with $\mathrm {crit }(j)={\kappa }$ . We furthermore assume that we have succeeded in showing that $\sup (j[\Theta ])<j(\Theta )$ .Footnote 23 Setting $\nu =\sup (j[\Theta ])$ , let $\mathcal {C}({\mathcal { H}}^-)$ be the set of all $A\subseteq \Theta $ such that $j(A)\cap \nu \in j({\mathcal { H}}^-)$ . Then ${\mathcal { H}}$ is the transitive model extending ${\mathcal { H}}^-$ that is coded by the elements of $\mathcal {C}({\mathcal { H}}^-)$ .Footnote 24

At any rate, one can simply regard ${\mathcal { H}}$ as a canonical one-cardinal extension of ${\mathcal { H}}^-$ . In fact, that ${\mathcal { H}}$ is a canonical extension of ${\mathcal { H}}^-$ is the central point. The next paragraph explains this.

Continuing with the above scenario, let now $h\subseteq Coll(\omega , \kappa )$ be $V[g]$ -generic.Footnote 25 Because $\vert {V_{\kappa }\vert }={\kappa }$ , we have that ${\vert {\mathcal { H}}^-\vert }^{V[g*h]}=\aleph _0$ and ${\vert {\mathcal { H}}\vert }^{V[g*h]}\leq \aleph _1$ . Letting $\eta =Ord\cap {\mathcal { H}}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} L(\Gamma^{\infty}_{g*h}, {\mathbb{R}}_{g*h}){\vDash} \text{ `there is an } \eta\text{-sequence of distinct reals'}. \end{align*} $$

Assuming $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , we get that $\eta <\omega _1$ as under $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}$ , and under $\mathsf {AD}$ , there is no $\omega _1$ -sequence of reals. Therefore, in V, $\eta <\kappa ^+$ as we have that $(\kappa ^+)^V=\omega _1^{V[g*h]}$ . Letting now

$\mathsf {UB-Covering:} \ {\mathrm cf}^V(Ord\cap {\mathcal { H}})\geq {\kappa }$ ,

$\mathsf {Sealing}$ implies that $\mathsf {UB-Covering}$ fails at measurable cardinals that are limits of strong cardinals. A similar argument can be carried out by only assuming that ${\kappa }$ is a singular strong limit cardinal.Footnote 26

All other sufficiently strong frameworks also imply that the $\mathsf {UB-Covering}$ fails but for different reasons. One particular reason is that $\mathsf {UB-Covering}$ implies that Jensen’s $\square _{\kappa }$ holds at singular cardinal $\kappa $ , while a celebrated theorem of Todorcevic says that under $\mathsf {PFA}$ , $\square _{\kappa }$ has to fail for all ${\kappa }\geq \omega _2$ .

The argument that has been used to show that ${\mathcal { H}}$ has large cardinals proceeds as follows. Pick a target large cardinal $\phi $ , which for technical reasons we assume is a $\Sigma _2$ -formula. Assume ${\mathcal { H}}{\vDash } \forall \gamma \neg \phi (\gamma )$ . Thus far, in all applications of the $\mathsf {CMI}$ , the facts that

$\phi \mathsf {\ -\ Minimality}: \ {\mathcal { H}}{\vDash } \forall \gamma \neg \phi (\gamma )$

and

$\neg \ \mathsf {UB-Covering}$ : cf $^V({{\mathcal { H}}\cap Ord})<{\kappa }$

hold have been used to prove that there is a universally Baire set not in $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ where $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , {\kappa })$ or $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\kappa })$ (depending where we do $\mathsf {CMI}$ ), which is obviously a contradiction.

Because of the work done in the first 15 years of the 2000s, it seemed as though this is a general pattern that will persist through the short extender region. That is, for any $\phi $ that is in the short extender region, either $\phi \mathsf {\ -\ Minimality}$ must fail or $\mathsf {UB-Covering}$ must hold. The main way Theorem 1.9 affects $\mathsf {IMPr}$ in the short extender region is by implying that this prevalent view is false. Footnote 27

Almost all existing literature on $\mathsf {CMI}$ uses the argument outlined above in one way or another. The interested reader can consult [Reference Adolf1], [Reference Sargsyan34], [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], [Reference Sargsyan and Trang39], [Reference Steel46], [Reference Trang57], [Reference Zhu63].

The future of $\mathsf {CMI}$

In the authors’ view, $\mathsf {CMI}$ should be viewed as a technique for proving that a certain type of covering holds rather than a technique for showing that ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ has large cardinals. The latter should be the corollary, not the goal. The type of covering that we have in mind is the following. We state it in the short extender region, and we use $\mathsf {NLE}$ Footnote 28 of [Reference Steel55] to state that we are in the short extender region.

Conjecture 1.12. Assume $\mathsf {NLE}$ and suppose there are unboundedly many Woodin cardinals and strong cardinals. Let $\kappa $ be a limit of Woodin cardinals and strong cardinals such that either ${\kappa }$ is a measurable cardinal or has cofinality $\omega $ . Then there is a transitive model M of $\mathsf {ZFC-Powerset}$ such that

  1. 1. $Ord\cap M= {\kappa }^+$ ,

  2. 2. M has a largest cardinal $\nu $ ,

  3. 3. for any V-generic $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\kappa })$ , letting $\mathbb {R}^* = \bigcup _{\alpha <{\kappa }} \mathbb {R}^{V[g\cap Coll(\omega ,\alpha )]}$ , in $V({\mathbb {R}}^*)$ ,

    $$ \begin{align*} L(M, \bigcup_{{\alpha}<\nu}(M|{\alpha})^\omega, \Gamma^{\infty}, {\mathbb{R}}^*){\vDash} \mathsf{AD}. \end{align*} $$
  4. 4. If in addition there is no inner model with a subcompact cardinal, then $M{\vDash } \square _{\nu }$ .

In [Reference Sargsyan36], the first author showed that Conjecture 1.12 holds in hod mice. Assuming V is a hod mouse and keeping the notation of Conjecture 1.12, M is simply the direct limit of all iterates of $V|\kappa ^+$ that are below $\kappa $ and have a countable length in $V[g]$ .

With more work, the conjecture can also be stated without assuming the large cardinals. We do not believe that the conjecture is true in the long extender region because of the following general argument. Assume ${\kappa }$ is an indestructible supercompact cardinal and suppose the conclusion of the conjecture holds at ${\kappa }$ . Let $g\subseteq Coll({\kappa }, {\kappa }^+)$ be V-generic. Then presumably if M satisfies the conclusion of Conjecture 1.12, then $M^V=M^{V[g]}$ . The confidence that this is true comes from the fact that we expect that any M satisfying clause 3 must have an absolute definition. Because ${\kappa }$ is still a supercompact in $V[g]$ , clause 1 has to fail.

We believe that proving Conjecture 1.12 should become the goal of $\mathsf {CMI}$ . To prove it, one has to develop techniques for building third- order canonical objects, objects that are canonical subsets of $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ .

One possible source of such objects is described in forthcoming [Reference Sargsyan and Trang40]. There, the authors introduced the notion of Z-hod pairs and developed their basic theory. We should also note that even in this paper, to prove Theorem 1.4, we build objects that resemble objects that are of third order. We build our third-order objects more or less according to the current conventions following [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38]. What we meant above is that we believe that to get to superstrongs entirely, new kinds of canonical objects need to be constructed. The reader can read more about such speculations in [Reference Sargsyan36].

The abstract claimed that Theorem 1.4 is the ultimate equiconsistency proved via $\mathsf {CMI}$ . This does not mean that there are no other equiconsistencies in the region of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . All it means is that to go beyond, one has to start thinking of $\mathsf {CMI}$ as a method of building third-order objects.

The authors view Theorem 1.4 as a natural accumulation point in the development of their understanding of $\mathsf {CMI}$ and the way it is used to translate set theoretic strength between natural set theoretic frameworks – namely, between forcing axioms, large cardinals, determinacy and other frameworks. It has been proven by arriving at it via a 15-year-long-process of trying to understand $\mathsf {CMI}$ . Because of this, we feel that it is a theorem proven by the entire community rather than by the authors. We especially thank Hugh Woodin and John Steel for their influential ideas throughout the first 25 years of the $\mathsf {Core\ Model\ Induction}$ .

The history of Theorem 1.4 is as follows. The first author, in [Reference Sargsyan33], stated a conjecture that in his view captured the ideas of the first 15 years of the 2000s – namely, that $\phi \mathsf {\ -\ Minimality}$ and $\neg \ \mathsf {UB-Covering}$ cannot coexist in the short extender region. Unfortunately, very soon after finishing that paper, he realized that the covering conjecture of that paper has to fail in the region of $\mathsf {LSA}$ .Footnote 29 However, no easily quotable theorem was proven by him. It was not until fall of 2018 when the second author was visiting the first author, that they realized that Theorem 1.4 says exactly that $\phi \mathsf {\ -\ Minimality}$ and $\neg \ \mathsf {UB-Covering}$ can coexist in the short extender region.

2. An overview of the fine structure of the minimal $\mathsf {LSA}$ -hod mouse and excellent hybrid mice

As was mentioned above, the proof of Theorem 1.4 is an accumulation of many ideas developed in the last 20 years. We will try to develop enough of the required background in general terms so that a reader familiar with the terminology of descriptive inner model theory can follow the arguments. The main technical machinery used in the proof is developed more carefully in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38]. In the next few sections, we will write an introduction to this technical machinery intended for set theorists who are familiar with [Reference Sargsyan32].

We say that M is a minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ if

  1. 1. $M{\vDash } \mathsf {LSA}$ ,

  2. 2. $M=L(A, \mathbb {R})$ for some $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}$ , and

  3. 3. for any $B\in {\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap M$ such that $w(B)<w(A)$ , $L(B,\mathbb {R}){\vDash } \neg \mathsf {LSA}$ .

It makes sense to talk about ‘the’ minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . When we say M is the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ , we mean that M is a minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ and $Ord, {\mathbb {R}}\subseteq M$ . Clearly from the prospective of a minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ , the universe is the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . The proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 10.3.1] implies that there is a unique minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ such that $Ord, {\mathbb {R}}\subseteq M$ .Footnote 30 This unique minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ is the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ .

One of the main contributions of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] is the detailed description of $V_{\Theta }^{\mathrm {HOD}}$ assuming that the universe is the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . The early chapters of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] deal with what is commonly referred to as the ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ analysis. These early chapters introduce the notion of a short-tree-strategy mouse, which is the most important technical notion studied by [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38]. To motivate the need for this concept, we first recall some of the other aspects of the ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ analysis.

Recall the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ (for example, see [Reference Sargsyan34, Definition 0.9] or [Reference Woodin61, Definition 9.23]). Recall that $\Theta $ is the least ordinal that is not a surjective image of the reals. The $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ is a way of measuring the complexity of the surjections that can be used to map the reals onto the ordinals below $\Theta $ . Assuming $\mathsf {AD}$ , let $(\theta _{\alpha }: {\alpha }\leq \Omega )$ be a closed in $\Theta $ sequence of ordinals such that

  1. 1. $\theta _0$ is the least ordinal $\eta $ such that $\mathbb {R}$ cannot be mapped surjectively onto $\eta $ via an ordinal definable function,

  2. 2. for ${\alpha }+1\leq \Omega $ , fixing a set of reals A such that A has Wadge rank $\theta _{\alpha }$ , $\theta _{{\alpha }+1}$ is the least ordinal $\eta $ such that $\mathbb {R}$ cannot be mapped surjectively onto $\eta $ via a function that is ordinal definable from A,

  3. 3. for limit ordinal ${\lambda }\leq \Omega $ , $\theta _{\lambda }=\sup _{{\alpha }<{\lambda }}\theta _{\alpha }$ , and

  4. 4. $\Omega $ is least such that $\theta _{\Omega }=\Theta $ .

It follows from the definition of $\mathsf {LSA}$ (Definition 1.2) that if ${\kappa }$ is the largest Suslin cardinal, then it is a member of the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ . It is not hard to show that $\mathsf {LSA}$ is a much stronger axiom than $\mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}+ \text {`}\Theta $ is regular’. Under $\mathsf {LSA}$ , letting ${\kappa }$ be the largest Suslin cardinal, there is an $\omega $ -club $C\subseteq {\kappa }$ such that for every ${\lambda }\in C$ , $L(\Gamma _{\lambda }, \mathbb {R}){\vDash } \text {`}\mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}} + {\lambda }=\Theta +\Theta $ is regular’, where $\Gamma _{\lambda }=\{A\subseteq \mathbb {R}: w(A)<{\lambda }\}$ .Footnote 31

Assume now that V is the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . It follows from the work done in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] that for every $\kappa $ that is a member of the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ but is not the largest Suslin cardinal there is a hod pair $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )$ such that

  1. 1. the Wadge rank of $\Sigma $ (or rather the set of reals coding $\Sigma $ ) is $\geq {\kappa }$ and

  2. 2. for some $\eta \in {\mathcal {P}}$ , letting ${\mathcal {M}}_{\infty }({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )$ be the direct limit of all countable $\Sigma $ -iterates ${\mathcal {Q}}$ of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that the iteration embedding $\pi ^\Sigma _{{\mathcal {P}}, {\mathcal {Q}}}$ is defined and letting $\pi ^\Sigma _{{\mathcal {P}}, \infty }:{\mathcal {P}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {M}}_{\infty }({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )$ be the iteration map, then $V_{\kappa }^{\mathrm {HOD}}$ is the universe of ${\mathcal {M}}_{\infty }({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )|\pi ^\Sigma _{{\mathcal {P}}, \infty }(\eta )$ .Footnote 32

A technical reformulation of the above fact appears as [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 7.2.2].

The situation, however, is drastically different for the largest Suslin cardinal. Let ${\kappa }$ be the largest Suslin cardinal. The inner model theoretic object that has Wadge rank $ {\kappa }$ cannot be an iteration strategy. This is because if $\Sigma $ is an iteration strategy with nice properties like hull condensation,Footnote 33 then assuming $\mathsf {AD}$ holds in $L(\Sigma , {\mathbb {R}})$ , $L(\Sigma , {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {M}}_1^{\#, \Sigma }$ exists and is $\omega _1$ -iterable’.Footnote 34 This then easily implies that $\Sigma $ is both Suslin and co-Suslin. It then follows that no nice iteration strategy can have Wadge rank $\geq {\kappa }$ , as any such strategy is both Suslin and co-Suslin.Footnote 35

The inner model theoretic object that has Wadge rank $ {\kappa }$ is a short-tree strategy, which is a partial iteration strategy. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is any iterable structure and $\Sigma $ is its iteration strategy. Suppose ${\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . Given ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Sigma )$ that is based on ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }$ , we say that ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\Sigma $ -short if letting $\Sigma ({\mathcal {T}})=b$ , either the iteration map $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_b$ is undefined or $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_b({\delta })>{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ . If ${\mathcal {T}}$ is not $\Sigma $ -short, then we say that it is $\Sigma $ -maximal. We then set $\Sigma ^{stc}$ be the fragment of $\Sigma $ that acts on short trees.

Following [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 3.1.4], we make the following definition.

Definition 2.1. Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a normal iteration tree of limit length. We then let

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathrm m}({\mathcal{T}})=\cup_{{\alpha} < {\mathrm lh}({\mathcal{T}})}{\mathcal{M}}_{\alpha}^{\mathcal{T}}|{\mathrm lh}(E_{\alpha}^{\mathcal{T}}) \text{ and } {\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal{T}})=({\mathrm m}({\mathcal{T}}))^\#. \end{align*} $$

In the language of the above definition, the convention used in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] is the following: $\Sigma ^{stc}({\mathcal {T}})=b$ if and only if

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\Sigma $ -short and $\Sigma ({\mathcal {T}})=b$ , or

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\Sigma $ -maximal and $b={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ .

Thus, $\Sigma ^{stc}$ tells us the branch of a $\Sigma $ -short tree or the last model of a $\Sigma $ -maximal tree.

The reader can perhaps imagine many ways of defining the notion of short-tree strategy without a reference to an actual strategy. The convention that we adopt in this paper is the following. If $\Lambda $ is a short-tree strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}$ , then we will require that

  1. 1. for some ${\mathcal {P}}$ -cardinal ${\delta }$ , ${\mathcal {P}}=({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta })^\#$ and ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal’,

  2. 2. if ${\delta }$ is as above and $\nu $ is the least $<{\delta }$ -strong cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ , then ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}\nu $ is a limit of Woodin cardinals’,

  3. 3. given an iteration tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Lambda )$ , $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ is either a cofinal well-founded branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ or is equal to ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ ,

  4. 4. for all iteration trees ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Lambda )$ , if $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ is a branch b, then $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_b({\delta })>{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ ,

  5. 5. for all iteration trees ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Lambda )$ , if $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ is a model, then ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

If a hod mouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ has properties 1 and 2 above, then we say that ${\mathcal {P}}$ is of $\#$ -lsa type. [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 2.7.3] introduces other types of LSA hod premice.

The set of reals that has Wadge rank ${\kappa }$ is some short-tree strategy $\Lambda $ . The hod mouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ that $\Lambda $ iterates has a unique Woodin cardinal ${\delta }$ such that if $\nu <{\delta }$ is the least cardinal that is $<{\delta }$ -strong in ${\mathcal {P}}$ , then ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}\nu $ is a limit of Woodin cardinals’. The aforementioned Woodin cardinal ${\delta }$ is also the largest Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . This fact is proven in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] (for example, see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 7.2.2] and [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 8]). There is yet another way that the $\mathsf {LSA}$ stages of the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ are different from other points.

We continue assuming that V is the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . If $\Sigma $ is a strategy of a hod mouse with nice properties, then ordinal definability with respect to $\Sigma $ is captured by $\Sigma $ -mice. More precisely, [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 10.2.1] implies that if x and y are reals, then x is ordinal definable from y using $\Sigma $ as a parameter if and only if there is a $\Sigma $ -mouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ over y Footnote 36 such that $x\in {\mathcal {M}}$ .

[Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 10.2.1] also implies that the same conclusion is true for short-tree strategies. Namely, if $\Lambda $ is a short-tree strategy, then for x and y reals, x is ordinal definable from y using $\Lambda $ as a parameter if and only if there is a $\Lambda $ -mouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ over y such that $x\in {\mathcal {M}}$ . Theorems of this sort are known as $\mathsf {Mouse\ Capturing}$ theorems. Such theorems are very important when analyzing models of determinacy using inner model theoretic tools.

For a strategy $\Sigma $ , the concept of a $\Sigma $ -mouse has appeared in many places. The reader can consult [Reference Sargsyan34, Definition 1.20], but the notion probably was first mentioned in [Reference Steel46] and was finally fully developed in [Reference Schlutzenberg and Trang43].

A $\Sigma $ -mouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ , besides having an extender sequence, also has a predicate that indexes the strategy. The idea, which is due to Woodin, is that the strategy predicate should index the branch of the least tree that has not yet been indexed.

Unfortunately, this idea does not quite work for $\Lambda $ -mice where $\Lambda $ is a short-tree strategy. In the next subsection, we will explain the solution presented in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38].

2.1. Short-tree-strategy mice

We are assuming that V is the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . Suppose $\Lambda $ is a short-tree strategy for a hod mouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ . We let ${\delta }$ be the largest Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . Thus, ${\mathcal {P}}=({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta })^\#$ . In this subsection, we would like to convince the reader that the concept of $\Lambda $ -mouse, while much more involved, behaves very similarly to the concept of a $\Sigma $ -mouse where $\Sigma $ is an iteration strategy.

In general, when introducing any notion of a mouse, one has to keep in mind the procedures that allow us to build such mice. Formally speaking, many notions of $\Lambda $ -mice might make perfect sense, but when we factor into it the constructions that are supposed to produce such mice, we run into a key issue.

In any construction that produces some sort of mouse (e.g., $K^c$ -constructions, fully backgrounded constructions, etc.), there are stages where one has to consider certain kinds of Skolem hulls, or as inner model theorists call them, fine structural cores. The reader can view these cores as some carefuly defined Skolem hulls. To illustrate the aformentioned problem, imagine we do have some notion of $\Lambda $ -mice and let us try to run a construction that will produce such mice. Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a tree according to $\Lambda $ that appears in this construction. Having a notion of a $\Lambda $ -mouse means that we have a prescription for deciding whether $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ should be indexed in the strategy predicate or not.

Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a $\Lambda $ -maximal tree. It is hard to see exactly what one can index so that the strategy predicate remembers that ${\mathcal {T}}$ is maximal. And this ‘remembering’ is the issue. Imagine that at a later stage, we have a Skolem hull $\pi : {\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}$ of our current stage such that ${\mathcal {T}}\in rng(\pi )$ . It is possible that ${\mathcal {U}}=_{def}\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {T}})$ is $\Lambda $ -short. If we have indexed X in our strategy that proves $\Lambda $ -maximality of ${\mathcal {T}}$ , then $\pi ^{-1}(X)$ now can no longer prove that ${\mathcal {U}}$ is $\Lambda $ -maximal. Thus, the notion of $\Lambda $ -mouse cannot be first order.

The solution is simply not to index anything for $\Lambda $ -maximal trees. This does not quite solve the problem as the above situation implies that nothing should be indexed for many $\Lambda $ -short trees as well. To solve this problem, we will only index the branches of some $\Lambda $ -short trees, those that we can locally prove are $\Lambda $ -short. We explain this below in more details.

Fix an lsa type hod premouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ and let $\Lambda $ be its short-tree strategy. Let ${\delta }$ be the largest Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and $\nu $ be the least $<{\delta }$ -strong of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . To explain the exact prescription that we use to index $\Lambda $ , we explain some properties of the models that have already been constructed according to this indexing scheme. Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a $\Lambda $ -premouse.

Call ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ universally short ( $\mathsf {uvs}$ ) if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is obviously short (see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 3.3.2]). For instance, it can be that the $\#$ -operator provides a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure and determines a branch c of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})$ Footnote 37 exists and ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})\unlhd {\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ . Another way that a tree can be obviously short is that there could be a model ${\mathcal {Q}}$ in ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_{{\mathcal {P}}, {\mathcal {Q}}}:{\mathcal {P}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {Q}}$ is defined and the portion of ${\mathcal {T}}$ that comes after ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is based on ${\mathcal {Q}}^b$ . Here, ${\mathcal {Q}}^b$ is defined as ${\mathcal {Q}}|(\kappa ^+)^{\mathcal {Q}}$ , where $\kappa $ is the supremum of the Woodin cardinals below the largest Woodin of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ . The reader should keep in mind that there is a formula $\zeta $ in the language of $\Lambda $ -premice such that for any $\Lambda $ -premouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ and for any iteration tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ , ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ if and only if ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \zeta [{\mathcal {T}}]$ .

Unfortunately, there can be trees that are not universally short ( $\mathsf {nuvs}$ ). Suppose then ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ . In this case, whether we index $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ or not depends on whether we can find a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure that can be authenticated to be the correct one. There can be many ways to certify a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure, and [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] provides one such method. An interested reader can consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 3.7]. Notice that because ${\mathcal {P}}$ has only one Woodin cardinal, not being able to find a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure is equivalent to the tree being maximal. Thus, in a nutshell, the solution proposed by [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] is that we index only branches that are given by internally authenticated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures.

Suppose now that we have the above Skolem hull situation – namely, that we have $\pi :{\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}$ and ${\mathcal {T}}$ in ${\mathcal {N}}$ that is $\Lambda $ -maximal but $\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {T}})$ is short. There is no more indexing problem. The reason is that in order to index $\Lambda (\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {T}}))$ in ${\mathcal {M}}$ , we need to find an authenticated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for $\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {T}})$ . The authentication process is first order, and so if ${\mathcal {N}}$ does not have such an authenticated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {T}}$ , then ${\mathcal {M}}$ cannot have such an authenticated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for $\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {T}})$ .

The reader of this paper does not need to know the exact way the authentication procedure works. However, the reader should keep in mind that the authentication procedure is internal to the mouse. More precisely, the following holds:

Internal Definability of Authentication: there is a formula $\phi $ in the appropriate language such that whenever $({\mathcal {P}}, \Lambda )$ is as above and ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a $\Lambda $ -mouse over some set X such that ${\mathcal {P}}\in X$ , for any iteration tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ , ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \phi [{\mathcal {T}}]$ if and only if ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Lambda )$ , ${\mathcal {T}}$ is short and $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})\in {\mathcal {M}}$ .

We again note that the Internal Definability of Authentication (IDA) is only shown to be true for the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . In general, IDA cannot be true as there can be short trees without ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures. The authors have recently discovered another short-tree indexing scheme that can work in all cases but has some weaknesses compared to the one introduced in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38].

Using the notation in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], recall that ${\mathcal {P}}^b$ is the ‘bottom part’ of ${\mathcal {P}}$ (i.e., ${\mathcal {P}}^b = {\mathcal {P}}|(\nu ^+)^{{\mathcal {P}}}$ , where $\nu $ is the supremum of the Woodin cardinals below the top Woodin of ${\mathcal {P}}$ ).

We now describe another key feature of the indexing scheme of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] that is of importance here. We say $\Sigma $ is a low-level component of $\Lambda $ if there is a tree ${\mathcal {T}}$ on ${\mathcal {P}}$ according to $\Lambda $ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ existsFootnote 38 ( ${\mathcal {T}}$ may be $\emptyset $ ) and for some ${\mathcal {R}}\unlhd \pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}^b)$ , $\Sigma =\Lambda _{\mathcal {R}}$ . Let $LLC(\Lambda )$ be the set of $\Sigma $ that are low-level components of $\Lambda $ . What is shown in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] is that $\Lambda $ is determined by $LLC(\Lambda )$ in a strong sense.

Given a transitive model M of a fragment of $\mathsf {ZFC}$ such that ${\mathcal {P}}\in M$ , we say M is closed under $LLC(\Lambda )$ if whenever ${\mathcal {T}}\in M$ is a tree according to $\Lambda $ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists, $\Lambda _{\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}^b)}$ has a universally Baire representation over M. More precisely, whenever $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , \pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}^b))$ is M-generic, for every M-cardinal ${\lambda }$ , there are trees $T, S\in M[g]$ on ${\lambda }$ such that $M[g]{\vDash } \text {`}(T, S)$ are $<{\lambda }$ -complementing’ and for all $<{\lambda }$ -generics h, $(p[T])^{M[g*h]}=Code(\Lambda _{\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}^b)})\cap M[g*h]$ . Here, $Code(\Phi )$ is the set of reals coding $\Phi $ (with respect to a fixed coding of elements of $HC$ by reals).

It is shown in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] that if, assuming $\mathsf {AD}^+$ , $(M, \Sigma )$ is such that

  1. 1. M is a countable model of a fragment of $\mathsf {ZFC}$ ,

  2. 2. M has a class of Woodin cardinals,

  3. 3. $\Sigma $ is an $\omega _1$ -iteration strategy for M and

  4. 4. whenever $i:M\rightarrow N$ is an iteration via $\Sigma $ , N is closed under $LLC(\Lambda )$ ,

then there is a formula $\psi $ such that whenever g is M-generic, for any ${\mathcal {T}}\in M[g]$ ,

(⋆) $$ \begin{align} {\mathcal{T}} \ \text{is according to } \Lambda \text{ if and only if } M[g]{\vDash} \psi[{\mathcal{T}}]. \end{align} $$

The interested reader can consult Chapters 5, 6 and 8 of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38].

The reason we explained the above is to give the reader some confidence that defining a short-tree strategy $\Lambda $ for a hod premose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is equivalent to describing the set $LLC(\Lambda )$ . This fact is the reason that the indexing schema of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] works in the following sense.

Being able to define short-tree-strategy mice is one thing; proving that they are useful is another. Usually what needs to be shown are the following two key statements. We let $\phi _{sts}$ be the formula that is mentioned in the Internal Definability of Authentication.

The Eventual Authentication. Suppose $({\mathcal {P}}, \Lambda )$ is as above and ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a sound $\Lambda $ -mouse over some set X such that ${\mathcal {P}}\in X$ and ${\mathcal {M}}$ projects to X. Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ is according to $\Lambda $ and is $\Lambda $ -short. Suppose further that ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \neg \phi _{sts}[{\mathcal {T}}]$ . Then there is a sound $\Lambda $ -mouse ${\mathcal {N}}$ over X such that ${\mathcal {M}}\unlhd {\mathcal {N}}$ and ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \phi _{sts}[{\mathcal {T}}]$ .Footnote 39

Mouse Capturing for $\Lambda $ : Suppose $({\mathcal {P}}, \Lambda )$ is as above. Then for any $x\in \mathbb {R}$ that codes ${\mathcal {P}}$ and any $y\in \mathbb {R}$ , y is ordinal definable from x and $\Lambda $ if and only if there is a $\Lambda $ -mouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ over x such that $y\in {\mathcal {M}}$ .

Both The Eventual Authentication and Mouse Capturing for $\Lambda $ are proven in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] (see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 8, Lemma 8.1.3, Lemma 8.1.5] and [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 10.2.1]).

The next subsection discusses the ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure authentication process mentioned above.

2.2. The authentication method

Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is a $\#$ -lsa type hod premouse. Recall from the previous subsections that this means that ${\mathcal {P}}$ has a largest Woodin cardinal ${\delta }$ such that ${\mathcal {P}}=({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta })^\#$ and the least $<{\delta }$ -strong cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ is a limit of Woodin cardinals. We let ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ be the largest Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and ${\kappa }^{\mathcal {P}}$ be the least $<{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ -strong cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . We shall also require that ${\mathcal {P}}$ is tame, meaning that for any $\nu <{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ , if $({\mathcal {P}}|\nu )^\#$ is of lsa type and ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {P}}$ is the largest such that ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}\nu $ is a Woodin cardinal’, then $\nu $ is not overlapped in ${\mathcal {M}}$ .Footnote 40

Our goal here is to explain the ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure authentication procedure employed by [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38]. Recall our discussion of $\mathsf {uvs}$ and $\mathsf {nuvs}$ trees. The ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure authentication procedure applies to only $\mathsf {nuvs}$ trees – trees that are not obviously short.

[Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapters 3.6-3.9] develop the aforementioned authentication procedure. [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 3.8.9, 3.8.16, 3.8.17] introduce the sts indexing scheme. For illustrative purposes, it is better to think of the indexing scheme introduced there as a hierarchy of indexing schemes indexed by ordinals. Naturally, this hierarchy is defined by induction. For illustrative purposes we call ${\gamma }$ th level of the hierarchy $sts_{\gamma }$ . Thus, $sts_{\gamma }({\mathcal {P}})$ is the set of all sts premice that are based on ${\mathcal {P}}$ (i.e., their short-tree-strategy predicate describes a short-tree strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}$ ) and have rank $\leq {\gamma }$ .

To begin the induction, we let $sts_0({\mathcal {P}})$ be the set of all sts premice that do not index a branch for any $\mathsf {nuvs}$ tree. More precisely, if ${\mathcal {M}}\in sts_0({\mathcal {P}})$ and ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(S^{\mathcal {M}})$ , then if $S^{\mathcal {M}}({\mathcal {T}})$ is defined, then ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ .

Below and elsewhere, $S^{\mathcal {M}}$ is the strategy predicate of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Given $sts_{{\alpha }}({\mathcal {P}})$ , we let $sts_{{\alpha }+1}({\mathcal {P}})$ be the set of all sts premice that index branches of those $\mathsf {nuvs}$ trees that have a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure in $sts_{\alpha }({\mathcal {P}})$ . More precisely, suppose ${\mathcal {M}}\in sts_{{\alpha }+1}({\mathcal {P}})$ and ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(S^{\mathcal {M}})$ and $S^{\mathcal {M}}({\mathcal {T}})$ is defined. Then either

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ or

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ and there is ${\mathcal {Q}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ such that ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {Q}}\in sts_{\alpha }({\mathcal {P}})'$ , ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}){\trianglelefteq }{\mathcal {Q}}$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’ but ${\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal with respect to some function definable over ${\mathcal {Q}}$ Footnote 41 and there is a cofinal branch b of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_b$ .

When ${\mathcal {Q}}$ exhibits the properties listed in clause 2, we say that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {T}}$ . It follows from the zipper argument of [Reference Martin and Steel25, Theorem 2.2] that for each ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure ${\mathcal {Q}}$ , there is at most one branch b with properties described in clause 2 above. However, there is nothing that we have said so far that guarantees the uniqueness of the ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure itself. The uniqueness is usually a consequence of iterability and comparison (see [Reference Steel53, Theorem 3.11]).Footnote 42 Thus, to make the definition of $sts_{{\alpha }+1}$ complete, we need to impose an iterability condition on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ .

The exact iterability condition that one needs is stated as clause 5 of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 3.8.9]. This clause may seem technical, but there are good reasons for it. For the purposes of identifying a unique branch b saying that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ in clause 2 is sufficiently iterable in ${\mathcal {M}}$ would have sufficed. However, recall the statement of the Internal Definability of Authentication. The problem is that when we require that an ${\mathcal {M}}$ as above is a $\Lambda $ -premouse, we in addition must say that the branch b that the ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure ${\mathcal {Q}}$ defines is the exact same branch that $\Lambda $ picks. To guarantee this, we need to impose a condition on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ will be iterable not just in ${\mathcal {M}}$ but in V. The easiest way of doing this is to say that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ has an iteration strategy in some derived model as then, using genericity iterations (see [Reference Steel53, Chapter 7.2]), we can extend such a strategy for ${\mathcal {Q}}$ to a strategy that acts on iterations in V.

For limit ${\alpha }$ , $sts_{\alpha }({\mathcal {P}})$ is essentially $\bigcup _{{\beta }<{\alpha }}sts_{\beta }({\mathcal {P}})$ . What has been left unexplained is the kind of strategy that the ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure ${\mathcal {Q}}$ must have in some derived model. Let $\Sigma $ be this strategy. If ${\mathcal {M}}\in sts_{\alpha }({\mathcal {P}})$ is a $\Lambda $ -mouse, then ${\mathcal {Q}}$ must be a $\Lambda _{{\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})}$ -mouse over ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ . Thus, our next challenge is to find a first-order way of guaranteeing that $\Sigma $ -iterates of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ are $\Lambda _{{\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})}$ -mice, even those iterates that we will obtain after blowing up $\Sigma $ via genericity iterations.

The solution that is employed in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] is that if ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a $\Sigma $ -iterate of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and ${\mathcal {U}}\in dom(S^{\mathcal {R}})$ , then ${\mathcal {U}}$ itself is authenticated by the extenders of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Below, we refer to this certification as tree certification. This is again a rather technical notion, but the following essentially illustrates the situation.

Let us suppose ${\mathcal {R}}={\mathcal {Q}}$ and ${\mathcal {U}}\in dom(S^{\mathcal {Q}})$ . The indexing scheme of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] does not index all trees in ${\mathcal {P}}$ . In other words, $S^{\mathcal {M}}$ is never total. $dom(S^{\mathcal {M}})$ consists of trees that are built via a comparison procedure that iterates ${\mathcal {P}}$ to a background construction of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Set ${\mathcal {N}}={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {U}})$ . One requirement is that ${\mathcal {N}}$ also iterates to one such background construction to which ${\mathcal {P}}$ also iterates. Let ${\mathcal {S}}$ be this common background construction and suppose ${\alpha }+1<lh({\mathcal {U}})$ is such that ${\alpha }$ is a limit ordinal. First, assume ${\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ . What is shown in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] is that knowing the branch of ${\mathcal {P}}$ -to- ${\mathcal {S}}$ tree, there is a first-order procedure that identifies the branch of ${\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ , and that procedure is the tree certification procedure applied to ${\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ .

Suppose next that ${\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ . Then because ${\alpha }+1<lh({\mathcal {U}})$ , ${\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ must be short and the branch chosen for it in ${\mathcal {Q}}$ must have a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure ${\mathcal {Q}}_1$ , which is itself an sts mouse. We have that ${\mathcal {Q}}_1\in {\mathcal {Q}}$ and ${\mathcal {Q}}_1$ must have the same certification in ${\mathcal {Q}}$ that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ has in ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Again, the $\mathsf {nuvs}$ trees in ${\mathcal {Q}}_1$ have a tree certification in ${\mathcal {Q}}$ according to the above procedure. The $\mathsf {uvs}$ ones produce another ${\mathcal {Q}}_2\in {\mathcal {Q}}_1$ . Because we cannot have an infinite descent, the definition of tree certification is meaningful.

Remark 2.2. It is sometimes convenient to think of a short-tree strategy as one having two components: the branch component and the model component. Given a short-tree strategy $\Lambda $ , we let $b(\Lambda )$ be the set of those trees ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Lambda )$ such that $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ is a branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ , and we let $m(\Lambda )$ be the set of those trees ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Lambda )$ such that $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ is a model.

The convention adopted in this paper is that if ${\mathcal {T}}\in m(\Lambda )$ , then $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ Footnote 43. Thus, if ${\mathcal {M}}$ is an sts premouse, then $S^{\mathcal {M}}$ is a short-tree strategy in the above sense (i.e., for ${\mathcal {T}}\not \in b(S^{\mathcal {M}})$ , $S^{\mathcal {M}}({\mathcal {T}})$ is simply left undefined).

This ends our discussion of sts premice. Of course, a lot has been left out, and the mathematical details are unfortunately excruciating, but we hope that the reader has gained some level of intuition to proceed with the paper.

In the next subsection, we will deal with one of the most important aspects of hod mice – namely, the generic interpretability of iteration strategies.

2.3. Generic interpretability

There are several situations when one has to be careful when discussing sts premice and $\Lambda $ -premice in general. First, for an iteration strategy $\Sigma $ , ${\mathcal {M}}_1^{\#, \Sigma }$ makes complete sense. It is the minimal active $\Sigma $ -mouse with a Woodin cardinal. For short-tree strategy $\Lambda $ , the situation is somewhat different. The expression ‘ ${\mathcal {M}}_1^{\#, \Lambda }$ is the minimal active $\Lambda $ -mouse with a Woodin cardinal’ does not say much as we do not say how closed ${\mathcal {M}}_1^{\#, \Lambda }$ must be. One must also add statements of the form ‘in which all $\Lambda $ -short trees are indexed’. This is because it could be that $\Lambda $ -premouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ is active and has a Woodin cardinal but there is a $\Lambda $ -short tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ that has not yet been indexed in ${\mathcal {M}}$ (see The Eventual Certification above). In particular, without extra assumptions, it may be the case that given a $\Lambda $ -sts mouse ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \mathsf {ZFC}$ , $\Lambda {\restriction } {\mathcal {M}}$ is not definable over ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Clearly, such definability holds for many strategy mice.

The above issue becomes somewhat of a problem when dealing with generic interpretability, which is the statement that the internal strategy predicate can be uniquely extended onto generic extensions. For ordinary strategy mice, generic interpretability is, in general, easier to prove. For short-tree-strategy mice, the situation is somewhat parallel to the above anomaly. Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a $\Lambda $ -mouse where $\Lambda $ is a short-tree strategy and suppose g is ${\mathcal {M}}$ -generic. In general, we cannot hope to prove that $\Lambda {\restriction } {\mathcal {M}}[g]$ is definable over ${\mathcal {M}}[g]$ . In this subsection, we introduce some properties of short-tree strategies that allow us to prove generic interpretability, albeit in a somewhat weaker sense.

The most important concept that is behind most arguments of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] is the concept of branch condensation (see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 4.9]). It is very possible that the concept of full normalization introduced in [Reference Steel55] can be used instead of branch condensation to obtain a greater generality. In fact, the authors have recently discovered a new notion of a short-tree-strategy mouse utilizing full normalization.

Branch condensation implies generic interpretability. The following is our generic interpretability theorem, which is essentially [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 6.1.5]. The aforementioned theorem is stated for strategies with branch condensation that are associated with a pointclass $\Gamma $ . Here, we need strategies whose association with pointclasses is a consequence of some abstract properties that it has, not something explicitly assumed about them. Such strategies can be obtained working inside a model of determinacy. The specific properties that we need are the following properties:

  1. 1. hull condensation,

  2. 2. strong branch condensation,

  3. 3. branch condensation for pull-backs.

The meaning of clause 3 above is as follows. Suppose $({\mathcal {P}}, \Lambda )$ is an sts hod pair. $\Lambda $ has branch condensation for pullbacks if whenever $\xi \in {\mathcal {P}}$ is a limit of Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathrm cf}(\xi )=\omega '$ and $\pi :{\mathcal {Q}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ is elementary, the $\pi $ -pullback of $\Lambda _{{\mathcal {P}}|\xi }$ has branch condensation. For more on branch condensation, the reader may consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 4.9].

Definition 2.3. We say that a short-tree strategy is splendid if it satisfies the above 3 properties.

Clause 3 above implies that the pullback of splendid strategies are splendid.Footnote 44 It might help to consult Remark 2.2 before reading the next theorem.

Theorem 2.4. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an lsa type hod premouse and $\Lambda $ is a splendid short-tree strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a $\Lambda $ -premouse satisfying $\mathsf {ZFC}$ and that ${\mathcal {N}}$ has unboundedly many Woodin cardinals. Then for any ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic g, $\Psi =_{def}S^{\mathcal {N}}$ has a unique extension $\Psi ^g\subseteq {\mathcal {N}}[g]$ that is definable from $\Psi $ over ${\mathcal {N}}[g]$ and $b(\Psi ^g)\subseteq b(\Lambda ){\restriction } {\mathcal {N}}[g]$ .

Our Theorem 2.4 is weaker than [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 6.1.4]. The conclusion of the aforementioned theorem is that $\Psi ^g=\Lambda {\restriction } {\mathcal {N}}[g]$ . However, in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 6.1.4], ${\mathcal {N}}$ satisfies a strong iterability hypothesis. Without this iterability hypothesis, $b(\Psi ^g)\subseteq b(\Lambda ){\restriction } {\mathcal {N}}[g]$ is all the proof that [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 6.1.4] gives.

In the next subsection, we will introduce a type of short-tree-strategy mouse that we will use to establish Theorem 1.4.

2.4. Excellent hod premice

Our proof of Theorem 1.4 is an example of how one can translate set theoretic strength from one set of principles to another set of principles by using inner model theoretic objects as intermediaries. Below, we introduce the notion of an excellent hybrid premouse. We will then use this notion to show that both $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ hold in a generic extension of an excellent hybrid premouse. Conversely, we will show that in any model of either $\mathsf {Sealing}$ or $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ , there is an excellent hybrid premouse. We start by introducing some terminology and then introduce the excellent hybrid premice.

Remark 2.5. Below and elsewhere, when discussing iterability, we usually mean with respect to the extender sequence of the structures in consideration. Sometimes our definitions will be stated with no reference to such an extender sequence, but these definitions will always be applied in contexts where there is a distinguished extender sequence.

To state our generic interpretability results, we need to introduce a form of self-iterability – namely, window-based self-iterability. We say that $[\nu , {\delta }]$ is a window if there are no Woodin cardinals in the interval $(\nu , {\delta })$ . Given a window w, we let $\nu ^w$ and ${\delta }^w$ be such that $w=[\nu ^w, {\delta }^w]$ . We say that a window w is above ${\kappa }$ if $\nu ^w\geq {\kappa }$ . We say that a window w is not overlapped if there is no $\nu ^w$ -strong cardinal. We say w is maximal if $\nu ^w=\sup \{{\alpha }+1: {\alpha }<\nu ^w$ is a Woodin cardinal $\}$ and ${\delta }^w$ is a Woodin cardinal.

Window-Based Self-Iterability. Suppose ${\kappa }$ is a cardinal. We say $\mathsf {WBSI}$ holds at ${\kappa }$ if for any window w that is above ${\kappa }$ and for any successor cardinal $\eta \in (\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ , setting $Q= H_{\eta ^+}$ , Q has an $Ord$ -iteration strategy $\Sigma $ which acts on iterations that only use extenders with critical points $>\nu ^w$ .

One usually says that Q is $Ord$ -iterable above $\nu ^w$ to mean exactly what is written above.

Definition 2.6. We let $T_0$ be the conjunction of the following statements.

  1. 1. $\mathsf {ZFC}$ .

  2. 2. There are unboundedly many Woodin cardinals.

  3. 3. The class of measurable cardinals is stationary.

  4. 4. No measurable cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals carries a normal ultrafilter concentrating on the set of measurable cardinals.

When we write $M{\vDash } T_0$ and M has a distinguished extender sequence, then we make the tacit assumption that the large cardinals and specific ultrafilters mentioned in Definition 2.6 are witnessed by extenders on the sequence of M.

Definition 2.7. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is hybrid premouse. We say that ${\mathcal {P}}$ is almost excellent if

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } T_0$ .

  2. 2. There is a Woodin cardinal ${\delta }$ of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {P}}_0=_{def}({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta })^{\#}$ is a hod premouse of $\#$ -lsa type’, ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an sts premouse based on ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ and ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}S^{\mathcal {P}}$ , which is a short-tree strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ , is splendid’.

  3. 3. Given any $\tau <{\delta }^{{\mathcal {P}}_0}$ such that $({\mathcal {P}}_0|\tau )^{\#}$ is of $\#$ -lsa type, there is ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {P}}$ such that $\tau $ is a cutpoint of ${\mathcal {M}}$ and ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}\tau $ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

    We say that ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent if in addition to the above clauses, ${\mathcal {P}}$ satisfies the following:

  4. 4. Letting ${\delta }$ be as in clause 2, ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}\mathsf {WBSI}$ holds at ${\delta }$ ’.

If ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent, then we let ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ be the ${\delta }$ of clause 2 above and ${\mathcal {P}}_0=(({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}})^\#)^{\mathcal {P}}$ .

Remark 2.8. In the previous subsection, we were mainly concerned with the structure of hod mice associated with the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . An excellent hybrid premouse is beyond the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . Indeed, the arguments used in the proofs of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Lemma 8.1.10 and Theorem 8.2.6] apply to show that if ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent and ${\lambda }>{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ is a limit of Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {P}}$ , then the (new) derived model at ${\lambda }$ is a model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . It follows from a standard Skolem hull argument and the derived model theorem that there is $A\in {\wp }({\mathbb {R}}^{\mathcal {P}})\cap {\mathcal {P}}$ such that $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}^{\mathcal {P}}){\vDash } \mathsf {LSA}$ .

Nevertheless, everything that we have said in the previous subsection about short-tree strategies and sts mice carries over to the level of excellent hybrid mice. The methods of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] work through the tame Footnote 45 hod mice. The authors recently have discovered a new sts indexing scheme that works for arbitrary hod mice. This work is not relevant to the current work as the indexing of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] just carries over verbatim.

For the rest of this paper, we assume the following minimality hypothesis $\neg (\dagger )$ , where

$(\dagger ):$ In some generic extension, there is a (possibly class-sized) excellent hybrid premouse.

We will periodically remind the reader of this. One consequence of this assumption is the following fact, which roughly says that all local non-Woodin cardinals of a hod premouse (or hybrid premouse) are witnessed by ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures which are initial segments of the model and are tame. It also shows that if ${\mathcal {P}}$ is a hod mouse such that there is an lsa initial segment ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and there is a Woodin cardinal $\delta> o({\mathcal {P}}_0)$ inside ${\mathcal {P}}$ , then we can construct an excellent hybrid premouse in ${\mathcal {P}}$ by essentially performing a fully backgrounded sts construction in ${\mathcal {P}}|\delta $ above ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ (with respect to the short-tree component of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ ).

Proposition 2.9 ( $\neg (\dagger )$ )

Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is a hod premouse. Let $\kappa $ be a measurable limit of Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and let $\xi \leq o^{\mathcal {P}}(\kappa )$ . Suppose $({\mathcal {P}}|\xi )^\#{\vDash } \text {`}\xi $ is a Woodin cardinal’ but either $\xi $ is not the largest Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ or $\xi <o^{\mathcal {P}}(\kappa )$ . Then there is ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {P}}$ such that $\xi $ is a cutpoint in ${\mathcal {M}}$ , $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})\leq \xi $ and ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}\xi $ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

Proof. Towards a contradiction, assume that there is no such ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Suppose first that $\xi $ is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . It must then be a cutpoint cardinal as otherwise we easily get an excellent hybrid premouse by performing a fully backgrounded construction inside ${\mathcal {P}}|\kappa $ with respect to the short-tree component of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ , where ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ is an lsa hod initial segment of ${\mathcal {P}}|\kappa $ . The existence of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ follows from the fact that $({\mathcal {P}}|\xi )^\sharp $ is an lsa initial segment of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and $\xi < o^{\mathcal {P}}(\kappa )$ .

It then follows that there is a Woodin cardinal $\zeta $ of ${\mathcal {P}}$ above $\xi $ . Now we can use [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Lemma 8.1.4] to build an excellent hybrid premouse via a backgrounded construction of ${\mathcal {P}}|\zeta $ as above (with respect to the short-tree component of $({\mathcal {P}}|\xi )^\sharp $ ).

Suppose next that $\xi $ is not a Woodin cardinal. Because no ${\mathcal {M}}$ as above exists, it follows that $\xi <o^{\mathcal {P}}(\kappa )$ . We can now repeat the above steps in $Ult({\mathcal {P}}, E)$ where E is the least extender overlapping $\xi $ .

There are a few important facts that we will need about excellent hybrid premice that one can prove by using more or less standard ideas, and that in one form or another have appeared in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38]. We will use the next subsection recording some of these facts.

2.5. More on self-iterability

Here, we prove that window-based strategy acts on the entire model. The main theorem that we would like to prove is the following.

Theorem 2.10. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse, w is a maximal window of ${\mathcal {P}}$ above ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ and $\eta \in [\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ is a regular cardinal. Let $\Sigma $ be the $Ord$ -strategy of ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ that acts on iterations that are above $\nu ^w$ . Let g be ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic for some poset $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}$ . Then $\Sigma $ has a unique extension $\Sigma ^g$ definable over ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ such that in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ , $\Sigma ^g$ is an $Ord$ -iteration strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}$ that acts on iterations that are based on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and are above $\nu ^w$ .

The proof will be presented as a sequence of lemmas. First we make a few observations. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent and for some ${\mathcal {P}}$ -cardinal $\xi>{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ is a limit of Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {P}}$ , $\pi :{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ is an elementary embedding in ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that ${\mathcal {N}}$ is countable. It follows that $\eta =_{def}\sup (\pi [{\delta }^{\mathcal {N}}])<{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ , and therefore, letting $\Lambda =(\pi $ -pullback of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ ),

(O1) ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}\Lambda ^{stc}$ is a splendid $Ord$ -strategy for ${\mathcal {N}}_0^{\prime }$ ,Footnote 46

(O2) ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {"}{\mathcal {N}}$ is a $\Lambda ^{stc}$ -premouse.Footnote 47

(O3) in ${\mathcal {P}}$ , Theorem 2.4 applies to ${\mathcal {N}}$ and $\Lambda $ .

(O4) if $i:{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}_1$ is such that $\mathrm {crit }(i)>{\delta }^{\mathcal {N}}$ , and for some $\sigma :{\mathcal {N}}_1\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ , $\pi =\sigma \circ i$ , then ${\mathcal {N}}_1$ is a $\Lambda ^{stc}$ -premouse.

(O4) will be key in many arguments in this paper, but often we will ignore stating it for the sake of succinctness. In each case, however, the reader can easily find the realizable embeddings. The reason (O4) is important is that without, it we cannot really prove any self-iterability results, as if iterating ${\mathcal {N}}$ above destroyed the fact that the resulting premouse is a $\Lambda ^{stc}$ -premouse. Then we could not find the relevant ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures using $\Lambda $ or comparison techniques.

Lemma 2.11. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse, w is a maximal window of ${\mathcal {P}}$ above ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ and $\eta \in [\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ is a regular cardinal. Let $\Sigma $ be the $Ord$ -strategy of ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ that acts on iterations that are above $\nu ^w$ . Then $\Sigma $ is an $Ord$ -iteration strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}$ that acts on iterations that are based on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and are above $\nu ^w$ .

Proof. We set $V={\mathcal {P}}$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is an iteration tree on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ according to $\Sigma $ . We can then naturally regard ${\mathcal {T}}$ as a tree on ${\mathcal {P}}$ . We claim that all the models of this tree are well founded. Towards a contradiction, assume not. Fix an inaccessible $\xi>{\delta }^w$ such that when regarding ${\mathcal {T}}$ as a tree on ${\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ , some model of it is ill founded. Let ${\mathcal {T}}^+$ be the result of applying ${\mathcal {T}}$ to ${\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ , and let $\pi : {\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ be such that

  1. 1. $w, {\mathcal {T}}^+ \in rng(\pi )$ ,

  2. 2. ${\vert {\mathcal {M}}\vert }=\eta $ , and

  3. 3. $\mathrm {crit }(\pi )>\eta $ .

Let ${\mathcal {U}}=\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {T}})$ and ${\mathcal {U}}^+=\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {T}}^+)$ . We thus have that some model of ${\mathcal {U}}^+$ is ill founded.

Let ${\mathcal {R}}={\mathcal {P}}|\eta ^+$ and let ${\mathcal {U}}^{\mathcal {R}}$ be the result of applying ${\mathcal {U}}$ to ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Notice that ${\mathcal {M}}\in {\mathcal {R}}$ . Because ${\mathcal {P}}$ has no Woodin cardinals in the interval $(\nu ^w, \eta ^+)$ , we have that ${\mathcal {U}}^{\mathcal {R}}$ is according to any $Ord$ -strategy of ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Thus, ${\mathcal {U}}^{\mathcal {R}}$ only has well-founded models. It is not hard to show, however, that for each ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {U}})$ , if $[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {U}}\cap \mathcal {D}^{\mathcal {U}}=\emptyset $ , then there is an elementary embedding $\sigma _{\alpha }:{\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{{\mathcal {U}}^+}\rightarrow \pi ^{{\mathcal {U}}^{\mathcal {R}}}_{0, {\alpha }}({\mathcal {M}})$ . In the case $[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {U}}\cap \mathcal {D}^{\mathcal {U}}\not =\emptyset $ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{{\mathcal {U}}^+}={\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{\mathcal {U}}={\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{{\mathcal {U}}^{\mathcal {R}}}$ .

In fact, more is true.

Lemma 2.12. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse, w is a maximal window of ${\mathcal {P}}$ above ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ and $\eta \in [\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ is a regular cardinal. Let $\Sigma $ be the $Ord$ -strategy of ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ that acts on iterations that are above $\nu ^w$ . Let $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}$ be a poset and $g\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ be ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. Then $\Sigma $ has a unique extension $\Sigma ^g$ definable over ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ such that in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ , $\Sigma ^g$ is an $Ord$ -iteration strategy for ${\mathcal {Q}}$ acting on iterations that are above $\nu ^w$ .

Moreover, in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ , $\Sigma ^g$ can be regarded as an $Ord$ -iteration strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}$ that acts on iterations that are based on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and are above $\nu ^w$ .Footnote 48

Proof. The proof is by now a standard argument in descriptive inner model theory. It has appeared in several publications. For example, the reader can consult the proof of [Reference Sargsyan34, Lemma 3.9 and Theorem 3.10] or [Reference Sargsyan37, Proposition 1.4-1.7]. We will only give an outline of the proof.

Fix $\zeta $ such that $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}|\zeta $ . Fix now a maximal window v such that $\nu ^v>\max (\zeta , \nu ^w)$ . Let $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi <\Omega )$ be the output of the fully background $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ -construction done over ${\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^w$ with critical point $>\nu ^v$ . Because $\Sigma $ is an $Ord$ -strategy, we must have a $\xi <\Omega $ such that ${\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }$ is a normal iterate of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ via an iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ that is according to $\Sigma $ and is such that the iteration embedding $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}:{\mathcal {Q}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }$ is defined.Footnote 49

Assume now that we have determined that an iteration ${\mathcal {U}}\in {\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^v[g]$ of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is according to $\Sigma ^g$ and has limit length. For simplicity, let us assume ${\mathcal {U}}$ has no drops. We want to describe $\Sigma ^g({\mathcal {U}})$ . Set $\Sigma ^g({\mathcal {U}})=b$ if and only if there is $\sigma :{\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {U}}_b\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }$ such that $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}=\sigma \circ \pi ^{\mathcal {U}}_b$ . To show that this works, we need to show that there is a unique branch b with the desired property. Such a branch b is called $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ -realizable.

Towards a contradiction, assume that either there is no such branch or there are two. Let ${\lambda }=(({\delta }^v)^{+2})^{\mathcal {P}}$ . Let now $\pi :{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|{\lambda }$ be a pointwise definable countable hull of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\lambda }$ . It follows that we can find a maximal window u of ${\mathcal {N}}$ , an ${\mathcal {N}}$ -regular cardinal $\zeta \in (\nu ^u, {\delta }^u)$ , a partial ordering $\mathbb {Q}\in {\mathcal {N}}$ and a maximal window z of ${\mathcal {N}}$ such that

  1. 1. $\mathbb {Q}\in {\mathcal {N}}|\nu ^z$ ,

  2. 2. for some ${\mathcal {W}}$ that is a model appearing in the fully backgrounded construction of ${\mathcal {N}}|{\delta }^z$ done over ${\mathcal {N}}|\nu ^u$ with respect to $S^{\mathcal {N}}$ using extenders with critical points $>\nu ^z$ , there is an iteration ${\mathcal { K}}\in {\mathcal {N}}$ on ${\mathcal {R}}=_{def}{\mathcal {N}}|\zeta $ with last model ${\mathcal {W}}$ such that $\pi ^{\mathcal { K}}$ is defined,

  3. 3. some condition $q\in \mathbb {Q}$ forces that whenever $h\subseteq \mathbb {Q}$ is ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic, there is an iteration ${\mathcal {X}}\in ({\mathcal {N}}|\nu ^z)[h]$ of ${\mathcal {R}}$ with no drops such that either there is no $\pi ^{\mathcal { K}}$ -realizable branch or there are at least two $\pi ^{\mathcal { K}}$ -realizable branches.

Let $h\in {\mathcal {P}}$ be ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic for $\mathbb {Q}$ . Let ${\mathcal {X}}\in ({\mathcal {N}}|\nu ^z)[h]$ be as in clause 3 above. Because $\pi ({\mathcal {R}})$ is fully iterable in ${\mathcal {P}}$ above $\pi (\nu ^u)$ , we have that ${\mathcal {R}}$ is fully iterable in ${\mathcal {P}}$ above $\nu ^u$ . Let b be the branch of ${\mathcal {X}}$ according to the strategy of ${\mathcal {R}}$ that is obtained as the $\pi $ -pullback of the strategy of $\pi ({\mathcal {R}})$ (recall that $\pi ({\mathcal {R}})$ is iterable as a $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ -mouse). Because ${\mathcal {R}}$ has no Woodin cardinals above $\nu ^u$ , we have a largest ${\mathcal {S}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_b$ such that ${\mathcal {S}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {X}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’ but $rud({\mathcal {S}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^{\mathcal {X}}$ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

We claim that

Claim. ${\mathcal {S}}\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ .

Proof. To see this, as ${\mathcal {N}}$ is closed under $\#$ , we can assume that ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {X}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {X}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’. Let ${\mathcal {V}}={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {X}})$ . We now compare ${\mathcal {V}}$ with the construction producing ${\mathcal {W}}$ . As ${\mathcal {W}}$ has no Woodin cardinals above $\nu ^u$ , we get that there are models ${\mathcal {V}}^*{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {V}}^{**}$ appearing on the construction producing ${\mathcal {W}}$ , a tree ${\mathcal {Y}}$ on ${\mathcal {V}}$ and a branch c of ${\mathcal {Y}}$ such that ${\mathcal {V}}^*={\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {Y}}_c$ and ${\mathcal {V}}^{**}$ is the least model appearing on the construction producing ${\mathcal {W}}$ such that ${\mathcal {V}}^{**}{\vDash } \text {`}\pi ^{\mathcal {Y}}_c({\delta }({\mathcal {X}}))$ is a Woodin cardinal’ but $rud({\mathcal {V}}^{**}){\vDash } \text {`}\pi ^{\mathcal {Y}}_c({\delta }({\mathcal {X}}))$ is not a Woodin cardinal’. It follows that ${\mathcal {S}}=Hull_n^{{\mathcal {V}}^{**}}(\{p\}\cup rng(\pi ^{\mathcal {Y}}_c))$ , where n is the fine structural level at which a counterexample to Woodiness of ${\delta }({\mathcal {X}})$ can be defined over ${\mathcal {S}}$ and p is the n-th standard parameter of ${\mathcal {V}}^{**}$ . Because ${\mathcal {V}}^{**}, {\mathcal {Y}}, c\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ , we have that ${\mathcal {S}}\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ .

It now follows that $b\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ , and as ${\mathcal {N}}$ is pointwise definable, we must have that b is $\pi ^{\mathcal { K}}$ -realizable in ${\mathcal {N}}[h]$ (notice that the argument from the above paragraph implies that ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_b$ iterates to ${\mathcal {W}}$ ). If d is another $\pi ^{\mathcal { K}}$ -realizable branch in ${\mathcal {N}}[h]$ (or in ${\mathcal {P}}$ ), then as both ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_b$ and ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_d$ are iterable as $S^{\mathcal {N}}$ -mice, we have that ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_b={\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_d$ . This is a contradiction as ${\delta }({\mathcal {X}})$ is not Woodin in either ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_b$ or ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {X}}_d$ .

In the case ${\mathcal {U}}$ has drops, the argument is very similar to the proof of the claim above. In this case, we cannot hope to find a realizable branch, but we can find the appropriate ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure using the proof of the claim.

Putting the proofs of Lemma 2.11 and Lemma 2.12 together, we obtain the proof of Theorem 2.10.

The proof of Theorem 2.10.

We outline the proof. We use the notation introduced in Theorem 2.10. Let $\xi $ be a ${\mathcal {P}}$ -inaccessible limit of ${\mathcal {P}}$ -Woodin cardinals and such that $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ , and let $\pi :{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ be such that ${\vert {\mathcal {N}}\vert }=\eta $ , $\mathrm {crit }(\pi )>\eta $ and $\mathbb {P}\in rng(\pi )$ . Let $\mathbb {Q}=\pi ^{-1}(\mathbb {P})$ . Let h be ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic for $\mathbb {Q}$ . Notice now that Lemma 2.12 applies both in ${\mathcal {N}}[h]$ and ${\mathcal {P}}[h]$ . Moreover, the proof of Lemma 2.12 shows that

(1) $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {P}}[h]}{\restriction } ({\mathcal {N}}[h])=(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {N}}[h]}$ .

To see (1), notice that as ${\mathcal {Q}}$ has no Woodin cardinals, both $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {P}}[h]}$ and $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {N}}[h]}$ are guided by ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures. To see that (1) holds, we need to show that both $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {P}}[h]}$ and $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {N}}[h]}$ pick the same ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures, and this would follow if we show that the ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures picked by $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {N}}[h]}$ are iterable in ${\mathcal {P}}[h]$ . To see this, we have to recall our definition of $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {N}}[h]}$ . The iterability of any ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure picked by $(\Sigma ^h)^{{\mathcal {N}}[h]}$ is reduced to iterabilty of ${\mathcal {N}}$ in some non-maximal window $u^{\mathcal {N}}$ . The iterability of this window is reduced to the iterability of ${\mathcal {P}}$ in some non-maximal window $\pi (u^{\mathcal {N}})$ , and according to Lemma 2.12, this last iterability holds.

Finally, notice that if we let ${\mathcal {Q}}^+={\mathcal {P}}|(\eta ^+)^{\mathcal {P}}$ and $\Lambda ^h$ be the strategy of ${\mathcal {Q}}^+$ given by Lemma 2.12, $\Lambda ^h_{\mathcal {Q}}=\Sigma ^h$ (again this is simply because they both are ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure guided strategies). It now just remains to repeat the argument from Lemma 2.11. Given any tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ according to $\Sigma ^h$ such that $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ exists, $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ can be applied to ${\mathcal {Q}}^+$ and hence to ${\mathcal {N}}$ . This finishes the proof of Theorem 2.10. $\Box $

2.6. Iterability of countable hulls

Here, we would like to prove that countable hulls of an excellent hybrid premouse have iteration strategies. The reason for doing this is to show that if ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse and g is ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic, then any universally Baire set A in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ is reducible to some iteration strategy which is Wadge below $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ . We will use this to show that $\mathsf {Sealing}$ holds in a generic extension of an excellent hybrid premouse (see Theorem 3.1).

Proposition 2.13. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse and $(w_i: i<\omega )$ are infinitely many consecutive windows of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . Set $\xi =\sup _{i<\omega }{\delta }^{w_i}$ . Suppose $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^{w_0}$ is a poset and $g\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ is ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. Working in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ , let $\pi : {\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|(\xi ^+)^{\mathcal {P}}[g]$ be a countable transitive hull. Then in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ , ${\mathcal {N}}$ has a $\nu ^{w_0}$ -strategy $\Sigma $ that acts on nondropping trees that are based on the interval $[\pi ^{-1}(\nu ^{w_0}), \pi ^{-1}(\xi )]$ .

Proof. Set $u_i=\pi ^{-1}(w_i)$ and $\zeta =\pi ^{-1}(\xi )$ . Our intention is to lift trees from ${\mathcal {N}}$ to ${\mathcal {P}}$ and use ${\mathcal {P}}$ ’s strategy. However, as ${\mathcal {P}}$ -moves, we lose Theorem 2.10; it is now only applicable inside the iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . To deal with this issue, we will use Neeman’s ‘realizable maps are generic’ theorem (see [Reference Neeman31, Theorem 4.9.1]). That it applies is a consequence of the fact that the strategy of ${\mathcal {P}}$ we have described in Theorem 2.10 is unique; thus, the lifted-up trees from ${\mathcal {N}}$ to ${\mathcal {P}}$ pick unique branches (this is a consequence of Steel’s result that UBH holds in mice – see [Reference Steel51, Theorem 3.3] – but can also be proved using methods of Theorem 2.10). One last wrinkle is to notice that when lifting trees from ${\mathcal {N}}$ to ${\mathcal {P}}$ , Theorem 2.10 applies. This is because for each i, $\sup (\pi [{\delta }^{u_i}])<{\delta }^{w_i}$ .

We now describe our intended strategy for ${\mathcal {N}}$ . We call this strategy $\Lambda $ . Notice that if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a normal iteration of ${\mathcal {N}}$ based on the interval $[\nu ^{u_0}, \zeta ]$ , then ${\mathcal {T}}$ can be reorganized as a stack of $\omega $ -iterations $({\mathcal {T}}_i, {\mathcal {N}}_i: i<\omega )$ , where ${\mathcal {N}}_0={\mathcal {N}}$ , ${\mathcal {N}}_{i+1}$ is the last model of ${\mathcal {T}}_i$ and ${\mathcal {T}}_{i+1}$ is the largest initial segment of ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {N}}_i}$ that is based on the window $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_{\leq {\mathcal {N}}_i}}(u_{i+1})$ .

Suppose then ${\mathcal {T}}=({\mathcal {T}}_i, {\mathcal {N}}_i: i<\omega )$ is a normal nondropping iteration of ${\mathcal {N}}$ based on $[\nu ^{u_0}, \zeta ]$ . We say ${\mathcal {T}}$ is according to $\Lambda $ if and only if there is an iteration ${\mathcal {U}}=({\mathcal {U}}_i, {\mathcal {P}}_i: i<\omega )$ of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and embeddings $\pi _i:{\mathcal {N}}_i\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}_i$ such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {P}}_0={\mathcal {P}}$ ,

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {U}}_i=\pi _i{\mathcal {T}}_i$ for each $i<\omega $ ,

  3. 3. ${\mathcal {P}}_{i+1}$ is the last model of ${\mathcal {U}}_i$ for each $i<\omega $ ,

  4. 4. for $i<\omega $ , letting $s_i=\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_{{\mathcal {N}}, {\mathcal {N}}_i}(u_i)$ , ${\lambda }_i=\sup (\pi _i[{\delta }^{s_i}])$ and ${\mathcal {Q}}_i={\mathcal {P}}_i|({\lambda }_i^+)^{{\mathcal {P}}_i}$ , ${\mathcal {P}}_i[g][\pi _i]{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {U}}_i$ is according to the strategy (as described in Lemma 2.12) of ${\mathcal {Q}}_i$ ’.Footnote 50

The reader can now use Theorem 2.10 and Neeman’s aforementioned result to show that ${\mathcal {N}}$ has a $\nu ^{w_0}$ -iteration strategy. The main point is that for any ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic $G \subseteq Coll(\omega ,{\mathcal {T}})$ , in ${\mathcal {P}}[g][G]$ , ${\mathcal {T}}$ is countable, so we can find generics $g_i$ for each i such that $\pi _i\in {\mathcal {P}}_i[g][g_i]$ . Furthermore, ${\mathcal {Q}}_i$ ’s strategy is unique and uniquely extends to all generic extensions of ${\mathcal {P}}_i$ , so the procedure described above can be carried out in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ using the forcing relation of $Coll(\omega , {\mathcal {T}})$ .

2.7. A revised authentication method

Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse. Let g be ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. We would like to know if $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ has a canonical interpretation in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ . That this is possible follows from Theorem 2.4. Perhaps consulting Remark 2.2 will be helpful. However, to make these notions more precise, we will need to dig deeper into the proof of Theorem 2.4 and understand how the definition of $\Psi ^g$ works. For this, we will need to understand expressions such as $\text {`}{\mathcal {Q}}$ is an authenticated sts premouse’. The intended meaning of ‘authenticated’ is the one used in the proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 6.1.5]. More specifically, the interested reader should consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 3.7.3, 3.7.4, 6.2.1 and 6.2.2]. Here, we will briefly explain the meaning of the expression and state a useful consequence of it that equates this notion to the standard notion of being constructed by fully backgrounded constructions (see Remark 2.16). The new key concepts are $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , X)$ -authenticated hybrid premouse and $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , X)$ -authenticated iteration. The essence of these two notions are as follows.

Definition 2.14 (Authenticated hod premouse)

Suppose $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )$ is an sts pair, $X\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}^b$ and ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a hod premouse. We say ${\mathcal {R}}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , X)$ -authenticated if there are

(e1) a $\Sigma $ -iterate ${\mathcal {S}}$ of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that the iteration embedding $\pi :{\mathcal {P}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {S}}$ exists and

(e2) an iteration ${\mathcal {U}}$ of ${\mathcal {R}}$ with last model some ${\mathcal {S}}^b||\xi $ .

The iteration ${\mathcal {U}}$ is constructed using information given by $\pi [X]$ . More precisely, for each maximal window w of ${\mathcal {S}}^b$ , consider

$$ \begin{align*} s(\pi, X, w)=Hull^{{\mathcal{S}}^b}(\pi[X]\cup \nu^w)\cap {\delta}^w. \end{align*} $$

It is required that for each limit ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {U}})$ , if $c=[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {U}}$ , then one of the following two conditions holds:

(C1) ${\mathcal {S}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ is not a Woodin cardinal’, ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ exists and ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }){\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {S}}$ .

(C2) ${\mathcal {S}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ is a Woodin cardinal’ and letting w be the maximal window of ${\mathcal {S}}$ such that ${\delta }^w={\delta }({\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ , $s(\pi , X, w)\subseteq rng(\pi ^{{\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }}_c)$ .

Usually, X is chosen in a way that for each window w of ${\mathcal {S}}$ , $\sup (s(\pi , X, w))={\delta }^w$ . For such X, conditions (C1) and (C2) completely determine ${\mathcal {U}}$ .

Given a hod premouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ of lsa type, a set $X\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}^b$ and a set $\Gamma $ consisting of iterations of ${\mathcal {P}}$ we can similarly define $({\mathcal {P}}, \Gamma , X)$ -authenticated hod premice.

Definition 2.15 (Authenticated iteration)

Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , X)$ authenticated hybrid premouse and ${\mathcal {W}}$ is an iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ . We say ${\mathcal {W}}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , X)$ -authenticated if there is a triple $({\mathcal {S}}, {\mathcal {U}}, \xi )$ $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , X)$ -authenticating ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $\pi ^{\mathcal {U}}$ -exists and ${\mathcal {W}}$ is according to $\pi ^{\mathcal {U}}$ -pullback of $\Sigma _{{\mathcal {S}}||\xi }$ .

Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is an sts premouse based on ${\mathcal {P}}$ and g is ${\mathcal {M}}$ -generic for a poset in ${\mathcal {M}}|\zeta $ . Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}\in {\mathcal {M}}|\zeta [g]$ is an lsa type hod premouse such that ${\mathcal {R}}^b$ is $({\mathcal {P}}, {\mathcal {S}}^{\mathcal {M}}, {\mathcal {P}}^b)$ -authenticated and ${\mathcal {R}}=({\mathcal {R}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}})^\#$ . In ${\mathcal {M}}[g]$ , we can build an sts premouse ${\mathcal {W}}$ based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ using $({\mathcal {P}}, S^{\mathcal {M}}, {\mathcal {P}}^b)$ -authenticated iterations. This means that whenever ${\mathcal {U}}$ is an iteration indexed in ${\mathcal {W}}$ , ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {U}})$ is a limit ordinal such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }, b}$ exists and ${\mathcal {X}}$ is the longest initial segment of ${\mathcal {U}}_{\geq {\alpha }}$ that is based on ${\mathcal {V}}=_{def}({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{\mathcal {U}})^b$ ; then both ${\mathcal {V}}$ and ${\mathcal {X}}$ are $({\mathcal {P}}, S^{\mathcal {M}}, {\mathcal {P}}^b)$ -authenticated. In addition to the above, we also require that if ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for some $\mathsf {nuvs}$ tree in ${\mathcal {W}}$ that has been authenticated by ${\mathcal {W}}$ via the authentication procedure used in sts premice, then any iteration indexed in ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}, {\mathcal {P}}^b, S^{\mathcal {M}})$ -authenticated. Moreover, the same holds for all iterates of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ via the strategy witnessing that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is authenticated in ${\mathcal {W}}$ .

It is important to keep in mind that the above construction may fail simply because some non- $({\mathcal {P}}, S^{\mathcal {M}}, {\mathcal {P}}^b)$ -authenticated object has been constructed. Also, the same construction can be done using $({\mathcal {P}}, S^{\mathcal {M}}, X)$ -authenticated objects where $X\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}^b$ .

Remark 2.16. Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is an sts premouse based on ${\mathcal {P}}$ and g is ${\mathcal {M}}$ -generic for a poset in ${\mathcal {M}}|\zeta $ . Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}\in {\mathcal {M}}|\zeta [g]$ is an lsa type hod premouse such that ${\mathcal {R}}^b$ is $({\mathcal {P}}, {\mathcal {P}}^b, S^{\mathcal {M}})$ -authenticated and ${\mathcal {R}}=({\mathcal {R}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}})^\#$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ has a Woodin cardinal ${\delta }$ above $\zeta $ . To say that an sts premouse ${\mathcal {Q}}$ over ${\mathcal {R}}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}, {\mathcal {P}}^b, S^{\mathcal {M}})$ -authenticated is equivalent to saying that ${\mathcal {Q}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {W}}$ , where ${\mathcal {W}}$ is a model in the $({\mathcal {M}},{\mathcal {P}}^b)$ -authenticated fully backgrounded construction described in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 6.2.2].

The reader may be wondering why it is enough to only authenticate the lower-level iterations. The reason is that in many situations, the lower-level strategies define the entire short-tree strategy. This point was explained in Section 2.1.

The construction mentioned in Remark 2.16 is called the $({\mathcal {P}}, X, S^{\mathcal {M}})$ -authenticated hod pair construction over ${\mathcal {R}}$ . The details of everything that we have said above appears in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 6.2]. The reader may choose to consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 6.2.2].

2.8. Generic interpretability

In this portion of the current section, we would like to outline the proof of generic interpretability. As was mentioned before, generic interpretability is somewhat tricky for short-tree strategies. This is because given a $\Lambda $ -sts premouse ${\mathcal {N}}$ and a tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ , ${\mathcal {T}}$ may be short, but ${\mathcal {N}}[h]$ may not be able to find the branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ that is according to $\Lambda $ , as this branch might have a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure that is more complex than ${\mathcal {N}}$ .

Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse. For the purposes of this paper, we say that ${\mathcal {P}}$ satisfies weak generic interpretability if for every poset $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}$ and for every ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic $g\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ , there is an sts strategy $\Lambda $ for ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ Footnote 51 that is definable (with parameters) over ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ such that for every tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Lambda )$ ,

  1. 1. if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ , then letting $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})=c$ , either

    1. (a) for some node ${\mathcal {R}}$ of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_{\leq {\mathcal {R}}}, b}$ is defined, ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {R}}}$ is a tree on ${\mathcal {R}}^b$ and ${\mathcal {T}}^\frown \{c\}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}_0, {\mathcal {P}}_0^b, S^{\mathcal {P}})$ -authenticated, or

    2. (b) for some node ${\mathcal {R}}$ of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_{\leq {\mathcal {R}}}, b}$ is defined, ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {R}}}$ is a tree on ${\mathcal {R}}^b$ that is above $Ord\cap {\mathcal {R}}^b$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})$ exists and ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}}){\trianglelefteq } {\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ ,

  2. 2. if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ , then letting $c=\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})$ , c is a cofinal branch if and only if ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})$ exists and ${\mathcal {T}}^\frown \{c\}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}_0, {\mathcal {P}}_0^b, S^{\mathcal {P}})$ -authenticated.

Proposition 2.17. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an excellent hybrid premouse. Then ${\mathcal {P}}$ satisfies weak generic interpretability.

Proof. We outline the proof, as the proof is very much like the proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 6.1.5]. Let g be ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. The definition of $\Lambda $ essentially repeats the above clauses. We first consider trees that are $\mathsf {uvs}$ .

Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is an $\mathsf {uvs}$ tree according to $\Lambda $ , and suppose that for some node ${\mathcal {R}}$ on ${\mathcal {T}}$ , $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_{\leq {\mathcal {R}}}, b}$ exists and ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {R}}}$ is a tree based on ${\mathcal {R}}^b$ . Because ${\mathcal {T}}$ is according to $\Lambda $ , we may assume that ${\mathcal {R}}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}_0, {\mathcal {P}}_0^b, S^{\mathcal {P}})$ -authenticated. Thus, we can fix a window w of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that g is $<\nu ^w$ -generic over ${\mathcal {P}}$ , and letting ${\mathcal {W}}$ be the iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ constructed by the fully backgrounded hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^w$ using extenders with critical point $>\nu ^w$ , we can find an embedding $\sigma :{\mathcal {R}}^b\rightarrow {\mathcal {W}}^b$ such that

(a) $\pi ^{{\mathcal {U}}, b}=\sigma \circ \pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_{\leq {\mathcal {R}}}, b}$ , where ${\mathcal {U}}$ is the ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ -to- ${\mathcal {W}}$ tree according to $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ and

(b) ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {R}}}$ is according to the $\sigma $ -pullback of $S^{\mathcal {P}}_{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ .

Letting c be the branch according to the strategy as in (b), we have that ${\mathcal {T}}^\frown \{c\}$ is $({\mathcal {P}}_0, {\mathcal {P}}_0^b, S^{\mathcal {P}})$ -authenticated. Moreover, there is only one such branch c. To see this, we need to reflect.

Let $\xi $ be large and let $\pi :{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ be a countable hull. Fix an ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic $h\in {\mathcal {P}}$ . Let ${\mathcal {U}}\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ be an $\mathsf {uvs}$ tree on ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ such that for some node ${\mathcal {S}}$ on ${\mathcal {U}}$ with the property that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {U}}, b}$ exists, ${\mathcal {U}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}}$ is a normal tree on ${\mathcal {S}}^b$ , and moreover, ${\mathcal {U}}$ is $({\mathcal {N}}_0, {\mathcal {N}}_0^b, S^{\mathcal {N}})$ -authenticated in ${\mathcal {N}}[h]$ . Suppose now that there are two distinct branches c and d obtained in the above manner. We can then fix ${\mathcal {N}}$ -windows $u_1, u_2$ that play the role of w above and build ${\mathcal { K}}_1$ and ${\mathcal { K}}_2$ , the equivalents of ${\mathcal {W}}$ above, inside ${\mathcal {N}}|{\delta }^{u_1}$ and ${\mathcal {N}}|{\delta }^{u_2}$ . For $i\leq 2$ , we have maps $m_i:{\mathcal {S}}^b\rightarrow {\mathcal { K}}^b_i$ and $S^{\mathcal {N}}$ -iteration maps $\tau _i:{\mathcal {N}}_0^b\rightarrow {\mathcal { K}}^b_i$ such that $\tau _i=m_i\circ \pi ^{{\mathcal {U}}_{\leq {\mathcal {S}}}, b}$ . Let $\tau _i: {\mathcal { K}}^b_i \rightarrow \mathcal {Y}$ be the comparison map using strategies $(S^{\mathcal {N}})_{{\mathcal { K}}^b_i}$ . Then, for $i\in \{c,d\}$ , there is an embedding ${\lambda }_i: {\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {U}}_i \rightarrow \mathcal {Y}$ that factors into the iteration map from ${\mathcal {N}}_0^b$ to $\mathcal {Y}$ . It is then easy to see, using branch condensation of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ and its $\pi $ -pullback, that $c = d$ .

The rest of the argument is very similar. For example, we outline the proof of clause 2 in the definition of weak generic interpretability. Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ and ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is a $({\mathcal {P}}_0, {\mathcal {P}}_0^b, S^{\mathcal {P}})$ -authenticated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {T}}$ . We want to see that there is a cofinal well-founded branch $c\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})={\mathcal {Q}}$ . As above, instead of working with ${\mathcal {P}}$ , we can work with a reflection. Thus, we assume that $\pi :{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi $ is a countable elementary embedding, $h\in {\mathcal {P}}$ is ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic and ${\mathcal {T}}, {\mathcal {Q}}\in {\mathcal {N}}[h]$ . Moreover, we can assume that ${\mathcal {N}}$ is pointwise definable. Let $\Psi $ be the $\pi $ -pullback of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ . As ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is $({\mathcal {N}}_0, {\mathcal {N}}_0^b, S^{\mathcal {N}})$ -authenticated, it follows from Theorem 2.13 that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ has an iteration strategy as a $\Psi _{{\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})}$ -sts premouse. Let c be the branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ according to $\Psi $ . As ${\mathcal {N}}$ is pointwise definable, we have that ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})$ -exists, and hence, ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})={\mathcal {Q}}$ .

Next, we show that the low-level strategies are, in fact, universally Baire. However, Proposition 2.21 shows that $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ itself does not have a universally Baire representation.

Proposition 2.18. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent, g is ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic and $\Sigma $ is the generic interpretation of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ onto ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ . Let ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ be an iteration tree on ${\mathcal {P}}$ of length $<\omega _1^{{\mathcal {P}}[g]}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ -exists. Set ${\mathcal {R}}=\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}^b)$ . Then $(\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}{\restriction } HC^{{\mathcal {P}}[g]})\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ . Moreover, for any ${\mathcal {P}}$ -cardinal $\eta $ , there are $\eta $ -complementing trees $T, S\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ such that for all posets $\mathbb {Q}\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ such that ${\vert {\mathbb {Q}}\vert }^{{\mathcal {P}}[g]}<\eta $ and for all ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic $h\subseteq \mathbb {Q}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} (p[T])^{{\mathcal{P}}[g*h]}=\Sigma_{\mathcal{R}}^h{\restriction} HC^{{\mathcal{P}}[g*h]}. \end{align*} $$

Proof. We again outline the proof as the proof uses standard ideas. Let w be a maximal window of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that g is generic for a poset in ${\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^w$ . We now outline the construction producing $\nu ^w$ -complementing trees $(T, S)$ as in the statement of the proposition.

Let ${\mathcal {S}}$ be the model appearing on the hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^w$ in which extenders used have critical points $>\nu ^w$ and to which ${\mathcal {R}}$ normally iterates via $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}$ . Let $i: {\mathcal {R}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {S}}$ be the iteration embedding. What we need to show is that club many hulls of ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ are correct about $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}$ , where we take $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}$ to be defined as i-pullback of the strategy of ${\mathcal {S}}$ that ${\mathcal {S}}$ inherits from ${\mathcal {P}}$ (see Theorem 2.12). That this works follows from the fact that the strategy of ${\mathcal {S}}$ has hull condensation. Let $\Psi $ be the strategy of ${\mathcal {S}}$ .

More precisely, let $\phi (x, {\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {S}}, i)$ be the formula that says ‘ $x\in {\mathbb {R}}$ codes an iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ that is according to the i-pullback of $\Psi $ ’. Clearly, $\phi $ defines $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}{\restriction } HC^{{\mathcal {P}}[g]}$ . Let now $\xi $ be large and $\pi :{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|\xi [g]$ be countable such that ${\mathcal {R}}, (i, {\mathcal {S}})\in rng(\pi )$ . Let $\Phi =\pi ^{-1}(\Psi )$ and $j=\pi ^{-1}(i)$ . Let $h\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ be a $<\pi ^{-1}(\nu ^w)$ -generic over ${\mathcal {N}}$ and let ${\mathcal {U}}\in {\mathcal {N}}[g]$ be a tree on ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

Suppose first that ${\mathcal {N}}[h]{\vDash } \text {`}j{\mathcal {U}}$ is according to the strategy of $\Phi ^h$ ’. Because $\Phi ^h$ is the $\pi $ -pullback of $\Psi $ , we have that $i{\mathcal {U}}=\pi (j{\mathcal {U}})$ is according to $\Psi $ . Hence, ${\mathcal {U}}$ is according to $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}$ .

Next, suppose that ${\mathcal {U}}$ is according to $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}$ . It then follows by the above reasoning that ${\mathcal {N}}[h]{\vDash } \text {`}j{\mathcal {U}}$ is according to the strategy of $\Phi ^h$ ’. This finishes the proof that $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}$ has a uB representation. The rest of the proposition follows from the fact that the formula $\phi $ above defines $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}$ in all $<\nu ^w$ -generic extensions of ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ . Such calculations were carried out more carefully in [Reference Sargsyan34] and also in [Reference Sargsyan37]. In particular, the reader may wish to consult [Reference Sargsyan37, Proposition 1.4].

2.9. Fully backgrounded constructions inside excellent hybrid premice

Given an excellent hybrid premouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ , we would eventually like to show that collapsing $(({\delta }^{\mathcal {P}})^+)^{\mathcal {P}}$ to be countable forces both $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ . Such an analysis of generic extensions of fine structural models usually requires some kind of reconstructibility property, which guarantees that the model can somehow see versions of itself inside it. In this subsection, we would like to establish some such facts about excellent hybrid premice. Proposition 2.19 is a key proposition that we will need in this paper. Recall the definition of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ from Definition 2.7.

Proposition 2.19. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent and g is ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. Let $\Sigma $ be the generic interpretation of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ onto ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ and suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a $\Sigma $ -maximal iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ . Let w be a maximal window of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that w is above ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ , g is generic for a poset in ${\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^w$ and ${\mathcal {R}}\in {\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^w[g]$ . Let $\xi <{\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}^b}$ be a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ is the output of the fully backgrounded hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^w[g]$ done relative to $\Sigma _{{\mathcal {R}}|\xi }$ and over ${\mathcal {R}}|\xi $ and using extenders with critical points $>\nu ^w$ . Then $Ord\cap {\mathcal {N}}_0={\delta }^w$ .

Proof. Towards a contradiction, suppose that $\eta =_{def}Ord\cap {\mathcal {N}}_0<{\delta }^w$ . We will now work towards showing that $\eta $ is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . As $\eta \in (\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ , this is clearly a contradiction. Suppose then $\eta $ is not a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ . As ${\mathcal {P}}$ has no Woodin cardinals in the interval $(\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ , we must have that there is a $\Sigma $ -mouse ${\mathcal {P}}|\eta {\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {Q}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {P}}$ such that $\eta $ is a cutpoint of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}{\vDash } \text {`}\eta $ is a Woodin cardinal’ but $\eta $ is not Woodin relative to functions definable over ${\mathcal {Q}}$ . Unfortunately, ${\mathcal {Q}}$ cannot be translated into a $\Sigma _{{\mathcal {N}}_0}$ -mouse, but we can rebuild it in a sufficiently rich model extending ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ .

Let ${\mathcal {N}}$ be the output of a fully backgrounded construction of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^w[g]$ done with respect to $\Sigma _{{\mathcal {N}}_0}$ and over ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ using extenders with critical point $>\eta $ . As ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ is a $\Sigma $ -maximal iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ ,Footnote 52 we have that ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}\eta $ is a Woodin cardinal’. We now want to rebuild ${\mathcal {Q}}$ inside ${\mathcal {N}}[{\mathcal {P}}|\eta ]$ . The idea here goes back to [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 8.1.13] (for instance, the construction of ${\mathcal {N}}_2$ in the proof of the aforementioned theorem). Notice that if p is the ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ -to- ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ -iteration,Footnote 53 then $\pi ^{p, b}$ exists and $\pi ^{p, b}\in {\mathcal {N}}[{\mathcal {P}}|\eta ]$ . Let $X=\pi ^{p, b}[{\mathcal {P}}_0^b]$ . Working inside ${\mathcal {N}}[{\mathcal {P}}|\eta ]$ , we can build a $\Sigma $ -premouse over ${\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ via a fully backgrounded $({\mathcal {N}}_0, X, S^{\mathcal {N}})$ -authenticated construction. In this construction, we only use extenders with critical point $>\eta $ . Let ${\mathcal {W}}$ be the output of this construction. As ${\mathcal {W}}$ is universal, we have that ${\mathcal {Q}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {W}}$ . Thus, ${\mathcal {N}}[{\mathcal {P}}|\eta ]{\vDash } \text {`}\eta $ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

However, standard arguments show that ${\mathcal {N}}[{\mathcal {P}}|\eta ]{\vDash } \text {`}\eta $ is a Woodin cardinal’. Indeed, let $f:\eta \rightarrow \eta $ be a function in ${\mathcal {N}}[{\mathcal {P}}|\eta ]$ . Because ${\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ is added by an $\eta $ -cc poset, we can find $g\in {\mathcal {N}}$ such that for every ${\alpha }<\eta $ , $f({\alpha })<g({\alpha })$ . Let $E\in \vec {E}^{{\mathcal {N}}_0}$ be any extender witnessing Woodiness for g and such that ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}\nu _E$ is a measurable cardinal’. Thus, $\pi ^{{\mathcal {N}}_0}_E(g)(\kappa )<\nu _E$ , where $\kappa $ is the critical point of E. Let F be the resurrection of E. We must have that $\pi ^{\mathcal {P}}_F(f)(\kappa )<\nu _E$ . Thus, $F{\restriction } \nu _E\in {\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ is an extender witnessing Woodinness for f in ${\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ and hence in ${\mathcal {N}}[{\mathcal {P}}|\eta ]$ .

Using Proposition 2.19, we can now prove that $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ itself is not a universally Baire set. Its proof requires a few more facts from [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], which we now review. Given an lsa type pair $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )$ , following [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 3.3.9], we let $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )$ be the set of all $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}$ such that for some countable iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists, A is Wadge reducible to $\Sigma _{\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}^b)}$ . The following comparison theorem is essentially [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 4.13.1].

Theorem 2.20. Assume $\mathsf {AD}^+$ and suppose $({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )$ and $({\mathcal {Q}}, \Lambda )$ are two lsa type hod pairs such that $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma )=\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {Q}}, \Lambda )$ and both $\Sigma $ and $\Lambda $ are splendid. Then there is an lsa type hod pair $({\mathcal {R}}, \Psi )$ such that ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a $\Sigma $ -iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and a $\Lambda $ -iterate of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and $\Sigma _{\mathcal {R}}=\Psi =\Lambda _{\mathcal {R}}$ .

Proposition 2.21. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent and g is ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. Let $\Sigma $ be the generic interpretation of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ onto ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ . Then ${\mathcal {P}}[g] \vDash \Sigma \notin \Gamma ^{\infty }$ .

Proof. Towards a contradiction, suppose that ${\mathcal {P}}[g]{\vDash } \Sigma ^g \in \Gamma ^{\infty }$ . Let $(w_i: i<\omega )$ be a sequence of successive windows of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that g is generic over a poset in ${\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^{w_0}$ . Set ${\delta }_i={\delta }^{w_i}$ .

For each i, let ${\mathcal {P}}_i$ be the $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ -iterateFootnote 54 built via the fully backgrounded hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }_i$ using extenders with critical points $>\nu _i^{w_i}$ . It follows from Proposition 2.19 that

(1) ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {P}}_i}={\delta }_i$ , i.e., ${\delta }_i$ is the largest Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}_i$ .

Fix now $k\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\delta }_{\omega })$ generic over ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ , where ${\delta }_{\omega }=\sup _{i<\omega }{\delta }_i$ . Recall next that Steel showed that if there are unboundedly many Woodin cardinals, then every universally Baire set has a universally Baire scale (see [Reference Steel47, Theorem 4.3]).Footnote 55 Let now W be the derived model of ${\mathcal {P}}$ as computed in ${\mathcal {P}}[m]$ where $m=g*k$ . It follows that

(2) the canonical set of reals coding $\Sigma ^m{\restriction } HC^W$ Footnote 56 has a scale in W.

This paragraph will be using Theorem 2.20 and the notation introduced there. Working inside W, let $\Gamma =\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}_0, \Sigma ^m)$ . Thus, $\Gamma $ is the set of reals that are generated by the low-level-components of $\Sigma ^m$ . More precisely, $A\in \Gamma $ if there is an iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ on ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ according to $\Sigma ^m$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists and A is Wadge below $\Sigma ^m_{\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}_0^b)}$ . As $\Sigma ^m{\restriction } HC^W$ is Suslin, co-Suslin in W, we must have a hod pair $({\mathcal {S}}, \Lambda )\in W$ such that $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {S}}, \Lambda )=\Gamma $ (this follows from the Generation of Mouse Full Pointclasses; see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 10.1.2]). We can further assume that ${\mathcal {S}}$ is a $\Sigma ^m$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ and $\Lambda ^{stc}=\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {S}}}{\restriction } HC^W$ (this extra possibility follows from Theorem 2.20).

Fix now $i<\omega $ such that letting $n=k\cap Coll(\omega , {\delta }_i)$ , ${\mathcal {P}}[g*n]$ has a uB representation of $\Lambda $ . It now follows that since

(3) ${\mathcal {P}}_{i+1}$ is a $\Lambda $ -iterate of ${\mathcal {S}}$ and

(4) letting $l:{\mathcal {S}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}_{i+1}$ be the iteration embedding, $l[{\delta }^{\mathcal {S}}]$ is cofinal in ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {P}}_{i+1}}$ ,

we have

$$ \begin{align*} {\delta}^{{\mathcal{P}}_{i+1}}<{\delta}_{i+1}. \end{align*} $$

This directly contradicts (1).

2.10. Constructing an iterate via fully backgrounded constructions

Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is strategy-hybrid $\eta $ -iterable mouse such that ${\mathcal {M}}\in V_{\eta }$ , $\eta $ is an inaccessible cardinal and ${\mathcal {M}}$ has an $\eta $ -strategy with hull condensation. Thus, ${\mathcal {M}}$ has an extender sequence $\vec {E}$ and a strategy predicate $S^{\mathcal {M}}$ , which can be a strategy of ${\mathcal {M}}$ itself (as in hod mice) or a strategy of some ${\mathcal {N}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ . We want to build an iterate ${\mathcal {X}}$ of ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that the extenders of ${\mathcal {X}}$ are all fully backgrounded. Here, we describe this construction.

We say $({\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {T}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }: \xi <\iota )$ are the models and iterations of the fully backgrounded $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ -iterate-construction of $V_{\eta }$ if the following conditions are satisfied with ${\alpha }_{\xi }=Ord\cap {\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }$ .

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {V}}_0={\mathcal {W}}_0=J_0^{\mathcal {M}}$ .

  2. 2. For every $\xi <\iota $ , ${\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }={\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }|{\alpha }_{\xi }$ .

  3. 3. For $\xi <\iota $ , ${\mathcal {T}}_{\xi }$ is an iteration of ${\mathcal {M}}$ according to $\Sigma $ with last model ${\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }$ such that ${\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }={\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }|{\alpha }_{\xi }$ and the generators of ${\mathcal {T}}_{\xi }$ are contained in ${\alpha }_{\xi }$ .Footnote 57

  4. 4. For $\xi <\iota $ , if ${\alpha }_{\xi }\in dom(\vec {E}^{{\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }})\cup dom(S^{{\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }})$ , then ${\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }= {\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }||{\alpha }_{\xi }$ .

  5. 5. For $\xi <\iota $ , if ${\alpha }_{\xi }\not \in (dom(\vec {E}^{{\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }})\cup dom(S^{{\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }}))$ and ${\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }\not ={\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }$ , then ${\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }=J_1({\mathcal {V}}_{\xi })$ .

  6. 6. For $\xi <\iota $ , if there is a total extender $F\in V_{\eta }$ such that

    $$ \begin{align*} \pi_F(({\mathcal{V}}_{\zeta}, {\mathcal{W}}_{\zeta}, {\mathcal{T}}_{\zeta}, {\mathcal{X}}_{\zeta}: \zeta<\xi)){\restriction} \xi=({\mathcal{V}}_{\zeta}, {\mathcal{W}}_{\zeta}, {\mathcal{T}}_{\zeta}, {\mathcal{X}}_{\zeta}: \zeta<\xi), \end{align*} $$
    then $F\cap {\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }=E_{{\alpha }_{\xi }}^{{\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }}$ . It follows that ${\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }=({\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }, E_{{\alpha }_{\xi }}^{{\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }})$ .
  7. 7. For $\xi +1<\iota $ , ${\mathcal {V}}_{\xi +1}=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {W}}_{\xi })$ .

  8. 8. If $\xi <\iota $ is limit, then ${\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }=liminf_{\zeta \rightarrow \xi }{\mathcal {W}}_{\zeta }$ and ${\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }=C({\mathcal {W}}_{\xi })$ . More precisely, given ${\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }|\kappa $ , ${\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }|(\kappa ^+)^{{\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }}$ is the eventual value of ${\mathcal {W}}_{\zeta }|(\kappa ^+)^{{\mathcal {W}}_{\zeta }}$ .

We then let $\mathsf {FBIC}({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma , \eta )$ be the models and iterations of the above construction. We can vary this construction in two ways. The first way is that fixing some ${\lambda }<\eta $ , we can require that the extender F in clause 6 has critical point $>{\lambda }$ . This amounts to backgrounding extenders via total extenders that have critical points $>{\lambda }$ . The second way is that we may choose to start the construction with any initial segment of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . More precisely, given a cardinal cutpoint $\nu $ of ${\mathcal {M}}$ , we can start by setting ${\mathcal {V}}_0={\mathcal {M}}|\nu $ .

Thus, by saying that $({\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {T}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }: \xi <\iota )$ are the models and iterations of the $\mathsf {FBIC}({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma , \eta , {\lambda }, \nu )$ , we mean that the sequence is built as above but starting with ${\mathcal {M}}|\nu $ and using backgrounded extenders that have critical points $>{\lambda }$ .

$\mathsf {FBIC}({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma , \eta , {\lambda }, \nu )$ can break without reaching its eventual goal. We say

$$ \begin{align*} \mathsf{FBIC}({\mathcal{M}}, \Sigma, \eta, {\lambda}, \nu) \end{align*} $$

is successful if one of the following conditions holds.

  1. 1. $\iota =\xi +1$ , $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_{\xi }}$ exists and either ${\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }={\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }$ or ${\mathcal {W}}_{\xi }={\mathcal {X}}_{\xi }$ ,

  2. 2. $\iota $ is a limit ordinal and $liminf_{\xi \rightarrow \iota }{\mathcal {V}}_{\xi }$ is the last model of a normal $\Sigma $ -iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ of ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ exists.

If $\mathsf {FBIC}({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma , \eta , {\lambda }, \nu )$ is successful, then we say ${\mathcal {N}}$ is its output if it is the iterate of ${\mathcal {M}}$ described above.

The following is the main theorem that we will need from this section. We say E is a strictly short extender if its generators are bounded below $\pi _E(\mathrm {crit }(E))$ . We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ is strictly short if all of its extenders are strictly short.

Theorem 2.22. Suppose $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ and $\eta $ are as above and in addition to the above data, $\eta $ is a Woodin cardinal and ${\mathcal {M}}$ is strictly short. Suppose ${\lambda }<\eta $ and $\nu $ is a cutpoint cardinal of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Then $\mathsf {FBIC}({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma , \eta , {\lambda }, \nu )$ is successful.

The proof is a standard combination of universality (see [Reference Steel52, Lemma 11.1]) and stationarity (see [Reference Schlutzenberg and Trang44, Lemma 3.23]) of fully backgrounded constructions.

3. An upper bound for $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$

The goal of this section is to prove Theorem 3.1. It reduces $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ to a large cardinal theory. This essentially constitutes one half of Theorem 1.4 and Theorem 1.7.

Theorem 3.1. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is excellent and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , {\delta }^{\mathcal {P}})$ is ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. Then both $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ hold in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ .

We start the proof of Theorem 3.1. Let ${\mathcal {P}}$ be excellent (see Definition 2.7). Set ${\delta }_0={\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ and let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega ,\delta _0)$ be ${\mathcal {P}}$ -generic. We first show that $\mathsf {Sealing}$ holds in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ . Let ${\mathcal {P}}_0=_{def}({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }_0)^{\#}$ . We write ${\mathcal {P}} = (|{\mathcal {P}}|,\in , \mathbb {E}^{\mathcal {P}}, S^{\mathcal {P}})$ , where $\mathbb {E}^{\mathcal {P}}$ is the extender sequence of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ is the predicate coding the short-tree strategy of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ in ${\mathcal {P}}$ . Thus, ${\mathcal {P}}$ above ${\delta }_0$ is a short-tree-strategy premouse over ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ .

Let $\Sigma ^-$ be this short-tree strategy. It follows from Proposition 2.17 that for any ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic h, $\Sigma ^-$ has a canonical extension $\Sigma ^h$ in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ Footnote 58. Let then $\Sigma $ be the extension of $\Sigma ^-$ in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ .

3.1. An upper bound for $\mathsf {Sealing}$

Let h be ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic. Working in ${\mathcal {P}}[g][h]$ , let $\Delta ^h=\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}_0, \Sigma )$ . Equivalently, $\Delta ^h$ is the set of reals $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h]}$ such that for some countable tree ${\mathcal {T}}$ on ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ with last model ${\mathcal {Q}}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists, $A\in L(\Sigma ^h_{{\mathcal {Q}}^b}, {\mathbb {R}}^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h]})$ . It follows from Proposition 2.18 that if ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is as above, then $\Sigma ^h_{{\mathcal {Q}}^b}\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ .

Lemma 3.2. $\Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}=\Delta ^h$ .

Proof. It follows from Proposition 2.18 that $\Delta ^h\subseteq \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ . Fix $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h]}$ that is a universally Baire set in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ . Work in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ and suppose $A\not \in \Delta ^h$ . Because there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals, any two universally Baire sets are Wadge comparable. Since $\Delta ^h\cup \{A\}\subseteq \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ and $A\not \in \Delta ^h$ , we have that $\Delta ^h\subseteq L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h})$ . Recall that by a result of Steel ([Reference Steel47, Theorem 4.3]), A is Suslin, co-Suslin in $\Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ . Hence, we can assume, without losing generality, that in $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h})$ , there are Suslin, co-Suslin sets beyond $\Delta ^h$ .

It follows from [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 10.1.1] that there is a lsa-type hod pair $({\mathcal {S}}, \Lambda )\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ such that $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {S}}, \Lambda )=\Delta ^h$ . Just like in the proof of Proposition 2.21, we can assume that ${\mathcal {S}}$ is a $\Sigma ^h$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ and $\Lambda ^{stc}=\Sigma ^h_{\mathcal {S}}$ . It then follows that $\Sigma ^h\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ , contradicting Proposition 2.21.

By the results of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Section 8.1] (specifically, [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 8.1.1 clause 4]), we get that in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ ,

(1) $$ \begin{align} \Delta^h = {\wp}(\mathbb{R}_{g*h})\cap L(\Delta^h, {\mathbb{R}}_{g*h}). \end{align} $$

The lemma and (1) immediately give us clause (1) of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ . For clause (2), let h be ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic and k be ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ -generic. We want to show that there is an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j:L(\Delta^h, {\mathbb{R}}_{g*h})\rightarrow L(\Delta^{h*k}, {\mathbb{R}}_{g*h*k}) \end{align*} $$

such that for every $A\in \Delta ^h$ , $j(A)$ is the canonical extension of A in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h*k]$ . This will be accomplished in Lemma 3.4. The next lemma provides a key step in the construction of the desired elementary embedding. It does so by realizing $L(\Delta ^h, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h})$ as a derived model of an iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ .

Recall from [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 2.7.2] that if ${\mathcal {S}}$ is a hod premouse of limit type (including lsa type), then ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {S}}^b}$ is the supremum of the Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {S}}^b$ . In general, the reader may wish to review some of the notation concerning hod premice; the relevant notation can be found in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 2 and 3]. The Key Phenomenon stated before [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 2.7.8] might also be useful.

Lemma 3.3. Suppose $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ is a poset and $m\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ is ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic. Suppose further that in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*m]$ , ${\mathcal {S}}$ is a countable $\Sigma ^m$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ such that the ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ -to- ${\mathcal {S}}$ iteration embedding exists. Suppose ${\kappa }<{\delta }^{{\mathcal {S}}^b}$ is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {S}}$ and $A\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*m}$ (in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*m]$ ). Then in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*m]$ , there is a countable $\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {S}}$ -iterate ${\mathcal {W}}$ of ${\mathcal {S}}$ such that the ${\mathcal {S}}$ -to- ${\mathcal {W}}$ iteration embedding exists, the ${\mathcal {S}}$ -to- ${\mathcal {W}}$ iteration is above ${\kappa }$ and A is Wadge below $\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ .

Proof. The lemma follows from Proposition 2.19. Indeed, let w be a window of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that $g*m$ is generic for a poset in ${\mathcal {P}}|\nu ^w$ . Let ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ be the output of $\mathsf {FBIC}({\mathcal {S}}, \Sigma ^m, {\delta }^w, \nu ^w, {\kappa })$ (see Theorem 2.22). Thus, ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ is a $\Sigma ^m$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {S}}$ above ${\kappa }$ , and all of its extenders with critical point $>{\kappa }$ have, in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ , full background certificates whose critical points are strictly greater than $\nu ^w$ . We also have that

(A) $Ord\cap {\mathcal {N}}_0={\delta }^w$ (see Proposition 2.19).

Working inside ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ , let ${\mathcal {N}}$ be the output of the hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ done using extenders with critical point $>{\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_0^b}$ .

It follows from Lemma 3.2 that there is a countable iteration p of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ according to $\Sigma ^m$ such that $\pi ^{p, b}$ exists and letting ${\mathcal {R}}=\pi ^{p, b}({\mathcal {P}}_0^b)$ , A is Wadge below $\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {R}}}$ . Fix such a $(p, {\mathcal {R}})$ . We now claim that

Claim. for some $\xi <{\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}^b}$ , ${\mathcal {N}}|\xi $ is a $\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {R}}$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

Proof. To see this, we compare ${\mathcal {R}}$ with the construction producing ${\mathcal {N}}$ . We need to see that ${\mathcal {R}}$ can be compared with ${\mathcal {N}}$ . There are two ways such a comparison could go wrong.

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {N}}$ and ${\mathcal {R}}$ are not full with respect to the same $Lp$ -operator. More precisely, for some normal $\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {R}}$ -iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ of limit length letting $b=\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {R}}({\mathcal {T}})$ , either

    1. (a) ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_b{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’ and ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’ or

    2. (b) ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_b{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’ and ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal.

  2. 2. A strategy disagreement is reached. More precisely, for some normal $\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {R}}$ -iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ with last model ${\mathcal {R}}^*$ and some $\xi $ which is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {R}}^*$ , ${\mathcal {R}}^*|\xi ={\mathcal {N}}|\xi $ yet $S^{\mathcal {N}}_{{\mathcal {R}}^*|\xi }\not = \Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {R}}^*|\xi }$ .

It is easier to argue that case 2 cannot happen. This essentially follows from [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 4.13.2]. Because ${\mathcal {N}}$ is backgrounded via extenders whose critical points are $>{\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_0^b}$ , the fragment of $\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {N}}_0}$ , we need to compute the strategy of ${\mathcal {N}}|\xi $ as the fragment that acts on nondropping trees that are above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_0^b}$ and are based on ${\mathcal {N}}_0|\zeta $ . Then [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 4.13.2] implies that this fragment of $\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {N}}_0}$ is induced by the unique strategy of ${\mathcal {P}}|\zeta $ . The same strategy of ${\mathcal {P}}|\zeta $ also induces $\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {R}}^*|\xi }$ . Therefore, clause 2 cannot happen.

We now show that clause 1 also cannot happen. Suppose $\xi <{\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}^b}$ is a limit of Woodin cardinals or is a Woodin cardinal. Let $\zeta =o^{\mathcal {N}}(\xi )$ , the Mitchell order of $\xi $ , and let ${\mathcal {T}}$ be a normal tree on ${\mathcal {R}}$ with last model ${\mathcal {W}}$ such that ${\mathcal {W}}|\zeta ={\mathcal {N}}|\zeta $ and the generators of ${\mathcal {T}}$ are contained in $\zeta $ . Furthermore, assume that $\zeta $ is a cutpoint in ${\mathcal {W}}$ . Let $\nu $ be the least Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {W}}$ above $\zeta $ and let $\tau $ be the least Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {N}}$ above $\zeta $ . It is enough to show that whenever $({\mathcal {T}}, {\mathcal {W}}, \xi , \zeta , \nu , \tau )$ are as above, then ${\mathcal {W}}|\nu $ normally iterates via $\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {W}}|\nu }$ to ${\mathcal {N}}|\tau $ .

To see this, it is enough to show that if ${\mathcal {U}}$ is a normal tree on ${\mathcal {W}}|\nu $ of limit length and ${\mathrm m}({\mathcal {U}}){\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {N}}|\tau $ , then setting $b=\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {W}}}({\mathcal {U}})$ , either

  1. 1. ${\delta }({\mathcal {U}})<\tau $ and ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {U}})$ exists and ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {U}}){\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {N}}|\tau $ or

  2. 2. ${\delta }({\mathcal {U}})=\tau $ and $\pi ^{\mathcal {U}}_b(\nu )=\tau $ .

To see the above, fix ${\mathcal {U}}$ and b as above. Suppose first that ${\delta }({\mathcal {U}})<\tau $ . Let ${\mathcal {Q}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {N}}|\tau $ be largest such that ${\mathcal {Q}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {U}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’. Then, as $\Sigma ^m$ is fullness preserving, ${\mathcal {Q}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {U}}_b$ .

Suppose then ${\delta }({\mathcal {U}})=\tau $ . If $\pi ^{\mathcal {U}}_b(\nu )>\tau $ , then ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {U}})$ -exists and is $Ord$ -iterable inside ${\mathcal {P}}[g*m]$ . Working inside ${\mathcal {N}}$ , let ${\mathcal { K}}$ be the output of the fully backgrounded construction of ${\mathcal {N}}$ done with respect to $S^{\mathcal {N}}_{{\mathcal {N}}|\tau }$ over ${\mathcal {N}}|\tau $ and using extenders with critical point $>{\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}^b}$ . Because ${\mathcal { K}}$ is universal, we must have that ${\mathcal {Q}}({\beta }, {\mathcal {U}}){\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal { K}}$ . Thus, ${\mathcal { K}}{\vDash } \text {`}\tau $ is not a Woodin cardinal’, which implies that ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}\tau $ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

Let now ${\mathcal {Y}}^*$ be a normal tree on ${\mathcal {S}}$ according to $\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {S}}$ whose last model is ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ . Let $\eta \in ({\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_0^b}, {\delta }^w)$ be such that ${\mathcal {R}}$ iterates to the hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {N}}_0|\eta $ . Let $E\in \vec {E}^{{\mathcal {N}}_0}$ be such that $\mathrm {crit }(E)={\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_0^b}$ and $lh(E)>\eta $ (the existence of such an E follows from (A) above). Let ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {Y}}^*)$ be the least such that $E\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{{\mathcal {Y}}^*}$ and set ${\mathcal {Y}}^{**}={\mathcal {Y}}^*{\restriction } {\alpha }+1$ . Finally, set ${\mathcal {Y}}={\mathcal {Y}}^{**\frown } \{E\}$ . Notice that if ${\mathcal {V}}$ is the last model of ${\mathcal {Y}}$ , then $\pi ^{\mathcal {Y}}$ -exists.

To finish the proof of the lemma, we need to take a countable Skolem hull of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\lambda }[g*m]$ , where ${\lambda }=(({\delta }^w)^+)^{\mathcal {P}}$ . Let $\pi :{\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P}}|{\lambda }[g*m]$ be a countable Skolem hull of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\lambda }[g*m]$ such that ${\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {N}}, {\mathcal {Y}} \in rng(\pi )$ . Let ${\mathcal {X}}=\pi ^{-1}({\mathcal {Y}})$ and let ${\mathcal {W}}$ be the last model of ${\mathcal {X}}$ . By elementarity, ${\mathcal {X}}={\mathcal {X}}^{*\frown }\{ F\}$ and ${\mathcal {R}}$ normally iterates via $\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {R}}$ to a hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {W}}|lh(F)$ . It follows now that $\Sigma ^m_{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ is Wadge above $\Sigma ^m_{\mathcal {R}}$ and hence Wadge above A. Therefore, ${\mathcal {X}}$ is as desired.

Lemma 3.4. There is an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j: L(\Delta^h,\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{P}}[g*h]})\rightarrow L(\Delta^{h*k},\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{P}}[g*h*k]}) \end{align*} $$

such that for each $A\in \Delta ^h$ , $j(A)=A^k$ , the interpretation of A in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h*k]$ .

Proof. Let $W_1=L(\Delta ^h,\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h]})$ and $W_2=L(\Delta ^{h*k},\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h*k]})$ . Let C be the set of inaccessible cardinals of ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h*k]$ . Because we have a class of Woodin cardinals, it follows that $(\Delta ^h)^\#$ exists. Moreover, for $\Gamma \subseteq {\wp }({\mathbb {R}})$ , assuming $\Gamma ^\#$ exists, any set in $L(\Gamma ,{\mathbb {R}})$ is definable from a set in $\Gamma $ , a real and a finite sequence of indiscernibles. It is then enough to show that

(*) if $s=({\alpha }_0, ..., {\alpha }_n)\in C^{<\omega }$ , $A\in \Delta ^h$ , $x\in {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ and $\phi $ is a formula, then

$$ \begin{align*} L(\Delta^h, {\mathbb{R}}_{g*h}){\vDash} \phi[A, x, s] \text{ if and only if } L(\Delta^{h*k}, {\mathbb{R}}_{g*h*k}){\vDash} \phi[A^k, x, s]. \end{align*} $$

Indeed, we first show that (*) induces an elementary $j:W_1\rightarrow W_2$ as desired. Let Y be the set of a that are definable over $L(\Delta ^{h*k}, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h*k})$ from a member of $C^{<\omega }$ , a set of the form $A^k$ for some $A\in \Delta ^h$ and a real $x\in {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ . Notice that (*) implies that

Claim 1. Y is elementary in $L(\Delta ^{h*k}, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h*k})$ .

Proof. We show that Y is $\Sigma _1$ -elementary. The general case follows from Tarski-Vaught criteria. To see this, fix $a\in Y$ and let $\phi $ be a $\Sigma _1$ formula. Suppose that

$$ \begin{align*} W_2{\vDash} \phi[a]. \end{align*} $$

Fix a term t, $s\in C^{<\omega }$ , a set of the form $A^k$ , where $A\in \Delta ^h$ and $x\in {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ such that $a=t^{W_2}[s, A^k, x]$ . It then follows from (*) that if $b=t^{W_1}[s, A, x]$ , $W_1{\vDash } \phi [b]$ . Let $\phi =\exists u \psi (u, v)$ . Fix a term $t_1$ , $s_1\in C^{<\omega }$ , $B\in \Delta ^h$ and $y\in {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ such that setting $c=t^{W_1}_1[s_1, B, y]$ , $W_1{\vDash } \psi [c, b]$ . Therefore, (*) implies that if $d=t^{W_2}[s_1, B^k, y]$ , then $W_2{\vDash } \psi [d, a]$ . As $d\in Y$ , we have $Y{\vDash } \phi [a]$ .

Let now N be the transitive collapse of Y. It is enough to show that $N=W_1$ . This easily follows from (*) and the proof of the claim. For example, let us show that ${\mathbb {R}}^N={\mathbb {R}}^{W_1}$ . Fix $x\in {\mathbb {R}}^N$ . Let t be a term, $s\in C^{<\omega }$ , $A\in \Delta ^h$ and $a\in {\mathbb {R}}^{W_1}$ such that $x=t^{W_2}[s, A^k, a]$ . Letting $y=t^{W_1}[s, A, a]$ , it is easy to see that $x=y$ . We now let $j:W_1\rightarrow W_2$ be the inverse of the transitive collapse of Y. Clearly, j is elementary and $j(A)=A^k$ for $A\in \Delta ^h$ .

By a similar reduction, using the definition of $\Delta ^h$ and $\Delta ^{h*k}$ , it is enough to show that (**) holds where

(**) if $s=({\alpha }_0, ..., {\alpha }_n)\in C^{<\omega }$ , ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a countable iteration of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ according to $\Sigma ^h$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists, ${\mathcal {R}}=\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}_0^b)$ , $x\in {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ and $\phi $ is a formula, then

$$ \begin{align*} W_1{\vDash} \phi[\Sigma^h_{\mathcal{R}}, x, s] \text{ if and only if } W_2{\vDash} \phi[\Sigma^{h*k}_{\mathcal{R}}, x, s]. \end{align*} $$

To show (**), let $s\in C^{<\omega }$ , ${\mathcal {T}}$ be a countable iteration of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ according to $\Sigma ^h$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists, ${\mathcal {R}}=\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {P}}_0^b)$ , $x\in {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ and $\phi $ be a formula such that $W_1{\vDash } \phi [\Sigma ^h_{\mathcal {R}}, x, s]$ . Notice that without losing generality, we can assume that $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ exists, as otherwise we can work with a shorter initial segment of ${\mathcal {T}}$ that produces the same bottom part ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Let ${\mathcal {S}}^*$ be the last model of ${\mathcal {T}}$ and let ${\mathcal {S}}^{**}$ be the ultrapower of ${\mathcal {S}}^*$ by the least extender on the sequence of ${\mathcal {S}}^*$ with the critical point ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}}$ . Let $\iota $ be the least Woodin of ${\mathcal {S}}^{**}$ that is $>{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ . Let ${\mathcal {W}}$ be the $\Sigma ^h$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {S}}^{**}$ that is obtained via an x-genericity iteration done in the window $({\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}, \iota )$ .

We would now like to see that $W_2{\vDash } \phi [\Sigma ^{h*k}_{\mathcal {R}}, x, s]$ . The idea is to realize $W_1$ and $W_2$ , respectively, as a derived model of ${\mathcal {W}}$ . Given a transitive model of set theory M with ${\lambda }$ a limit of Woodin cardinals of M, we let $D(M, {\lambda })$ be the derived model at ${\lambda }$ as computed by some symmetric collapse of ${\lambda }$ . While $D(M, {\lambda })$ depends on this generic, its theory does not. Thus, expressions like $D(M, {\lambda }){\vDash } \psi $ have an $\mathsf {uvs}$ meaning. If $u\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\lambda })$ is the generic, then $D({\mathcal {M}}, {\lambda }, u)$ is the derived model computed using u.Footnote 59

To finish the proof, we will need a way of realizing $W_1$ as a derived model of an iterate of ${\mathcal {W}}$ that is obtained by iterating above $\xi $ , where $\xi $ is the least Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {W}}$ above $\delta ^{\mathcal {R}}$ . The same construction will also realize $W_2$ as a derived model of a ${\mathcal {W}}$ ’s iterate. Let $l\subseteq Coll(\omega , \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h})$ be ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ -generic. Working in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h*l]$ , let $(A_i: i<\omega )$ be a generic enumeration of $\Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ and let $(x_i: i<\omega )$ be a generic enumeration of ${\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ .

(1) There is sequence $({\mathcal {W}}_i, p_i^*, p_i: i<\omega ) \in {\mathcal {P}}[g*h*l]$ such that

  1. 1. for each $n<\omega $ , $({\mathcal {W}}_i, p_i^*, p_i: i\leq n)\in HC^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h]}$ ,

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {W}}_0={\mathcal {W}}$ ,

  3. 3. letting $E_i\in \vec {E}^{{\mathcal {W}}_i}$ be the Mitchell order 0 measure on ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}_i^b}$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_i=Ult({\mathcal {W}}_i, E_i)$ ,Footnote 60 $p_i^*$ is an iteration of ${\mathcal {M}}_i$ according to $\Sigma ^h_{{\mathcal {M}}_i}$ that is above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}_i^b}$ , has a last model ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ and is such that $\pi ^{p_i^*}$ exists and for some $\nu _i<{\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_i^b}$ a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {N}}_{i}$ , $A_i<_w \Sigma ^h_{{\mathcal {N}}_i|\nu _i}$ ,

  4. 4. fixing some $\nu _i$ as above and letting $\xi $ be the least Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ that is $>\nu _i$ , ${\mathcal {W}}_{i+1}$ is the $\Sigma ^h_{{\mathcal {N}}_i}$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ that is above $\nu _i$ and makes $x_i$ generic at the image of $\xi $ ; $p_i$ is the corresponding iteration.

The proof of (1) is a straightforward application of Lemma 3.3. Let $\pi _{i, j}:{\mathcal {W}}_i\rightarrow {\mathcal {W}}_j$ be the iteration embedding and let ${\mathcal {W}}_{\omega }$ be the direct limit of $({\mathcal {W}}_i, \pi _{i, j}: i<j<\omega )$ . It follows that for some $u\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}_{\omega }^b})$ -generic,

(2) ${\mathbb {R}}^{{\mathcal {W}}_{\omega }[u]}={\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}$ and $\Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}={\wp }({\mathbb {R}}_{g*h})\cap D({\mathcal {W}}_{\omega }, {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}_{\omega }^b}, u)$ , and hence,

(3) $W_1=D({\mathcal {W}}_{\omega }, {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}_{\omega }^b}, u)$

Letting S stand for the strategy predicate and t be the sequence of the first n indiscernibles of ${\mathcal {W}}|{\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ , we thus get by our assumption $W_1{\vDash } \phi [\Sigma ^h_{\mathcal {R}}, x, s]$ and by elementarity that

(4) $D({\mathcal {W}}[x], {\delta }^{{\mathcal {S}}^b}){\vDash } \phi [S^{\mathcal {W}}_{\mathcal {R}}, x, t]$ .

The same construction that gives (3) also gives ${\mathcal {N}}_{\omega }$ and v such that

(5) ${\mathcal {N}}_{\omega }$ is a $\Sigma ^{h*k}$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {W}}$ above $\xi $ , $v\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_{\omega }^b})$ is generic and $D({\mathcal {N}}_{\omega }, {\delta }^{{\mathcal {N}}_{\omega }^b}, v)=W_2$ .

Thus, $W_2{\vDash } \phi [\Sigma ^{h*k}_{\mathcal {R}}, x, t_1]$ , where $t_1$ is the image of t in ${\mathcal {N}}_{\omega }$ . By indiscernability, we get that $W_2{\vDash } \phi [\Sigma ^{h*k}_{\mathcal {R}}, x, s]$ .

3.2. An upper bound for $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$

Let $({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Sigma ^-), {\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , g$ be as before (see right after Theorem 3.1). Now we show $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ is satisfied in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ . Fix a poset $\mathbb {P}\in P[g]$ and let $h\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ be ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic. We will show that

  1. 1. $L(\Sigma ^{g*h}, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h}){\vDash } \mathsf {LSA}$ and

  2. 2. $\Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ is the Suslin co-Suslin sets of $L(\Sigma ^{g*h}, {\mathbb {R}}_{g*h})$ .

Clause 2 above is an immediate consequence of clause 1 and the results of the previous section.

We now show clause 1. Let $(\gamma _i : i<\omega )$ be the first $\omega $ Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ and $\gamma = sup_{i<\omega } \gamma _i$ . Let $w_i$ be the corresponding consecutive windows determined by the $\gamma _i$ ’s. Write $\Lambda $ for $\Sigma ^{h}$ , the canonical interpretation of $\Sigma $ in $P[g*h]$ . In ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ , let

$$ \begin{align*} \pi: {\mathcal{M}} \rightarrow ({\mathcal{P}}[g*h]|\gamma^+)^\# \end{align*} $$

be elementary and such that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is countable and $\mathrm {crit }(\pi )> {\delta }_0$ . For each i, let $\delta _i = \pi ^{-1}(\gamma _i)$ , and $\lambda = \sup _{i<\omega } \delta _i$ . Note that because $\mathrm {crit }(\pi )> {\delta }_0$ , ${\mathcal {M}}|{\lambda }$ is closed under $\Lambda $ , and $\lambda $ is the supremum of the Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . It follows from Proposition 2.13 that ${\mathcal {M}}$ has a $\nu ^{w_0}$ -strategy acting on nondropping trees based on the interval $[\pi ^{-1}(\nu ^{w_0}), \lambda )$ in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ ; call this strategy $\Psi $ .

Let $k\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\lambda )$ be ${\mathcal {M}}$ -generic. Let $\mathbb {R}^*_k = \bigcup _{\xi <\lambda } \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {M}}[k|\xi ]}$ and recall the ‘new’ derived model of ${\mathcal {M}}$ at $\lambda $

$$ \begin{align*} D^+({\mathcal{M}},\lambda,k) = L(\{A\in {\wp}(\mathbb{R}^*_k)\cap {\mathcal{M}}(\mathbb{R}^*_k): L(A,\mathbb{R}^*_k) {\vDash} \mathsf{AD}^+ \}). \end{align*} $$

By Woodin’s derived model theorem, cf. [Reference Steel47], $D^+({\mathcal {M}},{\lambda },k){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}^+$ . Again, the theory of $D^+({\mathcal {M}},\lambda ,k)$ does not depend on k. When we reason about the theory of the new derived model without concerning about any particular generic, we write $D^+({\mathcal {M}},\lambda )$ . Recall that we set $\Lambda =\Sigma ^h$ .

Proposition 3.5. $\Lambda \cap {\mathcal {M}}(\mathbb {R}^*_k)\in D^+({\mathcal {M}}, {\lambda })$ . Furthermore, in $D^+({\mathcal {M}},{\lambda })$ , $L(\Lambda ,\mathbb {R})\vDash \mathsf {LSA}$ .

Proof. First, note that there is a term $\tau \in {\mathcal {M}}$ such that $({\mathcal {M}},\Psi ,\tau )$ term captures $\Sigma ^{h}$ . More precisely, letting $i:{\mathcal {M}} \rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}$ be an iteration map according to $\Psi $ , let l be a $<i(\lambda )$ -generic over ${\mathcal {N}}$ . Then $Code(\Sigma ^{h})\cap {\mathcal {N}}[l] = i(\tau )_{l}$ ; this follows from results in Section 2 (cf. Proposition 2.17). To see that in ${\mathcal {M}}(\mathbb {R}^*_k)$ , $L(\Lambda ,\mathbb {R}) {\vDash } \mathsf {AD}$ ; suppose not. Let x be a real and A be the least $OD(\Lambda ,x)$ counterexample to $\mathsf {AD}$ in $L(\Lambda ,\mathbb {R})$ . Also, by minimizing the ordinal parameters, we may assume A is definable from x and $\Lambda $ in $L(\Lambda ,\mathbb {R})$ . Using the term $\tau $ for $\Lambda $ , we can easily define a term $\sigma $ over ${\mathcal {M}}[x]$ such that $({\mathcal {M}}[x],\Psi ,\sigma )$ term captures A.Footnote 61 Applying Neeman’s theorem (cf. [Reference Neeman30]), we get that A is determined. Finally, let $i:{\mathcal {M}}[x]\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}$ be a $\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h]}$ -genericity iteration according to $\Psi $ .Footnote 62 By the argument just given, in ${\mathcal {N}}(\mathbb {R}_{g*h})$ , A is determined. So ${\mathcal {M}}(\mathbb {R}^*_k){\vDash } \sigma _k$ is determined. Contradiction.

If $\mathsf {LSA}$ fails in $L(\Lambda ,\mathbb {R})$ , then $\Lambda $ is Suslin co-Suslin in $D^+({\mathcal {M}},\lambda )$ , and the argument in Proposition 2.21 gives a contradiction. The point is that in $D^+({\mathcal {M}},{\lambda })$ , the Wadge ordinal of $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Lambda )$ is a limit of Suslin cardinals, and the failure of $\mathsf {LSA}$ means that there is a larger Suslin cardinal above the Wadge ordinalFootnote 63 of $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Lambda )$ . So $\Lambda $ is Suslin co-Suslin in $D^+({\mathcal {M}},\lambda )$ . Now we can run the argument in Proposition 2.21 to obtain a contradiction. Hence, in $D^+({\mathcal {M}},\lambda )$ ,

(2) $$ \begin{align} L(\Lambda,\mathbb{R}) \vDash \mathsf{LSA}. \end{align} $$

Now perform a $\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P}}[g*h]}$ -genericity iteration according to $\Psi $ at $\lambda $ . More precisely, there is an iteration $i:{\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}$ according to $\Psi $ such that letting $l \subseteq Coll(\omega , < i(\lambda ))$ be ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic, letting $\mathbb {R}^*_{l} = \bigcup _{\xi <i(\lambda )}\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {N}}[l|\xi ]}$ , we get

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{P}}[g*h]} = \mathbb{R}^*_{l} \end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*} L(\Sigma^{h},\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{P}}[g*h]}) \subseteq D^+({\mathcal{N}},i(\lambda),l). \end{align*} $$

Hence, by (2),

$$ \begin{align*} L(\Sigma^{h},\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{P}}[g*h]}) {\vDash} \mathsf{LSA}. \end{align*} $$

This completes the proof of clause 1 above and also the proof of $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ .

3.3. An upper bound for $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$

Let $({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Sigma ^-), {\mathcal {P}}, \Sigma , g$ be as before (see right after Theorem 3.1). We prove clause (2) of $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ holds in ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ . Clause (1) has already been established by the previous sections. Let $\mathbb {P}\in {\mathcal {P}}[g]$ be any poset, $h\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ be a ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ -generic and let $\delta $ be Woodin in ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h] =_{def} W$ . Let $G\subseteq \mathbb {Q}_{<\delta }$ be W-generic (the argument for $\mathbb {P}_{<\delta }$ is the same) and $j: W\rightarrow M \subset W[G]$ be the generic elementary embedding induced by G.Footnote 64

Let $\Lambda $ be the canonical interpretation of $\Sigma ^-$ in W and $\Lambda ^G$ be the canonical interpretation of $\Lambda $ in $W[G]$ (considered as the short-tree strategy of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ acting on countable trees). Now, by the fact that M is closed under countable sequences in $W[G]$ and the way $\Lambda ^G$ is defined (using generic interpretability),

(3) $$ \begin{align} \Lambda^G = j(\Lambda). \end{align} $$

Here is the outline of the argument. Let ${\mathcal {T}}$ be countable and according to both $j(\Lambda )$ and $\Lambda ^G$ . Note that ${\mathcal {T}}\in M$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ (the case ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ is similar). One gets that in $W[G]$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}(\Lambda ^G({\mathcal {T}}),{\mathcal {T}})$ exists and is authenticated by $\vec {C}$ , a fully backgrounded authenticated construction in W where extenders have critical point $> \delta $ ; note that we can take $\vec {C}\in W$ . This implies that ${\mathcal {Q}}(\Lambda ^G({\mathcal {T}}),{\mathcal {T}})$ is authenticated by $j(\vec {C})\in M$ ; ${\mathcal {Q}}(j(\Lambda )({\mathcal {T}}),{\mathcal {T}})$ is also authenticated by $j(\vec {C})$ in M. The details are very similar to the proof of Proposition 2.17. So $j(\Lambda )({\mathcal {T}}) = \Lambda ^G({\mathcal {T}})$ . Hence, $\Lambda ^G\in M$ .

By Lemma 3.2,

$$ \begin{align*} (\Gamma^{\infty})^{W[G]} = \Gamma^b({\mathcal{P}}_0,\Lambda^G). \end{align*} $$

By elementarity, the fact that $(\Gamma ^{\infty })^W = \Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Lambda )$ , 3, and Lemma 3.2,

$$ \begin{align*} j((\Gamma^{\infty})^W) = \Gamma^b({\mathcal{P}}_0,\Lambda^G). \end{align*} $$

So indeed, $(\Gamma ^{\infty })^{W[G]}= j((\Gamma ^{\infty })^W)$ as desired.

Remark 3.6. Another proof of clause (2) of $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ is the following. We give a sketch: by results of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], $\Lambda ^G\in L(\pi ^b_{{\mathcal {P}}_0,\infty }[{\mathcal {P}}_0], \mathcal {H},(\Gamma ^{\infty })^{W[G]})$ . Here, working in $W[G]$ , let $\mathcal {H}^-$ be the direct limit of hod pairs $({\mathcal {R}},\Delta )\in L(\Gamma ^{\infty })$ such that in $ L(\Gamma ^{\infty })$ , $\Delta $ is fullness preserving and has hull and branch condensation. $|\mathcal {H}^-| = V^{HOD}_{\Theta }$ in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty })$ . Let $\mathcal {H} = \bigcup \{{\mathcal {M}} : \mathcal {H}^- \lhd {\mathcal {M}}, {\mathcal {M}} \textrm { be a sound, hybrid } \textrm {countably iterable premouse such that } \rho _{\omega }({\mathcal {M}})\leq o(\mathcal {H}^-)\}$ . For each ${\mathcal {M}}\lhd \mathcal {H}$ as above, for every ${\mathcal {N}}$ countably transitive such that ${\mathcal {N}}$ is embeddable into ${\mathcal {M}}$ , ${\mathcal {N}}$ has an $\omega _1$ -strategy in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty })$ .

If $(\Gamma ^{\infty })^{W[G]}\neq j((\Gamma ^{\infty })^W)$ , then suppose the former is a strict Wadge initial segment of the latter (the other case is handled similarly). So the model

$$ \begin{align*} L(\pi^b_{{\mathcal{P}}_0,\infty}[{\mathcal{P}}_0], \mathcal{H},(\Gamma^{\infty})^{W[G]})\in M \end{align*} $$

as M is closed under $\omega $ -sequences in $W[G]$ . In fact, we get that $\Lambda ^G \in j((\Gamma ^{\infty })^W)$ . By Generation of Mouse Full Pointclasses (applied in $L(j((\Gamma ^{\infty })^W))$ and a comparison argument as in Lemma 2.21, there is a (maximal) $\Lambda ^G$ -iterate ${\mathcal {S}}$ of ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ such that ${\mathcal {S}}$ has an iteration strategy $\Psi $ such that

  • $\Psi ^{stc} = (\Lambda ^G)_{\mathcal {S}}$ ,

  • $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {S}},\Psi ) = \Gamma ({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Lambda ^G)$ ,

  • $\Psi \in j((\Gamma ^{\infty })^W)$ .

By elementarity, the existence of ${\mathcal {S}},\Psi $ holds in $L((\Gamma ^{\infty })^W)$ . This contradicts the fact that $j(\Lambda )\notin (\Gamma ^{\infty })^W$ .

4. Basic core model induction

The notation introduced in the section will be used throughout this paper. It will be wise to refer back to this section for clarifications. From this point on, the paper is devoted to proving that both $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ imply the existence of a (possibly class size) excellent hybrid premouse. As we have already shown that a forcing extension of an excellent hybrid premouse satisfies both $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ , this will complete the proof of Theorem 1.4.

We will accomplish our goal by considering ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ of $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})$ and showing that, in some sense, it reaches an excellent hybrid premouse. Our first step towards this goal is to show that $\Theta $ is a limit point of the Solovay sequence of $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})$ .

Proposition 4.1. Assume there are unboundedly many Woodin cardinals. Furthermore, assume either $\mathsf {Sealing}$ , or $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ , or $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ . Then for all set generic g, the following holds in $V[g]$ :

  1. 1. ${\wp }({\mathbb {R}})\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})=\Gamma ^{\infty }$ ,

  2. 2. $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}$ .

Proof. Towards a contradiction, assume that $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \neg \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}$ . By a result of Steel ([Reference Steel47, Theorem 4.3]), every set in $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ has a scale in $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ . Notice then that clause 1 implies clause 2. This is because given clause 1, $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }, {\mathbb {R}})$ satisfies that every set has a scale, and therefore, it satisfies $\mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}$ .Footnote 65

It is then enough to show that clause 1 holds. It trivially follows from $\mathsf {Sealing}$ or $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ . To see that it also follows from $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ , fix a set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}$ such that $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ is the set of Suslin, co-Suslin sets of $L(A, {\mathbb {R}})$ and $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {LSA}$ . It now follows that if ${\kappa }$ is the largest Suslin cardinal of $L(A, {\mathbb {R}})$ , then, in $L(A, {\mathbb {R}})$ , $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ is the set of reals whose Wadge rank is $<{\kappa }$ . Since $\kappa $ is on the Solovay sequence of $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ , $\Gamma ^{\infty } = L(\Gamma ^{\infty })\cap {\wp }(\mathbb {R})$ . Therefore, clause 1 follows.

For the rest of this paper, we write $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash }_{\Omega } \mathsf {AD}_{{\mathbb {R}}}$ to mean that clause 1 and 2 above hold in all generic extensions. $\Omega $ here is a reference to Woodin’s $\Omega $ -logic. We develop the notations below under $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash }_{\Omega } \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}$ .

Suppose $\mu $ is a cardinal. Let $g\subset Col(\omega ,<\mu )$ be V-generic. Working in V, we say that a pair $({\mathcal {M}},\Sigma )$ is a hod pair at $\mu $ if

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {M}}\in V_{\mu }$ ,

  2. 2. $\Sigma $ is a $(\mu ,\mu )$ -iteration strategy of ${\mathcal {M}}$ that is in $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ in $V^{Coll(\omega ,|{\mathcal {M}}|)}$ and is positional, commuting and has branch condensation, and

  3. 3. $\Sigma $ is fullness preserving with respect to mice with $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ -iteration strategy.

Let $\mathcal {F}$ be the set of hod pairs at $\mu $ . It is shown in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] that hod mice at $\mu $ can be compared (see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 4.6 and 4.10].). More precisely, given any two hod pairs $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ and $({\mathcal {N}}, \Lambda )$ in $\mathcal {F}$ , there is a hod pair $({\mathcal {S}}, \Psi )\in \mathcal {F}$ such that for some ${\mathcal {M}}^*\unlhd _{hod} {\mathcal {S}}$ and ${\mathcal {N}}^*\unlhd _{hod} {\mathcal {S}}$ ,

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ is a $\Sigma $ -iterate of ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that the main branch of ${\mathcal {M}}$ -to- ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ iteration does not drop,

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {N}}^*$ is a $\Lambda $ -iterate of ${\mathcal {N}}$ such that the main branch of ${\mathcal {N}}$ -to- ${\mathcal {N}}^*$ iteration does not drop,

  3. 3. $\Sigma _{{\mathcal {M}}^*}=\Psi _{{\mathcal {M}}^*}$ and $\Lambda _{{\mathcal {N}}^*}=\Psi _{{\mathcal {N}}^*}$ and

  4. 4. either ${\mathcal {S}}={\mathcal {M}}^*$ or ${\mathcal {S}}={\mathcal {N}}^*$ .

Working in $V[g]$ , let $\mathcal {F}^+$ be the set of all hod pairs $({\mathcal {M}},\Sigma )$ such that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is countable and $\Sigma $ is an $(\omega _1,\omega _1+1)$ -strategy of ${\mathcal {M}}$ that is $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ -fullness preserving, positional, commuting, has branch condensation,Footnote 66 and $\Sigma {\restriction } \mathrm {HC}\in \Gamma ^{\infty }$ .

Because any two hod pairs in $\mathcal {F}^+$ can be compared, $\mathcal {F}$ covers $\mathcal {F}^+$ . More precisely, for each hod pair $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )\in \mathcal {F}^+$ , there is $\Sigma $ -iterate ${\mathcal {N}}$ of ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that the ${\mathcal {M}}$ -to- ${\mathcal {N}}$ iteration does not drop on its main branch, $(\Sigma _{\mathcal {N}}{\restriction } V)\in V$ and $\Sigma _{\mathcal {N}}$ is the unique extension of $(\Sigma _{\mathcal {N}}{\restriction } V)$ to $V[g]$ .

Given any hod pair $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ , let $I({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ be the set of iterates ${\mathcal {N}}$ of ${\mathcal {M}}$ by $\Sigma $ such that the main branch of ${\mathcal {M}}$ -to- ${\mathcal {N}}$ does not drop. Let $X\subseteq I({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ be a directed set (i.e., if ${\mathcal {N}}, {\mathcal {P}}\in X$ , then there is ${\mathcal {R}}\in X$ such that ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a $\Sigma _{\mathcal {N}}$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {N}}$ and a $\Sigma _{\mathcal {P}}$ -iterate of ${\mathcal {R}}$ ). We then let ${\mathcal {M}}_{\infty }({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma , X)$ be the direct limit of all iterates of ${\mathcal {M}}$ by $\Sigma $ that are in X. Usually, X will be clear from context and we will omit it.

Working in $V[g]$ , let $\mathbb {R}_g = \mathbb {R}^{V[g]}$ . Let $\mathcal {H}^{-}$ be the direct limit of hod pairs in $\mathcal {F}^+$ . Because $\mathcal {F}$ covers $\mathcal {F}^+$ , we also have that $\mathcal {H}^-$ is the direct limit of hod pairs in $\mathcal {F}$ .

Fix $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )\in \mathcal {F}^+$ such that ${\mathcal {M}}_{\infty }({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )=_{def}{\mathcal {Q}}\unlhd _{hod} \mathcal {H}^-$ . We let $\Psi _{\mathcal {Q}}=\Sigma ^+_{{\mathcal {Q}}}$ . $\Psi _{\mathcal {Q}}$ only depends on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and does not depend on any particular choice of $({\mathcal {M}},\Sigma )\in \mathcal {F}^+$ . Let $({\mathcal { H}}^-(\alpha ): \alpha < \lambda )$ be the layers of ${\mathcal { H}}^-$ (in the sense of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] and [Reference Sargsyan34]) and let $\Psi _{\alpha }$ be the strategy of ${\mathcal { H}}^-(\alpha )$ for each $\alpha <\lambda $ . $\Psi _{\alpha }$ is the tail strategy $\Sigma _{\mathcal {Q}}$ for ${\mathcal {Q}} = {\mathcal {M}}_{\infty }({\mathcal {M}},\Sigma )$ for any $({\mathcal {M}},\Sigma )\in {\mathcal {F}}^+$ such that ${\mathcal {M}}_{\infty }({\mathcal {M}},\Sigma )={\mathcal { H}}^-(\alpha )$ . We now set

$$ \begin{align*} \Psi =_{def}\Psi_{\mu}=_{def} \oplus_{\alpha<\lambda^{\mathcal{H}^-}} \Psi_{\alpha}. \end{align*} $$

Definition 4.2. Suppose x is a set in $V({\mathbb {R}}_g)$ and $\Phi $ is an iteration strategy with hull condensation. Working in $V({\mathbb {R}}^*)$ , let $Lp^{cuB, \Phi }(x)$ be the union of all sound $\Phi $ -mice ${\mathcal {M}}$ over x that project to x and whenever $\pi : {\mathcal {N}} \rightarrow {\mathcal {M}}$ is elementary, ${\mathcal {N}}$ is countable and transitive. Then ${\mathcal {N}}$ has a universally Baire iteration strategy.

Continuing, we set

  1. 1. $\mathcal {H} = Lp^{cuB, \Psi }(\mathcal {H}^-)$ (note that $\mathcal {H}\in V$ ),

  2. 2. $\Theta = o(\mathcal {H}^-)$ ,

  3. 3. $(\theta _{\alpha } : \alpha < \lambda )$ as the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ of $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ . Note that $\Theta = sup_{\alpha } \theta _{\alpha }$ and $\theta _{\alpha } = \delta ^{{\mathcal { H}}^-(\alpha )}$ for each $\alpha <\lambda $ .

We note that all objects defined in this section up to this point depend on $\mu $ . To stress this, we will use $\mu $ as subscript. Thus, we will write, if needed, $\Psi _{\mu }$ or ${\mathcal { H}}_{\mu }$ for $\Psi $ and ${\mathcal { H}}$ , respectively. We will refer to the objects introduced above (e.g., ${\mathcal { H}}_{\mu }$ and $\Psi _{\mu }$ ) as the CMI objects at $\mu $ .

Given a hybrid strategy mouse ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and an iteration strategy $\Lambda $ for ${\mathcal {Q}}$ , we say $\Lambda $ is potentially-universally Baire if whenever $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , {\mathcal {Q}})$ is generic, there is a unique $\Phi \in V[g]$ such that

  1. 1. $\Phi {\restriction } V=\Lambda $ ,

  2. 2. in $V[g]$ , $\Phi $ is a uB iteration strategy for ${\mathcal {Q}}$ .

Similarly, we can define potentially- $\eta $ -uB iteration strategies.

Definition 4.3. Suppose $\mu $ is a cardinal and $({\mathcal {Q}}, \Lambda )$ is such that ${\mathcal {Q}}\in H_{\mu ^+}$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is a hybrid strategy mouse and $\Lambda $ is a potentially-uB strategy for ${\mathcal {Q}}$ . Suppose $X\in H_{\mu ^+}$ . We then let $Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X)$ be the union of all sound $\Lambda $ -mice over X that project to X and have a potentially-uB iteration strategy.

Clearly, $Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X){\trianglelefteq } Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)$ . In many core model induction applications, it is important to show that, in fact, $Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X)= Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)$ . The reason this fact is important is that the first is the stack that we can prove is computed by the maximal model of determinacy containing X after we collapse X to be countable while if ${\mathcal {Q}}, X$ are already countable, the $OD(\Lambda , {\mathcal {Q}}, X)$ information inside the maximal model is captured by $Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)$ . This is because for countable ${\mathcal {Q}}, X$ , $Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)=Lp^{uB, \Lambda }(X)$ where the mice appearing in the latter stack have universally Baire strategies. The equality $Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X)= Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)$ is important for covering type arguments that appear in the proof of Proposition 5.9.

5. $Lp^{cuB}$ and $Lp^{puB}$ operators

The following is the main result of this section, and it is the primary way we will translate strength from our hypothesis over to large cardinals. If $\mu $ is such that $Hom^*_g=\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ for any $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\mu )$ , then we say that $\mu $ stabilizes uB.

Definition 5.1. For each inaccessible cardinal $\mu $ , let $A_{\mu }\subseteq \mu $ be a set that codes $V_{\mu }$ . We then say that $X\prec H_{\mu ^+}$ captures $Lp^{cuB, \Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })$ if $Lp^{cuB, \Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })\in X$ and letting $\pi _X: M_X\rightarrow H_{\mu ^+}$ be the uncollapse map and letting $\Lambda $ be the $\pi $ -pullback of $\Psi _{\mu }$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_X^{-1}(Lp^{cuB, \Psi_{\mu}}(A_{\mu}))=Lp^{cuB, \Lambda}(\pi_X^{-1}(A_{\mu})). \end{align*} $$

Theorem 5.2. Suppose there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and a stationary class of measurable cardinals.Footnote 67 Suppose further that $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash }_{\Omega }\mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}$ . There is then a stationary class S of measurable cardinals that are limits of Woodin cardinals, a proper class $S_0\subseteq S$ , and a regular cardinal $\nu \geq \omega _1$ such that the following holds:

  1. 1. for any $\mu \in S$ , ${\vert {\mathcal { H}}_{\mu }\vert }<\mu ^+$ , ${\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal { H}}_{\mu })<\mu $ , and ${\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap Lp^{cuB,\Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu }))<\mu $ ;

  2. 2. for any $\mu \in S_0$ , $\mu $ stabilizes uB, ${\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal { H}}_{\mu })<\nu $ , and ${\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap Lp^{cuB,\Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu }))<\nu $ ;

  3. 3. for any $\mu \in S_0$ , there is $Y_{\mu }\in {\wp }_{\nu }(H_{\mu ^+})$ such that $A_{\mu }\in Y_{\mu }$ and whenever $X\prec H_{\mu ^+}$ is of size $<\mu $ , is $\nu $ -closed and $Y_{\mu }\subseteq X$ , X captures $Lp^{cuB, \Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })$ .

We emphasize that the arguments in this section (and in this paper) are carried out entirely in $\mathsf {ZFC}$ , though it may appear that we are working with proper classes. See Remark 5.10 for a more detailed discussion and summary. First, we prove a useful lemma, pointed out to us by Ralf Schindler. Below, by ‘class’, we of course mean ‘definable class’.

Lemma 5.3 ( $\mathsf {ZFC}$ )

Suppose S is a stationary class of ordinals. Suppose $f: S \rightarrow Ord$ is regressive (i.e., $f(\alpha )<\alpha $ for all $\alpha \in S$ ). There is an ordinal $\nu $ and a proper class $S_0\subseteq S$ such that $f[S_0] = \{\nu \}$ .

Proof. Suppose not. For each $\nu $ , let $\alpha _{\nu } = sup\{\alpha : f(\alpha ) = \nu \}$ if $\nu \in rng(f)$ and $\nu +1$ otherwise. $\alpha _{\nu }$ exists because we are assuming that $f^{-1}(\{\nu \})$ is a set. Let $g: Ord \rightarrow Ord$ be the function: $\nu \mapsto \alpha _{\nu }$ ; hence, $g(\nu )>\nu $ for all $\nu $ . Let $C = \{\mu : g[\mu ] \subseteq \mu \}$ . So C is a club class. Let $\alpha \in lim(C)\cap S$ . We may assume for unboundedly many $\beta < \alpha $ , $\beta \in rng(f)$ . Then we easily get that $f(\alpha )$ is not $< \alpha $ . Contradiction.

Clause 1 of Theorem 5.2 follows easily from the above lemma.

Proposition 5.4. Suppose there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and S is a stationary class of inaccessible cardinals that are limit of Woodin cardinals. Then there is a proper class $S^*\subseteq S$ such that whenever $\mu \in S^*$ and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega ,<\mu )$ is V-generic, in $V[g]$ , $Hom^*_g= \Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ .

Proof. Clearly, $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g\subseteq Hom^*_g$ . Suppose then the claim is false. We then have a club C such that whenever $\mu \in C\cap S$ and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\mu )$ , $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g \not =Hom^*_g$ . For each $\mu \in C\cap S$ , let $\eta _{\mu }<\mu $ be least such that whenever $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , \eta _{\mu })$ , there are $\mu $ -complementing trees $(T, U)\in V[g]$ with the property that $p[T]$ is not uB in $V[g][h]$ for any $V[g]$ -generic $h\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\mu )$ . By Lemma 5.3, we then have a proper class $S_0\subseteq S$ such that for every $\mu _0<\mu _1\in S_0$ , $\eta _{\mu _0}=\eta _{\mu _1}$ . Let $\eta $ be this common value of $\eta _{\mu }$ for $\mu \in S_0$ and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , \eta )$ be V-generic. For each $\mu \in S_0$ , we have a pair $(T_{\mu }, U_{\mu })\in V[g]$ that represents a $\mu $ -uB set that is not uB. A simple counting argument then shows that for a proper class $S^{*}\subseteq S_0$ , whenever $\mu _0, \mu _1\in S^{*}$ , $V[g]{\vDash } p[T_{\mu _0}]=p[T_{\mu _1}]$ . Letting $A=(p[T_{\mu }])^{V[g]}$ for some $\mu \in S^{*}$ , we get a contradiction as A is uB in $V[g]$ .

What follows is a sequence of propositions that collectively imply the remaining clauses of Theorem 5.2. We start by establishing that the two stacks are almost the same.

Proposition 5.5. Suppose $\mu , ({\mathcal {Q}}, \Lambda ), X$ are as in Definition 4.3 and suppose $\mu $ is in addition a measurable cardinal stabilizing uB. Let $j:V\rightarrow M$ be an embedding witnessing the measurability of $\mu $ . Then $Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X) =(Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X))^M$ .

Proof. Let $j: V\rightarrow M$ be an embedding witnessing the measurability of $\mu $ . Let ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X) $ be such that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})=X$ . Let $h\subseteq Coll(\omega , <j(\mu ))$ be generic. Consider $j({\mathcal {M}})$ . In $M[h]$ , ${\mathcal {M}}$ , as it embeds into $j({\mathcal {M}})$ , has a uB strategy. It follows that ${\mathcal {M}}$ has a potentially-uB strategy in M, and hence, ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } (Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X))^M$ . Conversely, if ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } (Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X))^M$ is such that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})=X$ , then in M, ${\mathcal {M}}$ has a potentially-uB strategy, and hence, in V, any countable $\pi :{\mathcal {M}}^*\rightarrow {\mathcal {M}}$ has a $\mu $ -uB-strategy. As $\mu $ -stabilizes uB, we have ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)$ .

The next two propositions are rather important. Similar propositions hide behind any successful core model induction argument.

Proposition 5.6. Suppose there are unboundedly many Woodin cardinals, $\mu $ is an inaccessible cardinal and $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash }_{\Omega } \mathsf {AD}_{{\mathbb {R}}}$ . Suppose further that $\Lambda $ is a potentially-uB iteration strategy for some ${\mathcal {Q}}\in H_{\mu ^+}$ and $X\in H_{\mu ^+}$ . Let ${\mathcal {M}}=Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X)$ . Then ${\vert {\mathcal {M}}\vert }<\mu ^+$ .

Proof. Suppose $Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}}=\mu ^+$ . Let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , \mu )$ be generic. Then

$$ \begin{align*} (Lp^{puB, \Lambda}(X))^{V}=(Lp^{puB, \Lambda}(X))^{V[g]}. \end{align*} $$

Moreover, $(Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X))^{V[g]}\in L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ . Hence, $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g){\vDash }$ ‘there is an $\omega _1$ -sequence of reals’. This contradicts the fact that $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g){\vDash } \mathsf {AD}^{+}$ .

Corollary 5.7. Suppose there are unboundedly many Woodin cardinals, $\mu $ is a measurable limit of Woodin cardinals that stabilizes uB and $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash }_{\Omega } \mathsf {AD}_{{\mathbb {R}}}$ . Suppose further that $\Lambda $ is a potentially-uB iteration strategy for some ${\mathcal {Q}}\in H_{\mu ^+}$ and $X\in H_{\mu ^+}$ . Let ${\mathcal {M}}=Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)$ . Then ${\vert {\mathcal {M}}\vert }<\mu ^+$ and ${\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}})<\mu $ .

Proof. Fix $j:V\rightarrow M$ witnessing the measurability of $\mu $ . It follows from Proposition 5.5 that ${\mathcal {M}}=(Lp^{puB, \Lambda }(X))^M$ . Applying Proposition 5.6 in M, we get that ${\vert {\mathcal {M}}\vert }<\mu ^+$ .

Assume next that ${\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}})=\mu $ . Let $\eta =Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}}$ and let $\vec {C}$ be the $\square (\eta )$ -sequence of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Because $\mu $ is measurable, we have that $\vec {C}$ is threadable. To see there is a thread D, note that $sup \ j[\eta ] =_{def} \gamma < j(\eta )$ . Let $E = j(\vec {C})_{\gamma }$ and $D = j^{-1}[E]$ . Then D is a thread through $\vec {C}$ .

This implies that there is a $\Lambda $ -mouse ${\mathcal {N}}$ extending ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that $\rho ({\mathcal {N}})=\eta $ and every $<\mu $ -submodel of ${\mathcal {N}}$ embeds into some ${\mathcal {N}}^*{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}$ .Footnote 68 It follows that ${\mathcal {N}}{\trianglelefteq } Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(X)$ .

Corollary 5.8. Assume there is a class of Woodin cardinals and let $\mu $ be a measurable limit of Woodin cardinals that stabilizes uB. Assume $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash } _{\Omega } \mathsf {AD}_{{\mathbb {R}}}$ . Let $\mathcal {H}^-, \mathcal {H}$ , etc. be defined relative to $\mu $ as in Section 4. Set

$$ \begin{align*} \xi=\max({\mathrm cf}^V(Ord\cap \mathcal{H}), {\mathrm cf}^V(Ord\cap Lp^{cuB, \Psi_{\mu}}(A_{\mu})). \end{align*} $$

Then $\xi < \mu $ .

Proof. We show that ${\mathrm cf}^V(Ord\cap \mathcal {H})<\mu $ . The second inequality is very similar. Let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\mu )$ . Notice that ${\vert {\Gamma ^{\infty }_g}\vert }^{V[g]}=\aleph _1=\mu $ . It follows that $\vert {\Theta }\vert <\mu ^+$ (recall that ${\wp }({\mathbb {R}}_g)\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)=\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ ). The fact that ${\vert {\mathcal {H}\vert }}^V<\mu ^+$ follows from Corollary 5.7. The fact that ${\mathrm cf}^V(Ord\cap \mathcal {H})<\mu $ follows from the fact that $\square (\mu )$ fails while letting $\zeta =Ord\cap \mathcal {H}$ ; ${\mathcal { H}}$ has a $\square (\zeta )$ -sequence. Let $\vec {C}$ be the $\square (\zeta )$ -sequence constructed via the proof of $\square $ in ${\mathcal { H}}$ .Footnote 69 If ${\mathrm cf}(\zeta )=\mu $ , then $\vec {C}$ has a thread D by measurability of $\mu $ ; the existence of D follows by an argument similar to that of Corollary 5.7. Because of the way $\vec {C}$ is defined, D indexes a sequence of models $({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }: {\alpha }\in D)$ such that

  1. 1. for every ${\alpha }\in D$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal { H}}$ and $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha })=\Theta $ , and

  2. 2. for ${\alpha }<{\beta }, {\alpha }, {\beta }\in D$ , there is an embedding $\pi _{{\alpha }, {\beta }}:{\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }\rightarrow {\mathcal {M}}_{\beta }$ .

Let ${\mathcal {M}}$ be the direct limit along $({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }, \pi _{{\alpha }, {\beta }}: {\alpha }\in D)$ . Then every countable submodel of ${\mathcal {M}}$ embeds into some ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }$ , implying that ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal { H}}$ . However, as D is a thread, ${\mathcal { H}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}$ , contradiction.

The next proposition shows that sufficiently closed Skolem hulls of $Lp^{cuB}$ -operator condense. The proof of it is very much like the proof of [Reference Sargsyan33, Theorem 10.3] and the proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 9.2.6]. The proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 9.2.6] is done for ${\mathcal { H}}$ , not $A_{\mu }$ . The proof of Proposition 5.9 can be obtained from the proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 9.2.6] by simply changing ${\mathcal {P}}$ to $A_{\mu }$ everywhere.

Proposition 5.9. Suppose there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals, $\mu $ is a measurable limit of Woodin cardinals stabilizing uB and $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash } _{\Omega } \mathsf {AD}_{{\mathbb {R}}}$ . There is then $\nu <\mu $ and $Y_0\in {\wp }_{\nu }( H_{\mu ^+})$ such that $A_{\mu }\in Y_0$ and for any $X\prec H_{\mu ^+}$ of size $<\mu $ that is closed under $\nu $ -sequences and $Y_0\subseteq X$ , letting $\pi _X: M_X\rightarrow H_{\mu ^+}$ be the uncollapse map and letting $\Lambda $ be the $\pi $ -pullback of $\Psi $ , $\pi _X^{-1}(Lp^{cuB, \Psi }(A_{\mu }))=Lp^{cuB, \Lambda }(\pi _X^{-1}(A_{\mu }))$ .

Proof. Let $j: V\rightarrow M$ be an embedding witnessing that $\mu $ is a measurable cardinal. Thus, $\mathrm {crit }(j)=\mu $ . It follows from Corollary 5.8 that $j[Ord\cap Lp^{cuB, \Psi }(A_{\mu })]$ is cofinal in $Ord\cap j(Lp^{cuB, \Psi }(A_{\mu }))$ .Footnote 70 Below, we use the following information:

  • ${\mathcal {P}}=Lp^{cuB, \Psi }(A_{\mu })$ , $N=j(H_{\mu ^+})$ , $A=j(A_{\mu })$ ,

  • $Y_0^*=j[{\mathcal {P}}]$ and $Y_0=Hull^N(Y_0^*)$ , and

  • if $Y\in {\wp }_{\omega _1}(N)\cap M$ , then we let $M_Y$ be the transitive collapse of Y, $\pi _Y:M_Y\rightarrow j(H_{\mu ^+})$ be the inverse of the transitive collapse, ${\mathcal {P}}_Y=\pi ^{-1}_Y(j({\mathcal {P}}))$ and $\Sigma _Y$ be the $\pi _Y$ -pullback of $\Psi $ ,

  • if $Y\subseteq Y'$ , then we let $\pi _{Y, Y'}: M_Y\rightarrow M_{Y'}$ be the canonical embedding,

  • ${\mathcal { H}}$ and ${\mathcal { H}}^-$ are defined relative to $\mu $ as in Section 4.

We want to show that

(a) if $Y\in {\wp }_{j(\mu )}(N)\cap M$ is such that $Y_0\subseteq Y$ , then $\pi _Y^{-1}(j({\mathcal {P}}))=Lp^{cuB, \Sigma _Y}(\pi _Y^{-1}(A))$ .

Towards a contradiction, assume that (a) is false. Fix one such Y that is a counterexample to (a) and let ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } Lp^{cuB, \Sigma _Y}(\pi _Y^{-1}(A))$ be a sound $\Sigma _Y$ -mouse over $\pi _Y^{-1}(A)$ such that ${\mathcal {M}}\not {\trianglelefteq } \pi _Y^{-1}(j({\mathcal {P}}))$ and $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})=Ord\cap \pi _Y^{-1}(A)$ . We can then find some $\Sigma _{Y_0}$ -hod pair $({\mathcal {P}}^+, \Pi )\in M$ Footnote 71 and a hod pair $({\mathcal {S}}, \Phi )\in M$ such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {P}}^+\in H_{j(\mu )}^M$ and ${\mathcal {P}}^+$ is a hod premouse over $A_{\mu }$ extending ${\mathcal {P}}$ ,

  2. 2. $\Pi $ has strong branch condensation,

  3. 3. ${\mathcal {P}}^+$ is meek and of limit type (see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 2.7.1]),

  4. 4. ${\mathrm cf}^{{\mathcal {P}}^+}({\delta }^{{\mathcal {P}}^+})=\omega $ ,

  5. 5. $(Y\cap j({\mathcal { H}}^-))\subseteq {\mathrm rge}(\pi ^{\Phi }_{{\mathcal {S}}, \infty })$ and no proper complete layer of ${\mathcal {S}}$ has this property,Footnote 72

  6. 6. $\Pi \in M$ is a $(j(\mu ), j(\mu ))$ -strategy for ${\mathcal {P}}^+$ such that if $h\subseteq Coll(\omega , <j(\mu ))$ is M-generic, then $\Pi $ can be uniquely extended to a strategy $\Pi ^{h}\in (\Gamma ^{\infty })^{M[h]}$ , and moreover, $\Pi $ witnesses that ${\mathcal {P}}^+$ is a $\Sigma _{Y_0}$ -hod mouse.Footnote 73

Let $\tau : M_{Y_0}\rightarrow M_Y$ be the canonical embedding and let E be the long extender of length $Ord\cap \pi _Y^{-1}(Lp^{cuB, \Psi }(A))$ derived from $\tau $ . Because ${\mathcal {P}}^+$ might have cardinality $>\mu $ , when we form ${\mathcal {P}}_Y^+=_{def}Ult({\mathcal {P}}^+, E)$ , we cannot conclude that ${\mathcal {P}}_Y^+$ is iterable in M. This is because we do not know that $j{\restriction } {\mathcal {P}}^+\in M$ . To resolve this issue, we take a hull of size $\mu $ . Let $\mu _1=(\mu ^+)^V$ .

We work in M. We can now find $m: W\rightarrow N$ such that

  • $W\in M$ is transitive and $\mu +1\subseteq W$ ,

  • $(j({\mathcal {P}}), Y_0, Y, ({\mathcal {P}}^+, \Pi ), ({\mathcal {S}}, \Phi ))\in {\mathrm rge}(m)$ .

Let $Z=m^{-1}(Y)$ , ${\mathcal {N}}=m^{-1}({\mathcal {M}})$ , ${\mathcal {R}}=m^{-1}(j({\mathcal {P}}))$ and $k: {\mathcal {P}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {R}}$ be $m^{-1}(j{\restriction } {\mathcal {P}})$ . Working in M, set

  • ${\mathcal {Q}}=({\mathcal {P}}_{Z})^W$ ,

  • $\sigma =(\pi _{m^{-1}(Y_0), Z}{\restriction } {\mathcal {P}})^{W}$ and $\tau =(\pi _Z{\restriction } {\mathcal {Q}})^{W}$ ,

  • $\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}=m^{-1}({\mathcal {P}}^+)$ and $\overline {\Pi }=m^{-1}(\Pi )$ ,

  • $(\overline {{\mathcal {S}}}, \overline {\Phi })=m^{-1}({\mathcal {S}}, \Phi )$ .

Thus, we have that

(A) $k=\tau \circ \sigma $ , $\sigma :{\mathcal {P}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {Q}}$ and $\tau :{\mathcal {Q}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {R}}$ ,

(B) in W,

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a sound $\Sigma _{Z}$ -mouse over ${\mathcal {Q}}$ that projects to $Ord\cap {\mathcal {Q}}$ ,

  2. 2. in any derived model of $(\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}, \overline {\Pi })$ as computed by an ${\mathbb {R}}$ -genericity iteration, ${\mathcal {N}}$ has an $\omega _1$ -iteration strategy witnessing that it is a $\Sigma _Z$ -mouse,

  3. 3. ${\mathcal {N}}$ is not an initial segment of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ ,

  4. 4. $\overline {\Phi }$ is in the derived model of $(\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}, \overline {\Pi })$ as computed by any ${\mathbb {R}}$ -genericity iteration,

  5. 5. letting $\xi :\sigma ({\mathcal { H}})\rightarrow \overline {{\mathcal {S}}}|{\delta }^{\overline {{\mathcal {S}}}}$ be such that $\xi =(\pi ^{\overline {\Phi }}_{\overline {{\mathcal {S}}}, \infty })^{-1} \circ \tau $ , $\Sigma _Z=(\xi $ -pullback of $\overline {\Phi }_{\overline {{\mathcal {S}}}|{\delta }^{\overline {{\mathcal {S}}}}}$ .

Let now F be the long extender of length ${\delta }^{\mathcal {Q}}$ derived from $\sigma $ and set ${\mathcal {Q}}^+=Ult(\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}, F)$ . Let $\sigma ^+=\pi _F^{{\mathcal {P}}^+}$ . Notice that because $m\circ k=j{\restriction } {\mathcal {P}}$ , we have $\phi ^+:{\mathcal {Q}}^+\rightarrow j(\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+})$ such that

(C) $j{\restriction } \overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}=\phi ^+\circ \sigma ^+$ .

Let $\overline {\Pi }^+$ be the $m{\restriction } \overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}$ -pullback of $\Pi $ Footnote 74 and let $\overline {\Phi }^+$ be the m-pullback of $\Phi $ . Notice that

(D1) $\overline {\Pi }^+{\restriction } W= \overline {\Pi }$ ,Footnote 75

(D2) $\overline {\Pi }^+$ witnesses that $\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}$ is a $\Psi $ -hod mouseFootnote 76 ,

(D3) $\overline {\Phi }^+{\restriction } W= \overline {\Phi }$ .

Notice now that we have

(F) in M, $j(\overline {\Pi }^+{\restriction } H_{\mu _1}^{M})$ is a $(j(\mu ), j(\mu ))$ -iteration strategy witnessing that $j(\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+})$ is a $j(\Psi )$ -hod mouse, and moreover, $j{\restriction } \overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}\in M$ .Footnote 77

We let $\Gamma =(\Sigma _Z)^{W}$ . Notice that in W, $\Gamma $ is the $\tau $ -pullback of $m^{-1}(j(\Psi ))$ . Let $\Gamma ^+$ be the $\phi ^+{\restriction } {\mathcal {Q}}=m\circ \tau {\restriction } {\mathcal {Q}}$ -pullback of $j(\Psi )$ . It follows that

(G) $\Gamma ^+$ is the $m\circ \xi $ -pullback of $\Phi $ , and it is also $\xi $ -pullback of $\overline {\Phi }^+$ .

We now claim that

(b) in M, in any derived model of $(\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}, \overline {\Pi }^+)$ as computed by an ${\mathbb {R}}$ -genericity iteration, ${\mathcal {N}}$ has an $\omega _1$ -iteration strategy witnessesing that ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a $\Gamma ^+$ -mouse.

The proof of (b) is like the proof of Claim 1 of [Reference Sargsyan33, Lemma 10.4], and it is also very similar to the proof of (b) that appears in the proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 9.2.6]. Because of this, we skip the proof of (b).

To finish the proof of Proposition 5.9, it remains to implement the last portion of the proof of [Reference Sargsyan33, Theorem 10.3]. Let $\Delta _0$ be $\phi ^+$ -pullback of $j^+(\overline {\Pi }^+{\restriction } N)$ . Notice that it follows from (F) that $\Delta _0$ witnesses that ${\mathcal {Q}}^+$ is a $\Gamma ^+$ -hod mouse. It then follows from (b) that

(H) in M, in any derived model of $({\mathcal {Q}}^+, \Delta _0)$ as computed by an ${\mathbb {R}}$ -genericity iteration, ${\mathcal {N}}$ has an $\omega _1$ -iteration strategy $\Delta $ witnessing that ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a $\Gamma ^+$ -mouse.

(H) gives contradiction, as it implies that

(I) ${\mathcal {Q}}^+{\vDash } \text {`}Ord\cap {\mathcal {Q}}$ is not a cardinal’,Footnote 78

while clearly $\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}{\vDash } \text {`}Ord\cap {\mathcal {P}}$ is a cardinal’, contradicting the elementarity of $\phi ^+$ .

Proof of Theorem 5.2

We now prove Theorem 5.2. First, take S to be the stationary class of measurable cardinals which are limits of Woodin cardinals; for any $\mu \in S$ , $\mu $ satisfies clause (1) of Theorem 5.2 by Corollary 5.8. To get clauses (2) and (3), we apply Lemma 5.3 to the function f on S that maps each $\mu \in S$ to the maximum of the ordinals $\{\nu , \eta _{\mu }, \xi \}$ , where $\nu $ appears in Proposition 5.9, $\eta _{\nu }$ appears in the proof of Proposition 5.4, and $\xi $ appears in the statement of Corollary 5.8. Using Lemma 5.3, we obtain proper class $S_0\subseteq S$ such that for each $\mu \in S_0$ , $\nu $ witnesses clauses (2) and (3) of Theorem 5.2. This finishes the proof of Theorem 5.2. $\Box $

Remark 5.10.

  1. 1. By Lemma 5.3, the existence of $S,S_0,\nu $ above can be proved within $\mathsf {ZFC}$ .

  2. 2. It may appear that we use second-order set theory to ‘pick’ for each measurable limit of Woodin cardinals $\mu $ a set $A_{\mu }$ that codes $V_{\mu }$ , but the theory $\mathsf {ZFC} + $ ‘there is (global) well-order of V’ is conservative over $\mathsf {ZFC}$ . Over any $V{\vDash } \mathsf {ZFC}$ , we can find a (class) generic extension $V[g]$ of V such that $V[g]{\vDash } \text {`}\mathsf {ZFC} + $ there is a global well order’.

  3. 3. The above two remarks simply say that we may assume as part of the hypothesis that V has a global well-order. This then allows us to get $S, S_0, \nu $ and the sequences $(Y_{\mu }: \mu \in S_0)$ , $(A_{\mu }: \mu \in S)$ in Theorem 5.2.

The rest of the argument does not need the hypothesis that $\Gamma ^{\infty }{\vDash } _{\Omega } \mathsf {AD}_{{\mathbb {R}}}$ . It only needs the conclusion of Theorem 5.2. To stress this point, we make the following definitions.

Definition 5.11. We let T stand for the following theory.

  1. 1. $T_0$

  2. 2. There is a stationary class S, a proper class $S_0\subseteq S$ , an infinite regular cardinal $\nu $ and two sequences $\vec {Y}=(Y_{\mu }: \mu \in S_0)$ and $\vec {A}=(A_{\mu }: \mu \in S)$ such that the following conditions hold for any $\mu \in S$ :

    1. (a) $\mu $ is a measurable limit of Woodin cardinals,

    2. (b) $\mu $ stabilizes uB,

    3. (c) ${\vert {\mathcal {H}}_{\mu }}\vert <\mu ^+$ ,

    4. (d) $A_{\mu }\subseteq \mu $ codes $V_{\mu }$ and $\max ({\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal { H}}_{\mu }), {\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap Lp^{cuB, \Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu }))<\mu $ ;

    furthermore, if $\mu \in S_0$ , then the following hold:

    1. (a) $\max ({\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal { H}}_{\mu }), {\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap Lp^{cuB, \Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu }))<\nu $ ,

    2. (b) $Y_{\mu }\in {\wp }_{\nu }(H_{\mu ^+})$ ,

    3. (c) $A_{\mu }\in Y_{\mu }$ , and

    4. (d) whenever $X\prec H_{\mu ^+}$ is of size $<\mu $ , is $\nu $ -closed and $Y_{\mu }\subseteq X$ , X capturesFootnote 79 $Lp^{cuB, \Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })$ .

6. Condensing sets

Here, we review some facts about condensing sets that were introduced in [Reference Sargsyan33] and developed further in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 9.1]. We develop this notion assuming the theory T introduced in Definition 5.11. Let $(S, S_0, \nu _0,\vec {Y}, \vec {A})$ witness that T is true.

Fix $\mu \in S_0$ and let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\mu )$ be generic. We let $ \mathcal {H}, \Psi $ , etc. stand for the CMI objects associated with $\mu $ . We summarize some basic notions and results concerning condensing sets which will play a key role in our $K^c$ -constructions. [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 9] gives more details and proofs of basic facts about these objects.

The notion of fullness that we will use is full in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ . Notice that if $\Phi \in L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ is an $\omega _1$ -strategy with hull condensation, then in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ , for any $x\in {\mathbb {R}}_g$ , $OD(\Phi )$ is the stack of $\omega _1$ -iterable $\Phi $ -mice over x.Footnote 80 Because any such $\Phi $ -mouse has an iteration strategy in $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ , it follows that ‘full in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ ’ is equivalent to ‘full with respect to $Lp^{cuB}$ in $V[g]$ ’. Thus, given ${\mathcal {M}}\in HC^{V[g]}$ , we say ${\mathcal {M}}$ is $\Phi $ -full if for any ${\mathcal {M}}$ -cutpoint $\eta $ , $Lp^{cuB, \Phi }({\mathcal {M}}|\eta )\in {\mathcal {M}}$ . If ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a $\Phi $ -mouse over ${\mathcal {M}}|\eta $ , then by ‘ ${\mathcal {M}}$ is $\Phi $ -full’, we in fact mean that ${\mathcal {M}}|(\eta ^+)^{\mathcal {M}}=Lp^{cuB, \Phi }({\mathcal {M}}|\eta )$ . Here, we note again that ‘ $Lp^{cuB,\Phi }$ ’ is computed in $V[g]$ .

We start working in $V[g]$ . Following [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 9], for each $Z\subseteq {\mathcal { H}}$ , we let

  • ${\mathcal {Q}}_Z$ be the transitive collapse of $Hull_1^{\mathcal {H}}(Z)$ ,

  • $\tau _Z:{\mathcal {Q}}_Z\rightarrow \mathcal {H}$ be the uncollapse map, and

  • $\delta _Z = \delta ^{{\mathcal {Q}}_Z}$ , where $\tau _Z(\delta _Z) = \Theta = \delta ^{\mathcal {H}}$ .

For $X\subseteq Y \in {\wp }_{\omega _1}(\mathcal {H})$ , let

$$ \begin{align*} \tau_{X, Y}= \tau^{-1}_Y \circ \tau_X. \end{align*} $$

Definition 6.1. Let $Z\in {\wp }_{\omega _1}(\mathcal {H})$ . $Y \in {\wp }_{\omega _1}(\mathcal {H}^{-})$ is a simple extension of Z if

$$ \begin{align*} Hull_1^{\mathcal{H}} (Z \cup Y )\cap \mathcal{H}^- \subseteq Y. \end{align*} $$

Let $Z,Y$ be as in Definition 6.1. Let

(4) $$ \begin{align} Y \oplus Z = Hull_1^{\mathcal{H}}(Z\cup Y). \end{align} $$

Let

(5) $$ \begin{align} \tau^Z_Y = \tau_{Z\oplus Y}, \end{align} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*} \pi^Z_Y: {\mathcal{Q}}_Z \rightarrow {\mathcal{Q}}_{Z\oplus Y} \text{ be } \tau_{Z,Y\oplus Z}; \end{align*} $$

we also write ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ for ${\mathcal {Q}}_{Z\oplus Y}$ and $\delta ^Z_Y$ for $\delta ^{{\mathcal {Q}}_{Z\oplus Y}}$ . We have that

(6) $$ \begin{align} \tau_Z = \tau^Z_{Y}\circ \pi^Z_Y. \end{align} $$

Given two simple extensions of Z, $Y_0 \subseteq Y_1$ , we let $\pi ^Z_{Y_0,Y_1}:{\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Y_0} \rightarrow {\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Y_1}$ be the natural map. We also let

$$ \begin{align*} \Psi^Z_Y = \tau_Y^Z\text{-pullback of } \Psi. \end{align*} $$

Definition 6.2. Y is an extension of Z if Y is a simple extension of Z and $\pi ^Z_Y{\restriction } ( {\mathcal {Q}}_Z|\delta _Z)$ is the iteration embedding according to $\Psi ^Z_Y$ . Here, we allow Z to be an extension of itself.

Suppose Y is an extension of Z. Let $\sigma ^Z_{Y}:{\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y\rightarrow \mathcal {H}$ be given by

(7) $$ \begin{align} \sigma^Z_{Y}(q) = \tau_Z(f)(\pi^{\Psi^Z_Y}_{{\mathcal{Q}}^Z_Y,\infty}(a)), \end{align} $$

where $a\in ({\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y|\delta ^Z_Y)^{<\omega }$ and $q = \pi ^Z_{Y}(f)(a)$ .

Definition 6.3. Y is an honest extension of Z if

  1. 1. Y is an extension of Z,

  2. 2. $\mathrm {dom}(\sigma _Y^Z)={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ and $\sigma _Y^Z$ is elementary,

  3. 3. $\tau _Z =\sigma _Y^Z \circ \pi _Y^Z$ .Footnote 81

We say Y is an iteration extension of Z if Y is an honest extension of Z and $Y=\sigma ^Z_Y[{\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y|\delta ^Z_Y]$ .

Definition 6.4. We say Z is a simply condensing set if

  1. 1. for any extension Y of Z, ${\mathcal {Q}}_Y^Z$ is $\Psi ^Z_Y$ -full,

  2. 2. all extensions Y of Z are honest.

We say Z is condensing if for every extension Y of Z, $Z \oplus Y$ is a simply condensing set.

In $V[g]$ , let

$$ \begin{align*} Cnd(\mathcal{H}) = \{Z \in {\wp}_{\omega_1}(\mathcal{H}) : Z \textrm{ is condensing}\}. \end{align*} $$

Results in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 9] give the following:

Theorem 6.5. In $V[g]$ , $Cnd(\mathcal {H})$ is a club in ${\wp }_{\omega _1}(\mathcal {H})$ (i.e., it is unbounded and is closed under countable unions).

Furthermore, for any cardinal $\kappa \geq \nu _0$ and $\kappa <\mu $ , $\{X\in V: X \in Cnd(\mathcal {H})\wedge |X|^V \leq \kappa \} $ is a club in ${\wp }^V_{\kappa ^+}(\mathcal {H})$ . The same holds if V is replaced by $V[g\cap Coll(\omega , <\kappa )]$ .

Furthermore, for each $Z\in Cnd({\mathcal { H}})$ , if Y is an honest extension of Z, then Y is an iteration extension of Z.

Also, the following uniqueness fact is very important for this paper. It follows from Proposition 2.9 and can be proved exactly the same way as [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Lemma 9.1.14].

Proposition 6.6. Suppose Z is a condensing set. Suppose Y and W are extensions of Z such that ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_W$ . Then $\Psi ^Z_Y=\Psi ^Z_W$ .

The following are easy corollaries of Proposition 6.6.

Corollary 6.7. Suppose Z is a condensing set and ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is such that for some extension Y of Z, ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ . There is then a unique honest extension W of Z such that ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_W$ .

Corollary 6.8. Suppose Z is a condensing set. Suppose further that Y and W are two extensions of Z such that there is an embedding $i:{\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y\rightarrow _{\Sigma _1} {\mathcal {Q}}^Z_W$ such that $\tau ^Z_W\circ i[{\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y]$ is an extension of Z. Then the i-pullback of $\Psi ^Z_W$ is $\Psi ^Z_Y$ .

Proof. Let $Y^*=\tau ^Z_W\circ i[{\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y]$ . We have that ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Y}={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Y^*}$ . Moreover, $\Psi ^Z_Y=\Psi ^Z_{Y^*}$ and $\Psi ^Z_{Y^*}$ is the i-pullback of $\Psi ^Z_{W}$ .

7. Z-realizable iterations

In this section, we fix a condensing set Z.

Definition 7.1. Let Z be a condensing set. ${\mathcal {Q}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {Q}}_Z$ if ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is non-meekFootnote 82 and ${\mathcal {Q}}^b = {\mathcal {Q}}_Z$ . We also say that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is a nice extension of ${\mathcal {Q}}_Z$ .

Suppose Y is an extension of Z and ${\mathcal {Q}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ . We would like to analyze the stacks on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ , following the terminology and conventions used in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38]. A stackFootnote 83 ${\mathcal {T}}$ on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ has the form

$$ \begin{align*} {\vec{\mathcal{T}}}=(({\mathcal{M}}_{\alpha})_{{\alpha}<\eta}, (E_{\alpha})_{{\alpha}<\eta-1}, D, R, (\beta_{\alpha}, m_{\alpha})_{{\alpha}\in R}, T), \end{align*} $$

where the displayed objects are introduced in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 2.4.1]. The above notation is quite standard. D is the set of drops, R is the set of stages where player I starts a new round of the iteration game, $(\beta _{\alpha }, m_{\alpha })$ is the place player I drops at the beginning of the ${\alpha }$ th round, and T is the tree order. We adopt an important convention introduced in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38]. Namely, we assume that all our stacks are proper (see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Remark 2.7.27]). One of the key aspects of being proper is that if ${\beta }<lh({\vec {\mathcal {T}}})$ is such that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}_{\geq {\beta }}$ is a stack on ${\mathcal {M}}^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}_{\beta }$ , then ${\beta }\in R$ .Footnote 84 We will also use the notation introduced in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Notation 2.4.4]. In particular, for ${\alpha }\in R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ , ${\mathsf {next}}^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}({\alpha })=min(R^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}-({\alpha }+1))$ if this minimum exists and otherwise ${\mathsf {next}}^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}({\alpha })=lh({\vec {\mathcal {T}}})$ . For ${\alpha }\in R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ , we also set ${\mathsf {nc}}^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}_{\alpha }={\vec {\mathcal {T}}}_{[{\alpha }, {\alpha }']}$ , where ${\alpha }'={\mathsf {next}}^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}({\alpha })$ .

Definition 7.2. Suppose $Z\in Cnd({\mathcal { H}})$ and Y is an extension of Z. Suppose further that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ . Given $E\in \vec {E}^{\mathcal {Q}}$ such that $\mathrm {crit }(E)={\delta }^{{\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y}$ , we say E is $(Z, Y)$ -realizable if there is W, an extension of $Z\oplus Y$ such that $E=E^Z_{Y, W}$ , where $E^Z_{Y,W}$ is the extender defined by

(8) $$ \begin{align} (a,A)\in E^Z_{Y,W} \Leftrightarrow \tau^Z_{W}(a) = \pi^{\Psi^Z_W}_{{\mathcal{Q}}^Z_W,\infty}(a)\in \tau^Z_Y(A), \end{align} $$

for any $a\in [lh(E)]^{<\omega }$ and $A\in {\wp }(\mathrm {crit }(E))^{|a|}\cap {\mathcal {Q}}$ .

We are continuing with the notation of Definition 7.2. Suppose ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a stack on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ . We say ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a $(Z, Y)$ -realizable iteration if there is a sequence $(W_{\alpha }: {\alpha } \in R^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}})$ such that

  1. 1. $W_0=Y$ ,

  2. 2. if ${\alpha }, {\beta }\in R^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}$ and ${\alpha }<{\beta }$ , then $W_{\beta }$ is an extension of $Z\oplus W_{\alpha }$ ,

  3. 3. if ${\alpha }, {\beta }\in R^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}$ , ${\alpha }<{\beta }$ and $\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}, b}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}$ is defined, then $\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}, b}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}=\pi ^Z_{W_{\alpha }, W_{\beta }}$ ,Footnote 85 and

  4. 4. if ${\alpha }\in R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ and ${\vec {\mathcal {U}}}$ is the largest fragment of ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}_{\geq {\alpha }}$ that is based on ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^b$ , then ${\vec {\mathcal {U}}}$ is according to $\Psi ^Z_{W_{\alpha }}$ .

We say ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is Z -realizable if Y is an honest extension of Z and ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is $(Z, Y)$ -realizable.

The following lemma is a consequence os Proposition 6.6, Corollary 6.7 and Corollary 6.8.

Lemma 7.3. Suppose Y is an extension of Z and ${\mathcal {Q}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ . Suppose ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a $(Z, Y)$ -realizable iteration as witnessed by $(W^{\prime }_{\alpha }: {\alpha } \in R^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}})$ . For ${\alpha }\in R^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}$ , let $W_{\alpha }$ be the unique honest extension of Z with the property that $({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}})^b={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{W_{\alpha }}$ . Then $(W_{\alpha }: {\alpha }\in R^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}})$ witnesses that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is Z-realizable.

Proof. It is enough to show that if ${\alpha }, {\beta }\in R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ and ${\beta }=\min (R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}-({\alpha }+1))$ , then $\pi ^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}=\pi ^Z_{W_{\alpha }, W_{\beta }}$ . First, we show that $W_{\alpha }\subseteq W_{\beta }$ . We have that $x\in W_{\alpha }$ if for some $a\in {\delta }_{Z\oplus W_{\alpha }}$ and some $f\in Z$ , $x=\tau _Z(f)(\tau ^Z_{W_{\alpha }}(a))$ . Since $\tau ^Z_{W_{\alpha }}{\restriction } {\delta }_{Z\oplus W_{\alpha }}$ , $\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}, b}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}{\restriction } {\delta }_{Z\oplus W_{\alpha }}$ and $\tau ^Z_{W_{\beta }}\circ \pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}, b}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}{\restriction } {\delta }_{Z\oplus W_{\alpha }}$ are all iteration embeddings according to $\Psi ^Z_{W_{\alpha }}$ , we have that $x=\tau _Z(f)(\tau ^Z_{W_{\beta }}(\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}, b}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}(a))$ . Thus, $W_{\alpha }\subseteq W_{\beta }$ . A similar argument shows that $\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}, b}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}=\tau ^Z_{W_{\alpha }, W_{\beta }}$ .

Remark 7.4. It follows from Lemma 7.3 that $(Z, Y)$ -realizability is equivalent to Z-realizability. Because of this, in this paper, we will mostly use Z-realizability.

Suppose ${\mathcal {Q}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ and ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a Z-realizable iteration of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ . We cannot in general prove that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ picks unique branches mainly because we say nothing about ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures that appear in ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ when we iterate above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^b}$ for some ${\alpha }\in R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ . The next definition introduces a notion of a premouse that resolves this issue.

Definition 7.5. We say ${\mathcal {R}}$ is weakly Z -suitable if ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a hod premouse of lsa type such that ${\mathcal {R}}=({\mathcal {R}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}})^{\#}$ , ${\mathcal {R}}$ has no Woodin cardinals in the interval $({\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}^b}, {\delta }^{\mathcal {R}})$ and for some extension Y of Z, ${\mathcal {R}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {R}}^b={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ .

The following lemma says that hulls of Z-realizable iterations are Z-realizable and easily follows from Corollary 6.8.

Proposition 7.6. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\mathcal {S}}$ are weakly Z-suitable hod premice. Suppose further that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a Z-realizable iteration of ${\mathcal {S}}$ and ${\vec {\mathcal {U}}}$ is an iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $({\mathcal {R}}, {\vec {\mathcal {U}}})$ is a hullFootnote 86 of $({\mathcal {S}}, {\vec {\mathcal {T}}})$ . Then ${\vec {\mathcal {U}}}$ is Z-realizable.

We now define the notion of Z-approved sts premouse of depth n by induction on n. The induction ranges over all weakly Z-suitable hod premice.

Definition 7.7. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is weakly Z-suitable hod premouse and for some extension Y of Z, ${\mathcal {R}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {R}}^b={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ .

  1. 1. We say that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z -approved sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ of depth $0$ if ${\mathcal {M}}$ is an sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ Footnote 87 such that if ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ is according to $S^{\mathcal {M}}$ , then ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $(Z, Y)$ -realizable.

  2. 2. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is weakly Z-suitable hod premouse. We say that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z -approved sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ of depth $n+1$ if ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-approved sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ of depth n such that if ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ and $S^{\mathcal {M}}({\mathcal {T}})$ is defined, then letting $b=S^{\mathcal {M}}({\mathcal {T}})$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ is a Z-approved sts premouse over ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ of depth n.

Definition 7.8. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z -approved sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ if for each $n<\omega $ , ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-approved sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ of depth n. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ as above is a Z -approved sts mouse (over ${\mathcal {R}}$ ) if ${\mathcal {M}}$ has a $\mu $ -strategy $\Sigma $ such that whenever ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a $\Sigma $ -iterate of ${\mathcal {M}}$ , ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a Z-approved sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

The following proposition is an immediate consequence of our definitions but perhaps is a bit tedious to prove.

Proposition 7.9. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\mathcal {S}}$ are weakly Z-suitable, ${\mathcal {N}}$ is an sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-approved premouse (mouse) over ${\mathcal {S}}$ . Suppose $\pi :{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow _{\Sigma _1} {\mathcal {M}}$ . Then ${\mathcal {N}}$ is also a Z-approved premouse (mouse).

Proof. We only show that if ${\mathcal {T}}^*\in {\mathcal {N}}$ is according to $S^{\mathcal {N}}$ , then ${\mathcal {T}}^*$ is Z-realizable. Even less, we show that if ${\mathcal {T}}^*={\mathcal {T}}^\frown {\mathcal {U}}$ is such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists and ${\mathcal {U}}$ is based on $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {R}}^b)$ , then there is an extension Y of Z such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {R}}^b)={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Y}$ and ${\mathcal {U}}$ is according to $\Psi ^Z_{Y}$ . The rest of the proof is very similar.

Notice that by elementarity of $\pi $ , $\pi ({\mathcal {T}}^*)$ is according to $S^{\mathcal {M}}$ . Therefore, there is some extension W of Z such that $\pi (\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {R}}^b))={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{W}$ and $\pi ({\mathcal {U}})$ is according to $\Psi ^Z_W$ . Set $Y=\tau ^Z_W\circ \pi [\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {R}}^b)]$ . Then $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal {R}}^b)={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Y}$ and ${\mathcal {U}}$ is according to the $\pi $ -pullback of $\Psi ^Z_{W}$ . As the $\pi $ -pullback of $\Psi ^Z_{W}$ is just $\Psi ^Z_{Y}$ , we are done.

Definition 7.10. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is weakly Z-suitable. We let $Lp^{Za, sts}({\mathcal {R}})$ be the union of all Z-approved sound sts mice ${\mathcal {M}}$ over ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}) \leq Ord\cap {\mathcal {R}}$ .

Finally, we can define the correctly guided Z-realizable iterations.

Definition 7.11. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a weakly Z-suitable hod premouse and ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a Z-realizable iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ . We say ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is correctly guided if whenever ${\alpha }\in R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ , ${\mathcal {U}}=_{def}{\mathsf {nc}}^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}_{\alpha }$ is above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^b}$ , ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {U}})$ is a limit ordinal such that ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha }){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ is a Woodin cardinal’. Then, letting $b=[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {U}}$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {U}}{\restriction }\alpha )$ is a Z-approved sts mouse over ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {U}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ .

Combining Proposition 7.6 and Proposition 7.9, we get the following.

Corollary 7.12. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\mathcal {S}}$ are weakly Z-suitable hod premice. Suppose further that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a correctly guided Z-realizable iteration of ${\mathcal {S}}$ and ${\vec {\mathcal {U}}}$ is an iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $({\mathcal {R}}, {\vec {\mathcal {U}}})$ is a hull of $({\mathcal {S}}, {\vec {\mathcal {T}}})$ (in the sense of [Reference Sargsyan34, Definition 1.30]). Then ${\vec {\mathcal {U}}}$ is also correctly guided Z-realizable iteration.

Our uniqueness theorem applies to ${\mathcal {R}}$ that are not infinitely descending.

Definition 7.13. We say that a weakly Z-suitable hod premouse ${\mathcal {R}}$ is infinitely descending if there is a sequence $(p_i, {\mathcal {R}}_i, Y_i: i<\omega )$ such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {R}}_0={\mathcal {R}}$ ,

  2. 2. for every $i<\omega $ , ${\mathcal {R}}_i$ is weakly Z-suitable,

  3. 3. for every $i<\omega $ , $p_i$ is a correctly guided Z-realizable iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}_i$ ,

  4. 4. for every $i<\omega $ , $p_i$ has a last normal component ${\mathcal {T}}_i$ of successor lengthFootnote 88 such that ${\alpha }_i=_{def}lh({\mathcal {T}}_i)-1$ is a limit ordinal and ${\mathcal {R}}_{i+1}={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}_i{\restriction } {\alpha }_i)$ ,

  5. 5. for every $i<\omega $ , setting $b_i=_{def}[0, {\alpha }_i)_{{\mathcal {T}}_i}$ , $b_i$ is a cofinal branch of ${\mathcal {T}}_i$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_i, {\mathcal {T}}_i)$ exists and is Z-approved.

Note that in the above definition, for each i, ${\mathcal {R}}_{i+1}$ is a strict initial segment of ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_i, {\mathcal {T}}_i)$ . The following is our uniqueness result.

Proposition 7.14. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a weakly Z-suitable hod premouse that is not infinitely descending and ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a correctly guided Z-realizable iteration of limit length on ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Then there is at most one branch b of ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ such that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}^\frown \{b\}$ is correctly guided and Z-realizable.

Here, we outline the proof. First notice that

(a) if ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ does not have a last component or

(b) if there is ${\alpha }\in R^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ such that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}_{\geq {\alpha }}$ is based on ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^b$ ,

then there is nothing to prove, as letting $W_{\mathcal {S}}$ be as in Definition 7.2, $\Psi ^Z_{W_S}$ only depends on ${\mathcal {S}}^b$ (e.g., see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Lemma 9.1.9]).Footnote 89 Let now ${\mathcal {T}}={\mathsf {nc}}^{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}_{\alpha }$ be the last normal component of ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ . If $b, c$ are two different branches of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}^\frown \{b\}$ and ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}^\frown \{c\}$ are correctly guided Z-realizable iterations, then ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})\not ={\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})$ and both are Z-approved sts mice over ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ . It now follows from [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Lemma 4.7.2] and the fact that ${\mathcal {R}}$ is not infinitely descending that we can reduce the disagreement of ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ and ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})$ to a disagreement between $\Psi ^Z_X$ and $\Psi ^Z_U$ for some extensions $X,U$ of Z with ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_X={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_U$ . However, this cannot happen by Proposition 6.6 (the proof is given by [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Lemma 9.1.9]).

8. Z-validated iterations

We continue by assuming T. Let $(S, S_0, \nu _0,\vec {Y}, \vec {A})$ again witness that T is true and let $\mu , g, \mathcal {H}$ , etc. be defined as in Section 4. The goal of this section is to introduce some concepts to be used in the $K^c$ construction of the next section. The main new concept here is the concept of Z-validated iterations, which are the kind of iterations that will appear in the $K^c$ construction of the next section.

The following definition is important for this paper. It introduces the hulls that we will use to Z-validate mice, iterations, etc. It goes back to Steel’s [Reference Steel46].

Definition 8.1. Suppose ${\lambda }\in S_0-\mu $ and $U \prec _1 H_{{\lambda }^+}$ . We say U is $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good if $\mu \in U$ , $(Y_{\mu }\cup Y_{\lambda } \cup Z)\subseteq U$ , $\vert {U}\vert <\mu $ , $U\cap {\mathcal { H}}^-$ is an honest extension of Z and $U^{\nu _0}\subseteq U$ . When $\mu $ and ${\lambda }$ are clear from the context or are not important, we simply say U is a good hull. We say a good hull U is transitive below $\mu $ if $U\cap \mu \in \mu $

If U is a good hull, then we let $\pi _U : M_U = M \rightarrow H_{{\lambda }^+}$ be the inverse of the transitive collapse of U. If, in addition, U is transitive below $\mu $ , we let $\pi _U^+:M_U[g_{\nu }]\rightarrow H_{\Omega }[g]$ , where $\nu =\mathrm {crit }(\pi _U)$ and $g_{\nu }=g\cap Coll(\omega , <\nu )$ .

Definition 8.2. Suppose

  • ${\mathcal {R}}_0$ nicely extends ${\mathcal { H}}$ ,

  • p is an iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}_0$ ,

  • if p is ${\mathsf {nuvs}}$ , then setting ${\mathcal {R}}={\mathrm m}^+(p)$ , ${\mathcal {M}}$ is an sts mouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ , and

  • ${\lambda }\in S$ is the least such that $({\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {M}}, p)\in H_{\lambda }$ .

  1. 1. We say ${\mathcal {R}}$ is not infinitely descending if whenever U is a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that ${\mathcal {R}}\in U$ , $\pi _U^{-1}({\mathcal {R}})$ is not infinitely descending.

  2. 2. We say p is Z -validated if whenever U is a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $\{{\mathcal {R}}, p\}\subseteq U$ , $\pi _U^{-1}(p)$ is a correctly guidedFootnote 90 Z-realizable iteration of $\pi _U^{-1}({\mathcal {R}})$ .

  3. 3. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a weakly Z-suitable hod premouse above $\mu $ . We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z -validated sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ if for every $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull U such that $\{{\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {M}}\}\subseteq U$ , letting ${\mathcal {N}}=\pi _U^{-1}({\mathcal {M}})$ , ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a Z-approvedFootnote 91 sts premouse over $\pi ^{-1}_U({\mathcal {R}})$ .

  4. 4. Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ and $\xi $ is an ordinal. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ has a Z-validated $\xi $ -iteration strategy if there is $\Sigma $ such that $\Sigma $ is a $\xi $ -iteration strategy and whenever ${\mathcal {N}}$ is an iterate of ${\mathcal {M}}$ via $\Sigma $ , ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

  5. 5. Suppose q is an iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ . We say q is Z -validated if $p^\frown q$ is Z-validated.

The following proposition is very useful and is an immediate consequence of Proposition 7.9. When X is a good hull, we will use it as a subscript to denote the $\pi _X$ -preimages of objects that are in X.

Proposition 8.3. Suppose $({\mathcal {R}}_0, p, {\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {M}}, {\lambda })$ are as in Definition 8.2. Suppose U is a $(Z, \mu , {\lambda })$ -good hull such that $\{{\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {M}}\}\subseteq U$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_U$ is not Z-approved. Then whenever $U^*$ is a $(Z, \mu , {\lambda })$ -good hull such that $U\cup \{U\}\subseteq U^*$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{U^*}$ is not Z-approved.Footnote 92

Similarly for iterations.

Proposition 8.4. Suppose $({\mathcal {R}}_0, p, {\lambda })$ are as in Definition 8.2. Suppose U is a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $\{{\mathcal {R}}_0, p\}\subseteq U$ and $p_U$ is not Z-realizable. Then whenever $U^*$ is a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $U\cup \{U\}\subseteq U^*$ , $p_{U^*}$ is not Z-realizable.Footnote 93

Definition 8.5. Suppose $({\mathcal {R}}_0, p, {\mathcal {R}}, \mu )$ are as in Definition 8.2. We let $Lp^{Zv, sts}({\mathcal {R}})$ be the union of all Z-validated sound sts mice over ${\mathcal {R}}$ that project to $Ord\cap {\mathcal {R}}$ .

The following proposition is a consequence of Proposition 7.14.

Proposition 8.6. Suppose $({\mathcal {R}}_0, p, {\mathcal {R}}, \mu )$ are as in Definition 8.2 and ${\mathcal {R}}$ is not infinitely descending. Suppose ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ is a Z-validated iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ of limit length. Then there is at most one branch b of ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ such that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}^\frown \{b\}$ is Z-validated.

9. Realizability array

We continue with $(S, S_0, \nu _0,\vec {Y}, \vec {A})$ , $\mu \in S_0$ , etc. We define the notion of an array at $\mu $ by induction. We say $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}={\mathcal {V}}_0$ is an array of length $0$ if ${\mathcal {V}}_0={\mathcal { H}}$ . Suppose we have already defined the meaning of array of length $<\eta $ . We want to define the meaning of array of length $\eta $ .

Definition 9.1. We say $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}=({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha }:{\alpha }\leq \eta )$ is an array of length $\eta $ at $\mu $ if the following conditions hold.

  1. 1. For every ${\alpha }<\eta $ , $({\mathcal {V}}_{\beta }:{\beta }\leq {\alpha })$ is an array of length ${\alpha }$ at $\mu $ .

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ nicely extends ${\mathcal { H}}$ and is a hod premouse.

  3. 3. For all ${\alpha }<\eta $ , if ${\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha }$ is weakly Z-suitable, then there is ${\beta }\leq \eta $ such that ${\mathcal {V}}_{\beta }$ is a Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha }$ and $rud({\mathcal {V}}_{\beta }){\vDash } $ ‘there are no Woodin cardinals $>{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ ’.

  4. 4. For all ${\alpha }<\eta $ , if $rud({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha }){\vDash } $ ‘there are no Woodin cardinals $>{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ ’, then ${\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha }$ has a Z-validated iteration strategy.

We say $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is small if $rud({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }){\vDash }$ ‘there are no Woodin cardinals $>{\delta }^{\mathcal { H}}$ ’. We let $\eta =lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ and for ${\alpha }\leq \eta $ , we let $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}{\restriction } {\alpha }=({\mathcal {V}}_{\beta }:{\beta }\leq {\alpha })$ .

Recall the notions of k-maximal iteration trees in [Reference Steel53, Definition 3.4] and weak k-embeddings [Reference Steel53, Definition 4.1]. For an iteration tree ${\mathcal {T}}$ on ${\mathcal {M}}$ , letting ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_{\alpha }$ be the $\alpha $ -th model in the tree; for $\alpha +1<lh({\mathcal {T}})$ , recall the notion of degree $deg^{\mathcal {T}}(\alpha +1)$ [Reference Steel53, Definition 3.7]. Recall the definition of $D^{\mathcal {T}}$ : if $\alpha +1\in D$ , then the extender $E^{\mathcal {T}}_{\alpha +1}$ is applied to a strict initial segment of ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_{\beta }$ , where $\beta = T-pred(\alpha +1)$ . For $\lambda $ limit, $deg^{\mathcal {T}}(\lambda )$ is the eventual values of $deg^{\mathcal {T}}(\alpha +1)$ for $\alpha +1\in [0,\lambda ]_{\mathcal {T}}$ . For a cofinal branch b of ${\mathcal {T}}$ , $deg^{\mathcal {T}}(b)$ is defined to be the eventual value of $deg^{\mathcal {T}}(\alpha +1)$ for $\alpha +1\in b$ . We write $\mathcal {C}_k({\mathcal {M}})$ for the k-th core of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Sometimes, we confuse $\mathcal {C}_0({\mathcal {M}})$ with ${\mathcal {M}}$ itself.

Definition 9.2. Suppose $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is an array at $\mu $ . We say $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ has the Z-realizability property if for all ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {V}})$ , $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ has the Z-realizability property and whenever $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\mu )$ is generic, in $V[g]$ , whenever $\pi :{\mathcal {W}}\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_k({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ and ${\mathcal {T}}$ are such that

  1. 1. $\pi $ is a weak k-embedding,

  2. 2. $Z\subseteq rng(\pi )$ ,

  3. 3. ${\mathcal {W}}, {\mathcal {T}}\in HC$ ,

  4. 4. ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a correctly guided Z-realizableFootnote 94 k-maximal iteration of ${\mathcal {W}}$ that is above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ ,

one of the following holds (in $V[g]$ ).

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {T}}$ is of limit length and there is a cofinal well-founded branch c such that c has no drops in model (i.e., $D^{\mathcal {T}}\cap b = \emptyset $ ); letting $l=deg^{\mathcal {T}}(b)$ , there is a weak l-embedding $\tau :{\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_c\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ such that $\pi {\restriction } {\mathcal {W}}=\tau \circ \pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_c$ .

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {T}}$ is of limit length and there is a cofinal well-founded branch c such that c has a drop in model, and there is ${\beta }<\eta $ and a weak l-embedding $\tau :{\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_c\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\beta })$ such that $\tau {\restriction } ({\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_c)^b=\pi {\restriction } ({\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_c)^b$ , where $l=deg^{\mathcal {T}}(c)$ .

  3. 3. ${\mathcal {T}}$ has a last model and letting ${\gamma }=lh({\mathcal {T}})-1$ , $[0, {\gamma }]_{\mathcal {T}}\cap \mathcal {D}^{\mathcal {T}}=\emptyset $ and there is a weak l-embedding $\tau :{\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_{\gamma }\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ such that $\pi {\restriction } {\mathcal {W}}=\tau \circ \pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ , where $l = deg^{\mathcal {T}}(\gamma )$ .

  4. 4. ${\mathcal {T}}$ has a last model and letting ${\gamma }=lh({\mathcal {T}})-1$ , $[0, {\gamma }]_{\mathcal {T}}\cap \mathcal {D}^{\mathcal {T}}\not =\emptyset $ and for some ${\beta }<\eta $ , there is a weak l-embedding $\tau :{\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_{\gamma }\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\beta })$ such that $\tau {\restriction } ({\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_{\gamma })^b=\pi {\restriction } ({\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_{\gamma })^b$ , where $l = deg^{\mathcal {T}}(\gamma )$ .

When the above 4 clauses hold, we say that ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $(\pi , \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -realizable.

In the following, we will follow the convention in [Reference Steel55, Section 1.3]: a (hod, hybrid, or pure extender) premouse has the form $({\mathcal {M}},k)$ , where ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a k-sound, acceptable J-structure. $k({\mathcal {M}}) = k$ is the degree of soundness of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . We write the core $\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {M}})$ for the ( $k({\mathcal {M}})+1$ -)core of ${\mathcal {M}}$ (if this makes sense – that is, when ${\mathcal {M}}$ is $k({\mathcal {M}})+1$ -solid). Similarly, we write $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})$ for the $k({\mathcal {M}})+1$ -projectum and $p({\mathcal {M}})$ for the $k({\mathcal {M}})+1$ -standard parameters of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . When $\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {M}})$ exists, $k(\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {M}})) = k({\mathcal {M}})+1$ . ${\mathcal {M}}$ is sound iff ${\mathcal {M}} = \mathcal {C}({\mathcal {M}})$ . We allow our iterations (e.g., Z-validated iterations) to consist of stacks of normal trees, where we may drop gratuitously at the start of a tree.

Proposition 9.3. Suppose $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is an array with Z-realizability property. Assume further that p is a Z-validated iteration of $\mathcal {C}_n({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ (for some n) with last model ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $\pi ^p$ exists and all the generators of p are contained in ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}^b}$ . Suppose U is a good hull such that $(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, {\mathcal {R}}, p)\in U$ . Let ${\mathcal {R}}_U = \pi _U^{-1}({\mathcal {R}}), p_U = \pi ^{-1}(p), {\mathcal {W}} = \pi ^{-1}(\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }))$ . There is then a weak n-embedding $k:{\mathcal {R}}_U\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_n({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ such that $\pi _U{\restriction } {\mathcal {W}}=k\circ \pi ^{p_U}$ .

Proof. As p is Z-realizable, letting $X=U\cap {\mathcal { H}}^-$ , we can find a Y extending $Z\oplus X$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y={\mathcal {R}}^b_U$ and $\tau ^Z_X=\tau ^Z_Y\circ \pi ^{p_U, b}$ . Let E be the $({\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}_U^b}, {\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}})$ -extender derived from $\tau ^Z_Y$ and $i:Ult({\mathcal {R}}_U, E)\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_n({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ be the factor map given by $i(\pi ^p(f)(a))=\pi _U(f)(\tau ^Z_Y(a))$ . It then follows that $i\circ \pi _E$ is as desired.

Next, we introduce a weak notion of realizability.

Definition 9.4. Suppose $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is an array of length $\eta $ that has the Z-realizability property and p is a Z-validated iteration of $\mathcal {C}_n({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ with last model ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $\pi ^p$ exists and the generators of p are contained in ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}^b}$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is an $\mathsf {nuvs}$ iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ that is above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}^b}$ . We say b is $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ if whenever ${\lambda }\in S$ is such that $({\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {T}}, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})\in V_{\lambda }$ and U is a $(\mu , {\lambda },Z)$ -good hull with $(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, {\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {T}}, b)\in U$ , there is ${\alpha }\leq lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ , some l, and a weak l-embedding $k:{\mathcal {M}}^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}_{b_U}\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ .

Proposition 9.5. Suppose $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is a small array with the Z-realizability property. Set $\eta =lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ . Suppose further that p is a Z-validated iteration of $\mathcal {C}_n({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ with last model ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $\pi ^{p}$ exists and the generators of p are contained in ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}^b}$ . Additionally, suppose that ${\mathcal {T}}$ is an iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}^b}$ such that $p^\frown {\mathcal {T}}$ is Z-validated iteration of ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ . Then for all limit ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {T}})$ , if ${\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ , then $[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {T}}$ is the unique branch c of ${\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ exists and is $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable.

Proof. We first show that $c=_{def}[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {T}}$ is $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable. Towards contradiction, assume not and suppose ${\alpha }$ is least such that ${\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ but $[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {T}}$ is not $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable. Let U be a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $({\mathcal {R}}, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}},p, {\mathcal {T}}, {\alpha })\in U$ . Let ${\mathcal {V}}'=\pi _U^{-1}(\mathcal {C}_n({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }))$ and $k:{\mathcal {R}}_U\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_n({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ be such that $\pi _U{\restriction } {\mathcal {V}}'=k\circ \pi ^{p_U}$ .

We now have a cofinal branch d of ${\mathcal {T}}_U{\restriction } {\alpha }_U$ such that for some ${\beta }\leq \eta $ , there is $m:{\mathcal {M}}^{{\mathcal {T}}_U{\restriction } {\alpha }_U}_d\rightarrow {\mathcal {V}}_{\beta }$ and ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U{\restriction } {\alpha }_U)$ exists.Footnote 95 Let ${\mathcal {M}}={\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U{\restriction } {\alpha }_U)$ and ${\mathcal {N}}={\mathcal {Q}}(c_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U{\restriction } {\alpha }_U)$ . Both ${\mathcal {M}}$ and ${\mathcal {N}}$ are Z-approved. Let ${\mathcal {S}}_0={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}_U{\restriction } {\alpha }_U)$ . If we could conclude that ${\mathcal {M}}={\mathcal {N}}$ , then we would get that $c_U=d$ , and that would finish the proof. To conclude that ${\mathcal {M}}={\mathcal {N}}$ , we need to argue that ${\mathcal {S}}_0$ is not infinitely descending.Footnote 96 The reader may wish to review Definition 7.13 and the discussion after Proposition 7.14.Footnote 97

Claim. Suppose ${\mathcal {S}}_0$ is infinitely descending. Then there is a sequence $(p_i, {\mathcal {S}}_i: i<\omega )$ witnessing that ${\mathcal {S}}_0$ is infinitely descending such that for some ${\beta }'<\eta $ and for some $i_0<\omega $ for every $i<j\in (i_0, \omega )$ , there are weak $n_i$ -embeddings $m_i:{\mathcal {S}}_i\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_{n_i}({\mathcal {V}}_{{\beta }'})$ such that $m_i=m_j\circ \pi ^{p_i}$ .

Proof. Set $m_0=m$ , ${\mathcal {S}}_0={\mathcal {S}}$ and ${\beta }_0=\beta $ . We build the sequence by induction. As the successive steps of the induction are the same as the first step, we only do the first step. Let $(p_i', {\mathcal {S}}_i': i<\omega )$ be any sequence witnessing that ${\mathcal {S}}_0$ is infinitely descending. We now have two cases. Suppose first that there is ${\beta }_1\leq {\beta }_0$ and a weak k-embedding $m_1:{\mathcal {S}}_1'\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_k({\mathcal {V}}_{{\beta }_1})$ such that if ${\beta }_1={\beta }_0$ , then $m_0=m_1\circ \pi ^{p_0'}$ . In this case, set $p_0=p_0'$ and ${\mathcal {S}}_1={\mathcal {S}}_1'$ . Notice that ${\mathcal {S}}_1$ is infinitely descending. Suppose next that there is no such pair $({\beta }_1, m_1)$ . In this case, we have $d_1, {\beta }_1, m_1, n_1$ such that

  1. 1. ${\beta }_1\leq {\beta }_0$ ,

  2. 2. $d_1$ is a maximal branch of $p_1'{\restriction } \epsilon $ for some $\epsilon <lh(p_1')$ ,

  3. 3. $m_1:{\mathcal {M}}^{p_1'{\restriction } \epsilon }_{d_1}\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_{n_1}({\mathcal {V}}_{{\beta }_1})$ ,

  4. 4. if ${\beta }_1={\beta }_0$ , then $m_0=m_1\circ \pi ^{p_1'{\restriction } \epsilon }_{d_1}$ .

In this case, set $p_1=p_1'{\restriction } \epsilon ^\frown \{d_1\}$ and ${\mathcal {S}}_1={\mathcal {M}}^{p_1'{\restriction } \epsilon }_{d_1}$ , with ${\beta }_1$ and $m_1$ as above. We now claim that ${\mathcal {S}}_1$ is still infinitely descending. To see this, let $c=[0, \epsilon )_{p^{\prime }_1}$ . Notice that we must have that ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, p^{\prime }_1{\restriction } \epsilon )\not ={\mathcal {Q}}(d_1, p^{\prime }_1{\restriction } \epsilon )$ . As both are Z-approved, we must have that ${\mathcal {S}}_1$ is infinitely descending. Continuing in this manner, we get the sequence we desire.

The existence of a sequence as in the claim above gives us a contradiction, as the sequence must have a well-founded branch. The uniqueness proof is similar to the proof of the claim above, and we leave it to our reader.

Remark 9.6. If the iteration p in Propositions 9.3 and 9.5 drops, we can still embed ${\mathcal {R}}_U$ by some map $k: {\mathcal {R}}_U \rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ for some $\alpha < \epsilon $ and some $l<\omega $ . In this case, there is some model ${\mathcal {M}}\in p$ such that $\pi ^{p_U}_{{\mathcal {M}}_U,{\mathcal {R}}_U}$ exists and there is a weak l-embedding $\sigma : {\mathcal {M}}_U\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ such that $\sigma = k\circ \pi ^{p_U}_{{\mathcal {M}}_U,{\mathcal {R}}_U}$ .

Remark 9.7. The fact that ${\mathcal {V}}$ is small is key to the proof of Proposition 9.5. See Proposition 10.6, which partially deals with the situation when ${\mathcal {V}}$ is not small.

Motivated by Proposition 9.5, we make the following definitions.

Definition 9.8. We say ${\mathcal {R}}$ is weakly Z -suitable above $\mu $ if ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a hod premouse of lsa type such that ${\mathcal {R}}=({\mathcal {R}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}})^{\#}$ and whenever ${\lambda }\in S$ is such that ${\mathcal {R}}\in V_{\lambda }$ and U is a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull, ${\mathcal {R}}_U$ is weakly Z-suitable.Footnote 98

Definition 9.9. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is weakly Z-suitable above $\mu $ . We say ${\mathcal {R}}$ is honest if there is an array $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}=({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha }:{\alpha }\leq \eta )$ at $\mu $ with the Z-realizability property such that letting ${\lambda }\in S$ be the least such that ${\mathcal {R}}, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}}\in V_{\lambda }$ , the following conditions hold.

  1. 1. Either ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }={\mathcal {R}}$ or there is a Z-validated iteration p of ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ of limit length such that $\pi ^{p, b}$ exists and ${\mathcal {R}}={\mathrm m}^+(p)$ .

  2. 2. $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is small if and only if ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta } \not ={\mathcal {R}}$ .

If ${\mathcal {R}}$ is honest and $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is as above, then we say that $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is an honesty certificate for ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is honest as witnessed by $(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, p)$ . Then we say ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a Z-validated iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ if $p^\frown {\mathcal {T}}$ is a Z-validated iteration of ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ where $\eta +1=lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ .

Proposition 9.10. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is weakly Z-suitable above $\mu $ and $(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, p)$ is an honesty witness, and suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a Z-validated $\mathsf {nuvs}$ iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ with last model ${\mathcal {S}}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}}$ exists and the generators of ${\mathcal {T}}$ are contained in ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {S}}^b}$ . Suppose U is a good hull such that $({\mathcal {R}}, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, p, {\mathcal {T}}, {\mathcal {S}})\in U$ . There is then ${\alpha }\leq lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ , a Z-approved sts mouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ over ${\mathcal {R}}_U$ , an embedding $k:{\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow \mathcal {C}({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ and an embedding $\sigma :{\mathcal {S}}_U\rightarrow \mathcal {C}({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ is a Woodin cardinal’,

  2. 2. $k{\restriction } {\mathcal {R}}_U=\sigma \circ \pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}$ ,

  3. 3. ${\mathcal {M}}\not ={\mathcal {R}}_U$ if and only if ${\mathcal {R}}\not =\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {V}}_{\eta })$ (so $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is small), and

  4. 4. if ${\mathcal {M}}\not ={\mathcal {R}}_U$ , then $rud({\mathcal {M}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

Proof. First, we claim that there is ${\alpha }\leq lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ , an $l<\omega $ , and a weak l-embedding $k:{\mathcal {R}}_U\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ such that $Z\subseteq rng(k)$ . If ${\mathcal {R}}={\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ , then set ${\alpha }=\eta $ and $k=\pi _U{\restriction } {\mathcal {R}}_U$ .

Suppose then ${\mathcal {R}}\not ={\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ . In this case, $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is small. Let ${\mathcal {W}}$ be the largest node on p such that $\pi ^{p_{\leq {\mathcal {W}}}}$ exists and the generators of $p_{\leq {\mathcal {W}}}$ are contained in ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ . Then $p_{\geq {\mathcal {W}}}$ is above ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ . It follows from Proposition 9.5 and the remark after that $p_{\geq {\mathcal {W}}}$ is according to $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable branches, and therefore, we must have ${\alpha }\leq lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ and a cofinal branch c of $p_U$ such that there is an appropriate weak l-embedding $k:{\mathcal {M}}^{p_U}_c\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ Footnote 99 such that $Z\subseteq rng(k)$ . Set then ${\mathcal {M}}={\mathcal {M}}^{p_U}_c$ ; note that ${\mathcal {R}}_U \lhd {\mathcal {M}}$ and $rud({\mathcal {M}}) \vDash \text {`}\delta ^{\mathcal {R}}$ is not Woodin’ by smallness of $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ .

We continue with one such pair $({\alpha }, k)$ . Next, as ${\mathcal {T}}$ is Z-validated, we must have Y an extension of Z such that $X=_{def}k[{\mathcal {R}}_U^b]\subseteq Z\oplus Y$ , ${\mathcal {S}}_U^b={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ and $\tau ^Z_X=\tau ^Z_Y\circ \pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_U, b}$ . We can then lift $\tau ^Z_Y$ to ${\mathcal {S}}$ and obtain some weak l-embedding $\sigma :{\mathcal {S}}_U\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\alpha })$ such that $k=\sigma \circ \pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}$ . $\sigma $ is essentially the ultrapower map by the $({\delta }^{{\mathcal {S}}_U^b}, {\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}})$ -extender derived from $\tau ^Z_Y$ (see the proof of Proposition 9.3).

Finally, we discuss iterations that are above ${\mathcal {S}}^b$ where ${\mathcal {S}}$ is as in Proposition 9.10. The proof is just like the proof of Proposition 9.5.

Proposition 9.11. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is honest weakly Z-suitable above $\mu $ hod premouse and $(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, p)$ is an honesty witness for ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a normal Z-validated iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Let ${\alpha }'\in R^{\mathcal {T}}$ be the largest such that setting ${\mathcal {S}}={\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{\mathcal {T}}$ , $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_{\leq {\mathcal {S}}}}$ exists and the generators of ${\mathcal {T}}_{\leq {\mathcal {S}}}$ are contained in ${\mathcal {S}}^b$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}}$ is above $Ord\cap {\mathcal {S}}^b$ . Let U be a good hull such that $\{{\mathcal {R}},\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, {\mathcal {T}}\}\in U$ and let $({\alpha }, {\mathcal {M}}, k, \sigma )$ be as in Proposition 9.10. Then ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}}$ is $(\sigma , \vec {{\mathcal {V}}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ -realizable. Moreover, for each limit ordinal ${\beta }<lh({\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}})$ , if ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}}{\restriction } {\beta }$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ , then $d=_{def}[0, {\beta }]_{{\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}}}$ is the unqiue cofinal branch $d'$ of ${\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}}{\restriction } {\beta }$ which is $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable and ${\mathcal {Q}}(d', {\mathcal {T}}_{\geq {\mathcal {S}}}{\restriction } {\beta })$ exists.

Definition 9.12. We say ${\mathcal {R}}$ is Z -suitable above $\mu $ if it is weakly Z-suitable above $\mu $ and whenever ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ , ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

Our goal is to construct an ${\mathcal {R}}$ which is Z -suitable above $\mu $ . We do this in Proposition 10.7.

10. Z-validated sts constructions

We assume that the theory T holds (see Definition 5.11). We then fix $(S, S_0, \nu _0,\vec {Y}, \vec {A})$ that witness T and let $\mu \in S_0$ . We will omit $\mu $ when discussing CMI objects at $\mu $ .

The construction that we will perform in the next section will hand us a hod premouse ${\mathcal {R}}$ that is weakly Z-suitable above $\mu $ . The rest of the construction that we will perform will be a fully backgrounded construction over ${\mathcal {R}}$ whose aim is to either find a Z-validated sts mouse destroying the Woodiness of ${\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ or proving that no such structures exist. In the latter case, we will show that we must produce an excellent hybrid premouse.

The construction that we describe in this section is a construction that is searching for the Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ destroying the Woodiness of ${\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ . In this construction, we add two kinds of objects. The first type of objects are extenders, and they are handled exactly the same way that they are handled in all fully backgrounded constructions. The second kind of objects are iterations. Here, the difference with the ordinary is that there is no strategy that we follow as we index branches of iterations that appear in the construction. Instead, when our sts scheme demands that a branch of some iteration p must be indexed, we find an appropriate branch and index it. We will make sure that the iterations that we need to consider in the construction are all Z-validated. It must then be proved that given a Z-validated iteration, there is always a branch that is Z-validated.

The solution here has a somewhat magical component to it. As we said above, the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction is not a construction relative to a strategy. This is an important point that will be useful to keep in mind. Instead, the construction follows the sts scheme, and the Z-validation method is used to find branches of iterations that come up in the construction. To see that we do not run into trouble, we need to show that any such iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ that needs to be indexed according to our sts scheme has a branch b such that ${\mathcal {T}}^\frown \{b\}$ is Z-validated. Let ${\mathcal {M}}$ be the stage of the construction where ${\mathcal {T}}$ is produced. Recall now that we have two types of such iterations. If ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ , then Z-validation will produce a branch in a more or less straightforward fashion (see Proposition 10.5). If ${\mathcal {T}}$ is $\mathsf {nuvs}$ , then the fact that we need to index a branch of it suggests that we have also reached an authenticated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {T}}$ . We will then show that there must be a branch with this ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure. This is the magical component we speak of above. In general, given an iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ of a weakly Z-suitable ${\mathcal {R}}$ that is produced by $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ of the next section, there is no reason to believe that there is a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for it of any kind. Even if there is a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure ${\mathcal {Q}}$ of some kind, there is no reason to believe that sufficiently closed hulls of ${\mathcal {T}}$ will have branches determined by the pre-image of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ . In our case, what helps is that ${\mathcal {Q}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ , and this condition, in the authors’ opinion, is somewhat magical.Footnote 100

One particularly unpleasant problem is that we cannot in general prove that the non-weakly Z-suitable levels of the fully backgrounded construction produced in the next sections are iterable. This unpleasantness causes us to work with weakly Z-suitable ${\mathcal {R}}$ that are iterates of a level of the fully backgrounded construction of the next section. In order to have an abstract exposition of the Z-validated sts construction, we introduce the concept of honest weakly Z-suitable ${\mathcal {R}}$ over which we will perform our Z-validated sts constructions. The honest weakly Z-suitable hod premice will have honesty witnesses, and that is the concept we introduce first. The honesty witnesses are essentially models of a $K^c$ -construction.

In this section and subsequent sections, we work with the fine structure in [Reference Steel53].

10.1. The Z-validated sts construction

Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is honest and $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is an honesty certificate for ${\mathcal {R}}$ . We assume that ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a $\#$ -lsa type hod premouse. Let X be any transitive set such that ${\mathcal {R}}\in X$ . Let ${\lambda } \in S_0$ be such that ${\mathcal {R}}, X\in H_{\lambda }$ . In what follows, we introduce the fully backgrounded $(Z, {\lambda })$ -validated sts construction over X.

Definition 10.1. We say $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi \leq \Omega ^*)$ are the models of the fully backgrounded $(Z, {\lambda })$ -validated sts construction over X if the following conditions hold:

  1. 1. $\Omega ^*\leq {\lambda }$ , for all $\xi <{\lambda }$ , if ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }$ are defined, then ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ and ${\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }\in H_{\lambda }$ .

  2. 2. For every $\xi \leq \Omega ^*$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ and ${\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }$ are Z-validated sts hod premice over X.

  3. 3. Suppose the sequence $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi <\eta )$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ have been constructed. Suppose further that there is a total $({\kappa }, \nu )$ -extender F such that letting $G={\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }\cap F$ , $({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, G)$ is a Z-validated sts hod premouse over X. Let then ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }=({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, G)$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta +1}=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {N}}_{\eta })$ .Footnote 101

  4. 4. Suppose the sequence $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi <\eta )$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ have been constructed and ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ is the $<_{{\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }}$ -least $\mathsf {uvs}$ treeFootnote 102 without an indexed branch. Suppose further that there is a branch b of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that $({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, b)$ is a Z-validated sts hod premouseFootnote 103 over ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Let then ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }=({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, b)$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta +1}=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {N}}_{\eta })$ .

  5. 5. Suppose the sequence $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi <\eta )$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ has been constructed, and for some $\mathsf {nuvs}$ tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ there is a branch $b\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ such that $({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, b)$ is a Z-validated sts hod premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Let ${\mathcal {T}}$ be the $<_{{\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }}$ -least such tree and b be such a branch for ${\mathcal {T}}$ . Then ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }=({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, b)$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta +1}=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {N}}_{\eta })$ .Footnote 104

  6. 6. Suppose the sequence $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi <\eta )$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ has been constructed and all of the above cases fail. In this case, we let ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }=\mathcal {J}_1({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta })$ , provided ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }$ is a Z-validated sts hod premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta +1}=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {N}}_{\eta })$ .

  7. 7. Suppose the sequence $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi <\eta )$ has been constructed and $\eta $ is a limit ordinal. Then ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }=liminf_{\xi \rightarrow \eta }{\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ .

If $\lambda $ is clear from context, then we will omit it from our notation.

The fully backgrounded (f.b.) Z-validated sts construction can break down for several reasons. Let p be the ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ -to- ${\mathcal {R}}$ iteration witnessing that ${\mathcal {R}}$ is honest. Below, we list all of these reasons. We say that f.b. Z-validated sts construction breaks down at $\eta $ if one of the following conditions holds.

Break1. ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ is not solid or universal.

Break2. ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ is not Z-validated.Footnote 105

Break3. There is an $\mathsf {uvs}$ tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ such that the indexing scheme demands that a branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ must be indexed, yet ${\mathcal {T}}$ has no (cofinal well-founded) branch b such that $({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, b)$ is a Z-validated sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

Break4. There is an $\mathsf {nuvs}$ tree ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ such that the indexing scheme demands that a branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ must be indexed, yet letting $b\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ be the branch given by the authentication process, b is not $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable branch of ${\mathcal {T}}^\frown p$ .Footnote 106

Break5. $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta })\leq {\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ .

The argument that the construction does not break down because of Break1 is standard, cf. [Reference Mitchell and Steel28]. It is essentially enough to show that the countable substructures of ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ are iterable. We will show that much more complicated forms of iterability hold, and so to save ink and to not repeat ourselves, we will leave this portion to our kind reader. To see that the construction does not break down because of Break2 is not too involved, and we will present that argument below. At this point, we cannot do much about Break5. We will deal with it when X becomes a more meaningful object. The remaining cases will be handled in the next subsections.

Proposition 10.2. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is an honest weakly Z-suitable hod premouse as witnessed by $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ , X is a transitive set such that ${\mathcal {R}}\in X$ and ${\lambda }\in S_0$ is such that $X, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}}\in V_{\lambda }$ . Then the f.b. $(Z, {\lambda })$ -validated construction over X does not break down because of Break2.

Proof. Towards contradiction, assume that there is some ${\alpha }$ such that for all ${\beta }<{\alpha }$ , both ${\mathcal {M}}_{\beta }$ and ${\mathcal {N}}_{\beta }$ are Z-validated but ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }$ is not Z-validated. Set ${\mathcal {W}}={\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }$ be the least such model.

Suppose first ${\alpha }$ is a limit ordinal. Let U be a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $ \{{\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {W}}\}\subseteq U$ and $({\mathcal {M}}_{\beta }:{\beta }\leq {\alpha })\in U$ . Let $({\mathcal { K}}_{\xi }: \xi \leq {\alpha }_U)=\pi ^{-1}_U({\mathcal {M}}_{\beta }:{\beta }\leq {\alpha })$ . Fix ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal { K}}_{{\alpha }_U}$ according to $S^{{\mathcal { K}}_{{\alpha }_U}}$ . We need to see that ${\mathcal {T}}$ is Z-approved. Fix $\xi <{\alpha }_U$ such that ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal { K}}_{\xi }$ and is according to $S^{{\mathcal { K}}_{\xi }}$ . Then $\pi _U({\mathcal {T}})\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\pi _U(\xi )}$ and is according to $S^{{\mathcal {M}}_{\pi _U(\xi )}}$ . Therefore, ${\mathcal {T}}$ is Z-approved.

Suppose next that ${\alpha }={\beta }+1$ . Because we are assuming the least model that is not Z-validated is ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }$ , we must have that ${\mathcal {N}}_{\beta }$ is Z-validated. Let now U be a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $\{{\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {W}}\}\subseteq U$ . But then $\pi _U^{-1}({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha })=\mathcal {C}(\pi ^{-1}_U({\mathcal {N}}_{\beta }))$ . It then follows that $\pi _U^{-1}({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha })$ is Z-approved (see Proposition 7.9).

10.2. Break3 never happens

In this subsection, ${\mathcal {R}}$ is an honest weakly Z-suitable, X is a transitive set containing ${\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\lambda }\in S_0$ is such that $({\mathcal {R}}, X)\in V_{\lambda }$ . Our main goal here is to prove that the $(Z, {\lambda })$ -validated sts construction over X does not break down because of Break3. First, we prove the following general lemma.

Lemma 10.3. Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a hod premouse for which ${\mathcal {M}}^b$ is defined and p is an iteration of ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that $\pi ^{p, b}$ exists. Let ${\delta }$ be a Woodin cardinal of $\pi ^{p, b}({\mathcal {M}}^b)$ and let $\xi $ be least such that $\pi ^{p, b}(\xi )\geq {\delta }$ . Then ${\mathrm cf}({\delta })={\mathrm cf}((\xi ^+)^{\mathcal {M}})$ .

Proof. Let ${\mathcal {Q}}$ be the least model of p such that ${\mathcal {Q}}^b=\pi ^{p, b}({\mathcal {M}}^b)$ and set $q=p_{\leq {\mathcal {Q}}}$ . Let ${\mathcal {N}}$ be the least model on q such that ${\delta }\in rng(\pi ^q_{{\mathcal {N}}, {\mathcal {Q}}})$ . Without losing generality, we can assume ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {N}}$ as $rng(\pi ^q_{{\mathcal {N}}, {\mathcal {Q}}})\cap {\delta }$ is cofinal in ${\delta }$ . As the iteration embeddings are cofinal at Woodin cardinals, if $\pi ^q(\xi )={\delta }$ , then again there is nothing to prove. Assume then $\pi ^q(\xi )>{\delta }$ . Without loss of generality, we can assume that $\xi ={\delta }^{{\mathcal {M}}^b}$ . If $\xi <{\delta }^{{\mathcal {M}}^b}$ , then we need to redefine ${\mathcal {M}}$ as ${\mathcal {M}}|\zeta $ , where $\zeta $ is the ${\mathcal {M}}$ -successor of $o^{\mathcal {M}}(\xi )$ .

Because ${\mathcal {N}}$ is the least model that has ${\delta }$ in it, it must be case that ${\mathcal {N}}=Ult({\mathcal {W}}, E)$ , where ${\mathcal {W}}$ is a node in q and E is an extender used in q to obtain ${\mathcal {N}}$ . Moreover, $\mathrm {crit }(E)={\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ . Below, $\pi _E$ is used for $\pi _E^{\mathcal {W}}$ .

Suppose $\pi _E(f)(a)=\delta $ and $\pi _E(g)(a)= \nu _E$ , where

  1. 1. $\nu _E$ is the supremum of the generators of E,

  2. 2. $f,g: {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b} \rightarrow {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ are functions in ${\mathcal {W}}$ ,

  3. 3. $a \in [\nu _E+1]^{<\omega }$ .

Note that $\nu _E < \delta $ .

We first show that

(1) $\sup (\{ \pi _E(k)(a): k:{\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}\rightarrow {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}, k\in {\mathcal {W}}\}\cap {\delta })={\delta }$ .

To see (1), fix $h:{\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b} \rightarrow {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ in ${\mathcal {W}}$ and let s in $[\nu _E+1]^{<\omega }$ be such that $\pi _E(h)(s) < \delta $ . We want to find k such that $\pi _E(k)(a)$ is in $[\pi _E(h)(s), \delta ]$ . Set $k(u)=$ the supremum of points of the form $h(t)$ such that $h(t)< f(u)$ and t is a finite sequence from $g(u)$ . $f(u)$ is a Woodin cardinal (in ${\mathcal {R}}$ ), so $k(u)< f(u)$ for $E_a$ -almost all u, so

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_E(k)(a) < \delta = \pi_E(f)(a).\end{align*} $$

Also,

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_E(h)(s)\leq \pi_E(k)(a) \end{align*} $$

by the definition of k.

Let ${\lambda }=Ord\cap {\mathcal {W}}^b$ . We have that ${\mathrm cf}({\lambda })={\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}}^b)$ . Thus, it is enough to show that ${\mathrm cf}({\delta })={\mathrm cf}({\lambda })$ . Let $\eta ={\mathrm cf}({\delta })$ and let $(k_{\alpha }: {\alpha }<\eta )\subseteq {\mathcal {W}}$ be such that

  1. 1. for ${\alpha }<\eta $ , $k_{\alpha }:{\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b} \rightarrow {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ ,

  2. 2. for ${\alpha }<\eta $ , $k_{\alpha }\in {\mathcal {W}}$ ,

  3. 3. for ${\alpha }<{\beta }<\eta $ , $\pi _E(k_{\alpha })(a)<\pi _E(k_{\beta })(a)<{\delta }$ .

Let $\vec {{\gamma }}=({\gamma }_{\alpha }:{\alpha }<\eta )$ be increasing and such that

  1. 1. $k_{\alpha }\in {\mathcal {W}}|{\gamma }_{\alpha }$ ,

  2. 2. $\rho ({\mathcal {W}}|{\gamma }_{\alpha })={\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ .

We claim that $\vec {{\gamma }}$ is cofinal in ${\lambda }$ . Suppose it is not. In that case, we can fix $\zeta>\sup \vec {{\gamma }}$ such that $\rho _1({\mathcal {W}}|\zeta )={\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}$ . Let p be the first standard parameter of ${\mathcal {W}}|\zeta $ . For each ${\alpha }<\eta $ , let $a_{\alpha }\in [{\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b}]^{<\omega }$ be such that $k_{\alpha }$ is definable from p and $a_{\alpha }$ in ${\mathcal {W}}|\zeta $ . It then follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \sup(Hull_1^{\pi_E({\mathcal{W}}|\zeta)}(\pi_E(p), {\delta}^{{\mathcal{W}}^b})\cap {\delta})={\delta}, \end{align*} $$

as witnessed by $(a_{\alpha }: {\alpha }<\eta )$ . As $Hull_1^{\pi _E({\mathcal {W}}|\zeta )}(\pi _E(p), {\delta }^{{\mathcal {W}}^b})\in Ult({\mathcal {W}}, E)={\mathcal {N}}$ , the above equality implies that ${\delta }$ is singular in ${\mathcal {N}}$ ; a contradiction. Thus, $\vec {{\gamma }}$ must be cofinal in ${\lambda }$ . Therefore, ${\mathrm cf}({\lambda })=\eta $ .

Recall that we are working under theory T; see Definition 5.11.

Corollary 10.4. Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a normal tree on ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}$ exists and $\delta $ is a Woodin cardinal of $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}({\mathcal { H}})$ . Then ${\mathrm cf}(\delta ) < \mu $ and if ${\delta }>\sup (\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}[{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}])$ , then ${\mathrm cf}({\delta })<\nu _0$ .

Proof. First note that if $\delta $ is a Woodin cardinal of $\mathcal {H}$ , then ${\mathrm cf}(\delta ) < \mu $ . This is because there is a hod pair $({\mathcal {P}},\Sigma )\in \mathcal {F}$ , a $\delta ^*$ such that ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \delta ^*$ is Woodin and $\delta = \pi _{{\mathcal {P}},\infty }(\delta ^*)$ . Now, if ${\delta }>\sup (\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}, b}[{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}])$ , then by Lemma 10.3, ${\mathrm cf}({\delta })={\mathrm cf}(Ord\cap {\mathcal { H}})<\nu _0$ .

We now state and prove our main proposition of this subsection.

Proposition 10.5. The $(Z, {\lambda })$ -validated sts construction over X does not break down because of Break3.

Proof. [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Section 12] handles a similar situation, and the proof here is very much like the proofs in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Section 12]. Because of this, we give an outline of the proof.

Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a model appearing in the $(Z, {\lambda })$ -validated sts construction over X and ${\mathcal {T}}^*\in {\mathcal {M}}$ is an $\mathsf {uvs}$ iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}$ such that the indexing scheme requires that we index a branch of ${\mathcal {T}}^*$ at $Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}}$ . We need to show that there is a branch b of ${\mathcal {T}}^*$ such that $({\mathcal {M}}, b)$ is Z-validated. Because of Proposition 8.6 and Proposition 9.11, there can be at most one such branch.

Because ${\mathcal {T}}^*$ is $\mathsf {uvs}$ , we have a normal iteration ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {M}}$ with last model ${\mathcal {S}}$ such that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}}$ is defined and a normal iteration ${\mathcal {U}}$ based on ${\mathcal {S}}^b$ such that ${\mathcal {T}}^\frown {\mathcal {U}}={\mathcal {T}}^*$ . Because the construction does not break because of Break2 (see Proposition 10.2), we have that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is Z-validated, and therefore, ${\mathcal {T}}$ is Z-validated. Also, we can assume that ${\mathcal {U}}$ is not based on ${\mathcal {S}}|\xi $ where $\xi =\sup (\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}[{\delta }^{\mathcal { H}}])$ , as otherwise the desired branch of ${\mathcal {U}}$ is given by $\Psi $ .

We now show that ${\mathcal {U}}$ has a branch b such that $({\mathcal {M}}, b)$ is Z-validated. Let ${\lambda }\in S$ be least such that ${\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {M}}\in H_{\lambda }$ . Given a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull U such that $\{{\mathcal {M}}, {\mathcal {T}}, {\mathcal {S}}, {\mathcal {U}}\}\subseteq U$ , let $b_U=\Psi ^Z_W(\pi ^{-1}_U({\mathcal {U}}))$ , where W is any extension of Z such that $\pi ^{-1}_U({\mathcal {S}}^b)={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_W$ . First, we claim that for all U as above,

Claim 1. $b_U\in M_U$ .

Proof. Given a U as above, we will use it as a subscript to denote the $\pi _U$ -preimages of the relevant objects. Fix then a U as above. Suppose first that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {U}}_U)$ does not exist. As we are assuming ${\mathcal {U}}$ is not based on ${\mathcal {S}}|\xi $ , Corollary 10.4 implies that ${\mathrm cf}({\delta }({\mathcal {U}}))\leq \nu _0$ . Because $M_U$ is $\nu _0$ -closed, it follows that $b_U\in M_U$ .

Suppose next that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {U}}_U)$ exists. Let $A_U$ be the preimage of $A_{\lambda }$ . Notice now that letting $\Phi $ be the $\pi _U$ -pullback of $\Psi _{\lambda }$ , we have that $Lp^{cuB, \Phi }(A_U)\in M_U$ .

Let $Y=U\cap {\mathcal { H}}$ . Clearly, Y is an extension of Z and because ${\mathcal {M}}$ is Z-validated, we must have $W^*$ an extension of $Z\cup Y$ such that ${\mathcal {S}}_U^b={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{W^*}$ . Notice that because $\Psi ^Z_{W^*}$ is computable from $\Phi $ and because $Lp^{cuB, \Phi }(A_U)\in M_U$ , we must have that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {U}}_U)\in M_U$ . Hence, $b_U\in M_U$ .

Suppose first that ${\mathrm cf}(lh({\mathcal {U}}))>\omega $ . In this case, let ${\mathcal {U}}$ be as above and set $c=\pi _U(b_U)$ . Then c is the unique well-founded branch of ${\mathcal {U}}$ , and hence, for any $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull $X'$ such that $U\cup \{({\mathcal {M}}, c), U\}\in X'$ , $c_{X'}=b_{X'}$ . Hence, $({\mathcal {M}}, c)$ is Z-validated (see Proposition 8.3).

Suppose then $lh({\mathcal {U}})=\omega $ . We now claim that

Claim. there is a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hullFootnote 107 $X_0$ such that for all $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hulls Y such that $X_0\cup \{{\mathcal {M}}, X_0\}\in Y$ , $\pi _{X_0, Y}(b_{X'})=b_Y$ .

Proof. Assuming not, we get a continuous chain $(X_{\alpha }: {\alpha }<\mu )$ such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {M}}, {\mathcal {U}}\in X_0$ ,

  2. 2. for all ${\alpha }<\mu $ , $X_{{\alpha }+1}$ is a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull,

  3. 3. for all ${\alpha }<\mu $ , $X_{{\alpha }}\cup \{X_{{\alpha }}\}\in X_{{\alpha }+1}$ ,

  4. 4. for all ${\alpha }<\mu $ , $\pi _{X_{{\alpha }+1}, X_{{\alpha }+2}}(b_{X_{{\alpha }+1}})\not =b_{X_{{\alpha }+1}}$ .

Let $\nu \in (\nu _0, \mu )$ be an inaccessible cardinal such that $X_{\nu }\cap \mu =\nu $ . Fix now ${\alpha }<\nu $ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \sup(b_{X_{\nu}}\cap rng(\pi_{X_{\alpha}, X_{\nu}}))=lh({\mathcal{U}}_{X_{\nu}}). \end{align*} $$

As ${\mathrm cf}(lh({\mathcal {U}}_{X_{\nu }}))=\omega $ , this is easy to achieve. For ${\beta }\in [{\alpha }, \nu )$ , let $c_{\beta }$ be the $\pi _{X_{\alpha }, X_{\nu }}$ -pullback of $b_{X_{\nu }}$ . Let for ${\beta }\in [{\alpha }, \nu ]$ , $W_{\beta }$ be such that ${\mathcal {S}}^b_{X_{\beta }}={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{W_{\beta }}$ . It follows that $c_{\beta }$ is according to the $\pi _{X_{\beta }, X_{\nu }}$ -pullback of $\Psi ^Z_{W_{\nu }}$ . Because $\Psi ^Z_{W_{\beta }}$ depends only on ${\mathcal {S}}^b_{X_{\beta }}$ , we have that $c_{\beta }=b_{X_{\beta }}$ (this is because the $\pi _{X_{\beta }, X_{\nu }}$ -pullback of $\Psi ^Z_{W_{\nu }}$ is a strategy of the form $\Psi ^Z_Y$ , where ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y={\mathcal {S}}^b_{X_{\beta }}$ ). It follows that for all ${\beta }<{\gamma }\in [{\alpha }, \nu )$ , $\pi _{X_{\beta }, X_{\gamma }}(b_{X_{\beta }})=b_{X_{\gamma }}$ .

Fix now an $X_0$ as in the Claim. Set $c=\pi _{X_0}(b_{X_0})$ . The above property of $X_0$ guarantees that $({\mathcal {M}}, c)$ is Z-validated. Indeed, fix a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull U such that ${\mathcal {M}}, c\in U$ . Let Y be a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $X_0\cup U \cup \{X_0, U\}\in Y$ . Then $\pi _{U, Y}(c_U)=\pi _{X_0, Y}(b_{X_0})=b_Y$ . It follows that $c_U$ is the $\pi _{U, Y}$ -pullback of $\Psi ^Z_W$ , where W is such that ${\mathcal {S}}^b_Y={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_W$ . Hence, $c_U=b_U$ .

10.3. Break4 never happens

The following is the main proposition of this subsection. We continue with $({\mathcal {R}}, X, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, {\lambda })$ of the previous section.

Proposition 10.6. Suppose the $(Z, {\lambda })$ -validated sts construction over X breaks because of Break4 and that X is a transitive set such that $H_{{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}}^X$ is the universe of ${\mathcal {R}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ is a Woodin cardinal in X. Then

  1. 1. $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is not small (implying ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }={\mathcal {R}}$ ) and

  2. 2. letting $\eta '$ be such that Break4 occurs at $\eta '$ and letting $({\mathcal {T}}, b)\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta '}$ witness Break4 at $\eta '$ , either ${\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ is not a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta '}$ or $H_{{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}}^{{\mathcal {M}}_{\eta '}}$ is not the universe of ${\mathcal {R}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ .

Proof. Let p be the ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta '}$ -to- ${\mathcal {R}}$ iteration. Setting ${\mathcal {W}}={\mathcal {M}}_{\eta '}$ , we have that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {W}}$ is Z-validated and

  2. 2. b is not $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable (see Definition 9.4).

Let ${\beta }$ be such that ${\mathcal {W}}|{\beta }$ authenticates b. Thus, ${\mathcal {W}}|{\beta }$ is a model of $\mathsf {ZFC}$ in which there is a limit of Woodin cardinals $\nu $ and the derived model of ${\mathcal {W}}|{\beta }$ at $\nu $ has a strategy for ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ that is ${\mathcal {W}}|{\beta }$ -authenticated.

Claim 1. $p^\frown {\mathcal {T}}^\frown \{b\}$ is a Z-validated iteration (see Definition 8.2).

Proof. Towards a contradiction, suppose $p^\frown {\mathcal {T}}^\frown \{b\}$ is not Z-validated. Fix now a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull U such that $({\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {W}}, p, {\mathcal {T}}, b) \in U$ and $p_U^\frown {\mathcal {T}}_U^\frown \{b_U\}$ is not a correctly guided Z-realizable iteration of ${\mathcal {R}}_U$ . Because ${\mathcal {W}}$ is Z-validated, we can assume that $p_U^\frown {\mathcal {T}}_U$ is a correctly guided Z-realizable iteration. It must then be that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ is not Z-approved.

To save ink, let us prove that, in fact, ${\mathcal {N}}=_{def}{\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ is Z-approved of depth 1. As the proof of depth n is the same, we will leave the rest to the reader. To start with, notice that since ${\mathcal {T}}_U$ itself is correctly guided Z-realizable, we have that ${\mathcal {S}}={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}_U)$ is weakly Z-suitable. To prove that ${\mathcal {N}}$ is Z-approved of depth 1, we need to show that if ${\mathcal {U}}\in {\mathcal {N}}$ is according to $S^{{\mathcal {N}}}$ , then ${\mathcal {U}}$ is Z-realizable.

Fix then ${\alpha }\in R^{\mathcal {U}}$ and set ${\mathcal {X}}={\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^{\mathcal {U}}$ . First, let us show that there is $Z'$ an extension of Z such that ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Z'}={\mathcal {X}}^b$ . Because ${\mathcal {T}}_U^\frown \{b_U\}$ is authenticated inside ${\mathcal {W}}_U|{\beta }_U$ , we must have an iteration ${\mathcal {Y}}$ of ${\mathcal {R}}_U$ according to $S^{{\mathcal {W}}_U}$ with last model ${\mathcal {R}}_1$ such that there is an embedding $k:{\mathcal {X}}^b\rightarrow {\mathcal {R}}_1^b$ with the property that $\pi ^{{\mathcal {Y}}, b}=k\circ \pi ^{{\mathcal {U}}_{\leq {\mathcal {X}}}, b}$ . Because ${\mathcal {Y}}$ is Z-realizable, we must have Y an extension of Z such that ${\mathcal {R}}_1^b={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_Y$ . Composing k with $\tau ^Z_Y$ , we have that ${\mathcal {X}}^b={\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{Z'}$ for some $Z'$ .

The rest is similar. If ${\mathcal {U}}^*$ is the longest initial segment of ${\mathcal {U}}_{\geq {\mathcal {X}}}$ that is based on ${\mathcal {X}}^b$ , then there are ${\mathcal {Y}}$ and k as above such that ${\mathcal {U}}^*$ is according to the k-pullback of $S^{{\mathcal {M}}_U}_{{\mathcal {R}}_1^b}$ . But because ${\mathcal {W}}_U$ is Z-approved, $S^{{\mathcal {W}}_U}_{{\mathcal {R}}_1^b}$ is a fragment of $\Psi ^Z_Y$ , where Y is as above. Hence, ${\mathcal {U}}^*$ is according to $\Psi ^Z_X$ for some X (see Corollary 6.8).

Let now U be a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that $({\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {W}}, {\mathcal {T}}, b,{\mathcal {Q}})\in U$ . Because ${\mathcal {T}}$ is Z-validated, we have that the $\pi _U$ -realizable branch d of ${\mathcal {T}}_U$ is cofinal. Suppose then ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ exists. Then because it is Z-approved, we must have that ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)={\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ (for example, see Proposition 9.5). It follows that $d=b_U$ , and so b is $(Z, \vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ -embeddable.

Assume now that clause 1 fails. Because ${\mathcal {V}}$ is not small, we must have that ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ exists (as d is the realizable branch of $p^\frown {\mathcal {T}}_U$ ). Assume now that ${\mathcal {V}}$ is not small. This means that ${\mathcal {R}}={\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ . Assume now that clause 2 fails. Since ${\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ is a regular cardinal of ${\mathcal {W}}$ , $H_{{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}}^{{\mathcal {W}}}$ is the universe of ${\mathcal {R}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\mathcal {R}}={\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ . If ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_{\mathcal {U}})$ does not exist, then the d realizes back into ${\mathcal {W}}$ . We now argue that ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ exists.

Claim 2. ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ exists.

Proof. Towards a contradiction, assume ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ does not exist. Thus, $d\cap D^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}=\emptyset $ and $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}({\delta }^{{\mathcal {R}}_U})={\delta }({\mathcal {T}}_U)$ . Set ${\mathcal {N}}={\mathcal {M}}^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}_d$ and $j=\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}_d$ Footnote 108. Because ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ does not exist, we have that ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}}_U)$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

We have that $j({\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U))\in {\mathcal {N}}$ and is authenticated in ${\mathcal {N}}$ . Let ${\gamma }=j({\beta }_U)$ . Then ${\mathcal {N}}|{\gamma }$ has Woodin cardinals that are bigger than ${\delta }(j({\mathcal {T}}_U))$ . Let ${\delta }$ be the least one that is bigger than $Ord\cap j({\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U))$ . We can now iterate ${\mathcal {N}}$ below ${\delta }$ but above $Ord\cap j({\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U))$ to make ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ generic for the extender algebra at the image of ${\delta }$ . This iteration produces $i:{\mathcal {N}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}_1$ such that $\mathrm {crit }(i)>{\delta }(j({\mathcal {T}}_U))$ . Letting $h\subseteq Coll(\omega , i({\delta }))$ be ${\mathcal {N}}_1$ -generic such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)\in {\mathcal {N}}_1[h]$ , we can find

$$ \begin{align*} l:{\mathcal{Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal{T}}_U)\rightarrow j({\mathcal{Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal{T}}_U))^{109} \end{align*} $$

such that

  • $l\in {\mathcal {N}}_1[h]$ ,

  • $l{\restriction } ({\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}_U))^b=\pi ^{j({\mathcal {T}}_U), b}$ .

As ${\mathcal {N}}_1[h]{\vDash } \text {`}j({\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U))$ is authenticated and has an authenticated strategy’, ${\mathcal {N}}_1[h]{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ has an authenticated iteration strategy’, and hence, ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ is definable in ${\mathcal {N}}_1[h]$ from objects in ${\mathcal {N}}_1$ . It follows that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)\in {\mathcal {N}}_1$ , implying that ${\mathcal {N}}_1{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}}_U)$ is not a Woodin cardinal’. Hence, ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}}_U)$ is not a Woodin cardinal’. Therefore, ${\mathcal {Q}}(d, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ exists.

10.4. A conclusion

Proposition 10.7. Suppose $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is a small array with the Z-realizability property. Then either

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ has a Z-validated iteration strategy

    or

  2. 2. there is a Z-validated $\mathsf {nuvs}$ iteration p of ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ such that ${\mathrm m}^+(p)$ is Z-suitable.Footnote 110

Proof. The proof has already been given in the previous subsections. Suppose that ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ does not have a Z-validated iteration strategy. The proof of Proposition 10.5 shows that if p is a Z-validated $\mathsf {uvs}$ iteration of ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ of limit length, then there is a unique branch b of p such that $p^\frown \{b\}$ is Z-validated. Therefore, since picking Z-validated branches is not defining an iteration strategy for ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ , we must have a $\mathsf {nuvs}$ Z-validated iteration p of ${\mathcal {V}}_{\eta }$ which does not have a Z-validated branch.Footnote 111

We now claim that ${\mathrm m}^+(p)$ is a Z-suitable hod premouse. Indeed, suppose there is some Z-validated sts premouse ${\mathcal {Q}}$ extending ${\mathcal {R}}=_{def}{\mathrm m}^+(p)$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for p. Let then U be a good hull such that $\{\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}, p, {\mathcal {Q}}\}\in U$ . Appealing to Proposition 9.10, we now have ${\beta }\leq lh(\vec {{\mathcal {V}}})$ , a branch b of $p_U$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, p_U)$ exists and a weak l-embedding $k:{\mathcal {M}}_b^{p_U}\rightarrow \mathcal {C}_l({\mathcal {V}}_{\beta })$ for an appropriate l. It follows that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, p_U)$ is Z-approved, and hence, ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, p_U)={\mathcal {Q}}_U$ . Because ${\mathcal {Q}}_U\in M_U$ , we have that $b\in M_U$ . Then $c=_{def}\pi _U(b)$ is a (cofinal) branch of p such that $p^\frown \{c\}$ is Z-validated.

11. Hybrid fully backgrounded constructions

The goal of this section is to adopt the $K^c$ -construction used in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38] to our current situation. As we have the large cardinals in V, it is easier to perform fully backgrounded constructions than using partial background certificates. For instance, proofs of iterability will be easier.

The construction that we intend to perform will produce an almost excellent (see Definition 2.7) hod premouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ extending ${\mathcal { H}}$ . The construction will be done in V.

The fully backgrounded construction that we have in mind has two different backgrounding conditions for extenders. The extenders with critical point $>\Theta =_{def} \delta ^{\mathcal {H}}$ will have total extenders as their background certificates. The extenders with critical point $\Theta $ will be authenticated by good hulls. We call this construction the the hybrid fully backgrounded construction over ${\mathcal { H}}$ and denote it by $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ .

We fix a condensing set $Z\in Cnd({\mathcal { H}})\cap V$ . While Z will appear in our authentication definitions, it can be shown that $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ does not depend on Z. $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ proceeds more or less according to the usual procedure for building hod pairs until we reach a weakly Z-suitable stage ${\mathcal {R}}$ . At this stage, we must continue with a fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction over ${\mathcal {R}}$ . If this construction produces a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {R}}$ , then we attempt to construct a Z-validated strategy for it. Failing to do so will produce our honest Z-suitable ${\mathcal {R}}$ as in Proposition 10.7.

$\mathsf {HFBC}$ can fail in the usual ways by producing a level whose countable substructures are not iterable.Footnote 112 However, our constructions are aimed at producing models with strictly weaker large cardinal structure than those for which we know how to prove iterability. In particular, the main theorem of [Reference Neeman31] implies that $\mathsf {HFBC}$ does not fail because of issues having to do with iterability.

We should say that the construction that follows is an adaptation of a similar construction introduced in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Section 10.2.9 and 12.2]. Because of this we will not dwell too much on how extenders with critical point ${\delta }^{\mathcal {H}}$ are chosen. The reader may consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Lemma 12.3.15]. The first of these constructions used fully backgrounded certificates like we will do in the next subsection. It was used to prove the Mouse Set Conjecture in the minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ . The second was used to construct a model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ from $\mathsf {PFA}$ .

11.1. The levels of $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$

We assume that T holds and let $(S, S_0, \nu _0,\vec {Y}, \vec {A})$ witness it. Let $\mu \in S_0$ . When discussing the CMI objects at $\mu $ , we will omit $\mu $ from our notation.

Below, we will define the sequence $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi },\Sigma _{\xi }: \xi \leq \Omega ')$ , where $\Omega ' \leq Ord$ , of levels of the hybrid fully backgrounded construction at $\mu $ . Here, we develop the terminology that we will use to describe the passage from ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ to ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi +1}$ .

$\mathsf {HFBC}$ resembles the $K^c$ -construction of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Section 12.2] except that we require that the extenders with critical point $>\delta ^{\mathcal { H}}$ used in the construction have total certificates in the sense of [Reference Mitchell and Steel28, Chapter 12]. Because our construction does not reach a Woodin cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals, the results of [Reference Neeman31] apply. For instance, [Reference Neeman31, Theorem 1.1] will be used to conclude that the countable submodels of each ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ are $\omega _1+1$ -iterable. Other theorems that we will use from [Reference Neeman31] are [Reference Neeman31, Theorem 2.1, 2.10, 3.11 and Corollary 3.14].

Say that ${\mathcal {M}}$ nicely extends ${\mathcal { H}}$ if there is a $(\mu , \mu , Z)$ -good hull U such that ${\mathcal {M}}_U$ nicely extends ${\mathcal {Q}}^Z_{U\cap {\mathcal { H}}}$ . Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-validated hod premouse nicely extending ${\mathcal { H}}$ . Set $mo({\mathcal {M}})=o^{\mathcal {M}}({\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}})$ .Footnote 113

Definition 11.1. Given a Z-validated hod premouse nicely extending ${\mathcal { H}}$ , we say ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate if $Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}}=mo({\mathcal {M}})$ and ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash }$ ‘there are no Woodin cardinals in the interval $[{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}, mo({\mathcal {M}}))'$ .

Given an appropriate ${\mathcal {M}}$ , we would like to describe the next appropriate Z-validated hod premouse. We do this by preparing ${\mathcal {M}}$ , which involves building over ${\mathcal {M}}$ some mild structures in order to reach the next stage that is either a stage where we can add an extender or is a weakly Z-suitable stage. In the latter case, we will put $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ on hold and continue with the Z-validated sts construction. The preparation of ${\mathcal {M}}$ has two stages. We first add a sharp to ${\mathcal {M}}$ and then close the resulting hod premouse under its strategy. Each of these constructions can change ${\mathcal {M}}$ as they can reach levels that project across ${\mathcal {M}}$ . The functions that we referred to above are $next_{\#}$ , $next_s$ , $next_{bex}$ and $next_{\Theta -ex}$ .

$next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$

This function simply adds a backgrounded extender to ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Suppose that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate. We say $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is almost successful if there is a triple $({\kappa }, {\lambda }, F)$ such that

  1. 1. ${\kappa }<{\lambda }$ are inaccessible cardinals $>{\delta }^{\mathcal { H}}$ ,

  2. 2. F is a $({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ -extender such that $V_{\lambda }\subseteq Ult(V, F)$ ,

  3. 3. letting $G=F\cap {\mathcal {M}}$ , $({\mathcal {M}}, G)$ is hod premouse.

We say $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful if it is almost successful and there is a unique triple $({\kappa }, {\lambda }, F)$ as above such that if $G=F\cap {\mathcal {M}}$ , $({\mathcal {M}}, G)$ is a solid and universal Z-validated hod premouse with a Z-validated strategy and such that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}, G)>{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ .

Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ has badness type 0 if $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is almost successful but is not successful. We write $bad({\mathcal {M}})=0$ . If $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful or not almost successful, then

  1. 1. if $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful, then letting $({\kappa }, {\lambda }, F)$ be the unique triple witnessing the success of $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ , we let $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})=({\mathcal {M}}, G)$ , where $G=F\cap {\mathcal {M}}$ .

  2. 2. If $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is not almost successful, then we let $next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})={\mathcal {M}}$ .

$next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$

Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate and $bad({\mathcal {M}})\not =0$ . We let $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ be built as follows. Let $({\mathcal {M}}_i: i\leq k)$ be a sequence of Z-validated hod premice defined as follows:

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {M}}_0=next_{bex}({\mathcal {M}})$ .

  2. 2. If $i+1\leq k$ , then there is ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ that is an initial segment of $J[{\mathcal {M}}_i]$ such that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}^*)<mo({\mathcal {M}}_i)$ , and letting ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ be the least such initial segment of $J[{\mathcal {M}}_i]$ , ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ is solid and universal, $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}^*)>{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{i+1}=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {M}}^*)$ .

  3. 3. k is least such that either (i) no level of $J[{\mathcal {M}}_k]$ projects across $mo({\mathcal {M}}_k)$ or (ii) some level of $J[{\mathcal {M}}_k]$ projects to or below ${\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ .

We say $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful if

  1. (a) clause 3(ii) does not happen,

  2. (b) ${\mathcal {M}}_k^{\#}$ is solid and universal,

  3. (c) $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}_k^{\#})>{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ .

If $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful, then let $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {M}}_k^\#)$ .

Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ has badness type is 1 if $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ is not successful. We write $bad({\mathcal {M}})=1$ .

Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate and $bad({\mathcal {M}})\not =0, 1$ . We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ has badness type 2 if $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ is not weakly Z-suitable and does not have a Z-validated strategy. We write $bad({\mathcal {M}})=2$ .

$next_s({\mathcal {M}})$

Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate, $bad({\mathcal {M}})\not =0,1, 2$ and $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ is not weakly Z-suitable. Let $\Sigma $ be the unique Z-validated strategy of $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ . We now define $next_s({\mathcal {M}})$ , which, in a sense, adds $Lp^{\Sigma }(next_s({\mathcal {M}}))$ to ${\mathcal {M}}$ .

We let $next_s({\mathcal {M}})$ be build as follows. Let $({\mathcal {M}}_i, \Sigma _i: i\leq k)$ be a sequence of Z-validated hod premice along with their Z-validated strategies defined as follows:

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {M}}_0={\mathcal {N}}$ and $\Sigma _0=\Sigma $ .

  2. 2. If $i+1\leq k$ , then there is ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ that is an initial segment of $J[\vec {E}, \Sigma _i]({\mathcal {M}}_i)$ Footnote 114 such that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}^*)<mo({\mathcal {M}}_i)$ , and letting ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ be the least such initial segment of $J[\vec {E}, \Sigma _i]({\mathcal {M}}_i)$ , ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ is solid and universal, $\rho ({\mathcal {M}}^*)>{\delta }^{\mathcal { H}}$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{i+1}=\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {M}}^*)$ and $\Sigma _{i+1}$ is the unique Z-validated strategy of ${\mathcal {M}}_{i+1}$ .

  3. 3. k is least such that either (i) no level of $J[\vec {E}, \Sigma _k]({\mathcal {M}}_k)$ projects across $mo({\mathcal {M}}_k)$ or (ii) ${\mathcal {M}}_k$ does not have a Z-validated strategy, or (iii) some level of $J[\vec {E}, \Sigma _k]({\mathcal {M}}_k)$ projects to or below ${\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ .

We say $next_s({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful if clause 3(ii)–(iii) do not happen. If $next_s({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful, then let $next_{s}({\mathcal {M}})=J[\vec {E}, \Sigma _k]({\mathcal {M}}_k)|{\alpha }$ , where

$$ \begin{align*} {\alpha}=(mo({\mathcal{M}}_k)^+)^{J[\vec{E}, \Sigma_k]({\mathcal{M}}_k)}. \end{align*} $$

Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ has badness type 3 if $bad({\mathcal {M}})\not =0,1, 2$ and $next_{s}({\mathcal {M}})$ is not successful. We write $bad({\mathcal {M}})=3$ . We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ has badness type is 4 if $bad({\mathcal {M}})\not =0,1,2, 3$ and $next_s({\mathcal {M}})$ does not have a Z-validated strategy.

$next_{\Theta -ex}$

Suppose now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate and $bad({\mathcal {M}})\not \in 5$ . Let $\Sigma $ be the unique Z-validated strategy of $next_s({\mathcal {M}})$ . We say that $next_{\Theta -ex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful if there is a unique ${\mathcal {M}}$ -extender F such that

  1. 1. $\mathrm {crit }(F)={\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ ,

  2. 2. $({\mathcal {M}}, F)$ is a Z-validated hod mouse,

  3. 3. $\rho (({\mathcal {M}}, F))>{\delta }^{{\mathcal { H}}}$ .

If $next_{\Theta -ex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is successful, then we let $next_{\Theta -ex}({\mathcal {M}})=\mathcal {C}(({\mathcal {M}}, F))$ , where F is as above. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ has badness type 5 if $next_{\Theta -ex}({\mathcal {M}})$ is not successful. In this case, we write $bad({\mathcal {M}})=5$ .

Definition 11.2. Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate. We say ${\mathcal {M}}$ is bad if $bad({\mathcal {M}})$ is defined.

Definition 11.3. Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate. If ${\mathcal {M}}$ is not bad, then we let $next({\mathcal {M}})=next_{\Theta -ex}({\mathcal {M}})$ .

Remark 11.4. In order for ${\mathcal {M}}\in dom(next)$ , it is necessary that $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ is not a weakly Z-suitable level.

The $next$ function defined above gives us the next model in $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ , but it does not tell us how to start the construction. We will start $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ with ${\mathcal { H}}$ , which is an appropriate hod premouse. However, if we encounter ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ is weakly Z-suitable, then we have to continue with the Z-validated sts construction. We get back to $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ once we produce the canonical witness to non-Woodiness of ${\delta }^{next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})}$ . What we do next is we define the $start$ function whose domain will consist of objects that the Z-validated sts construction produces on top of $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}})$ .

$start({\mathcal {R}})$

Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}$ is a Z-validated hod mouse such that

  1. 1. $mo({\mathcal {R}})$ is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {R}}$ ,

  2. 2. $({\mathcal {R}}|mo({\mathcal {R}}))^\#{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {R}}$ ,

  3. 3. ${\mathcal {R}}$ is sound,

  4. 4. ${\mathcal {R}}$ is an sts premouse over $({\mathcal {R}}|mo({\mathcal {R}}))^\#$ such that $rud({\mathcal {R}}){\vDash } \text {`}mo({\mathcal {R}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

If ${\mathcal {R}}$ is as above, then we write ${\mathcal {R}}\in dom(stop)$ . Let $\Sigma $ be the Z-validated strategy of ${\mathcal {R}}$ if it exists; in the case it does not exist, we declare $start_0({\mathcal {R}})$ is unsuccessful, and letting p on ${\mathcal {R}}$ as in Proposition 10.7, we then switch to the f.b. $(Z, \lambda )$ -validated sts construction over ${\mathrm m}^+(p)$ . In the case $\Sigma $ exists, we define $start_0({\mathcal {R}})$ just like we defined $next_{s}({\mathcal {M}})$ above. If $start_0({\mathcal {R}})$ is successful, then it will output a Z-validated hod mouse ${\mathcal {W}}$ that nicely extends ${\mathcal { H}}$ and has a Z-validated strategy $\Lambda $ . Moreover, for some ${\delta }\in {\mathcal {W}}$ ,

  1. 1. $({\mathcal {W}}|{\delta })^\#{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {W}}$ is of lsa type,

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {W}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }$ is not a Woodin cardinal’,

  3. 3. letting ${\mathcal {W}}^*{\trianglelefteq }{\mathcal {W}}$ be largest such that ${\mathcal {W}}^*{\vDash } yy{\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal’, ${\mathcal {W}}^*$ is a $\Lambda ^{stc}_{({\mathcal {W}}|{\delta })^\#}$ -sts mouse over $({\mathcal {W}}|{\delta })^\#$ and ${\mathcal {W}}=J[\vec {E}, \Lambda _{{\mathcal {W}}^*}]|({\delta }^+)^{J[\vec {E}, \Lambda _{{\mathcal {W}}^*}]}$ .

Next, let $start_1({\mathcal {R}})$ be defined just like $next_{\Theta -ex}({\mathcal {M}})$ starting with $start_0({\mathcal {R}})$ . For ${\mathcal {R}}\in dom(start)$ , we say $start({\mathcal {R}})$ is successful if both $start_0({\mathcal {R}})$ and $start_1({\mathcal {R}})$ are successful, and we let $start({\mathcal {R}})$ be the model that $start_1({\mathcal {R}})$ outputs.

Definition 11.5. Suppose ${\mathcal {R}}\in dom(start)$ . We say ${\mathcal {R}}$ is ready for $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ if $start({\mathcal {R}})$ is successful.

Notice that if $start({\mathcal {R}})$ is successful, then $mo(start({\mathcal {R}}))=Ord\cap start({\mathcal {R}})$ . We end this subsection with the definition of $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ .

Levels of $\mathsf {HFBC}$

Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}={\mathcal { H}}$ or ${\mathcal {M}}=start({\mathcal {R}})$ for some ${\mathcal {R}}\in dom(start)$ such that $start({\mathcal {R}})$ is successful. Let $\Sigma $ be the unique Z-validated strategy of ${\mathcal {M}}$ .

Definition 11.6. We say $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi },\Sigma _{\xi }, : \xi < \Omega ')$ , where $\Omega ' \leq Ord$ , are the levels of the hybrid fully backgrounded construction at $\mu $ ( $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ ) done with respect to $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ if the following conditions hold.

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {M}}_0={\mathcal {M}}$ and $\Sigma _0=\Sigma $ .

  2. 2. For each $\xi <\Omega '$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ is appropriate and $\Sigma _{\xi }$ is the unique Z-validated strategy of ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ .

  3. 3. For all $\xi <\Omega '$ , if $\xi +1<\Omega '$ , then ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ is not bad and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi +1}=next({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi })$ .

  4. 4. For all $\xi < \Omega '$ , if $\xi $ is a limit ordinal, then letting ${\mathcal {M}}^*_{\xi }=_{def}liminf_{{\alpha }\rightarrow \xi }{\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }$ , ${\mathcal {M}}^*_{\xi }$ is appropriate and not bad and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }=next({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }^*)$ .

  5. 5. $\Omega '$ is the least ordinal ${\alpha }$ such that one of the following conditions hold:

    1. (a) ${\alpha }$ is a limit ordinal and ${\mathcal {M}}^*_{\alpha }$ is bad.

    2. (b) ${\alpha }$ is a limit ordinal and $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}}^*_{\alpha })$ is weakly Z-suitable.

    3. (c) ${\alpha }={\beta }+1$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\beta }$ is bad.

We say $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ converges if $\Omega '$ is as in clause 5(b) (i.e., $next_{\#}({\mathcal {M}}^*_{\Omega '})$ is weakly Z-suitable). The following proposition is essentially [Reference Mitchell and Steel28, Theorem 11.3].

Proposition 11.7. Suppose ${\delta }>\mu $ is a Woodin cardinal. Then if for all $\xi <{\delta }$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ is defined, then $\Omega '={\delta }$ and $\mathsf {HFBC}$ converges. Moreover, letting ${\mathcal {P}}^-=liminf_{\xi \rightarrow {\delta }}{\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ and ${\mathcal {P}}=({\mathcal {P}}^-)^\#$ , then ${\mathcal {P}}$ is weakly Z-suitable.

Letting ${\delta }>\mu $ be the least Woodin cardinal $>\mu $ , we need to show that $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ either lasts ${\delta }$ steps or encounters a weakly Z-suitable stage. Recall that we defined $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ over some $({\mathcal {M}}, \Sigma )$ .

12. Putting it all together

We are assuming theory T and let $(S, S_0, \nu _0, \vec {Y}, \vec {A})$ witness it; let $\mu \in S_0$ . Combining $\mathsf {HFBC}(\mu )$ with the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction, as shown by Proposition 10.7, we see that we reach an honest Z-suitable ${\mathcal {R}}$ . In this section, we would like to continue the Z-validated sts construction over ${\mathcal {R}}$ and show that it must reach an excellent ${\mathcal {P}}$ . To do this, we will stack fully backgrounded Z-validated sts constructions one on the top of another to reach an almost excellent hybrid premouse which we will show has external iterability. We will then need some arguments that translate iterable almost excellent hybrid premice into an excellent ones.

This stacking idea might be a little bit unnatural but it seems the most straightforward way of dealing with the two main issues at hand. What we would really like to do is to perform the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction over ${\mathcal {R}}$ and hope that it will reach an excellent hybrid premouse. There are two key issues that arise. The final model of our construction has to inherit a stationary class of measurable cardinals. Perhaps the most straightforward way of dealing with this issue is to attempt to show that every measurable cardinal ${\kappa }$ such that no cardinal is ${\kappa }$ -strong remains measurable in the output of the backgrounded construction. We do not know how to show this without working with more complex forms of backgrounded constructions. Our solution involves just adding the measure by ‘brute force’. Once the construction reaches one such ${\kappa }$ , we will continue by adding the measure coarsely, much like one does in the construction of $L[\mu ]$ .

The next issue is to guarantee window-based iterability. The most natural way of accomplishing this is by showing that the models of our backgrounded construction are iterable. However, this may not work, and if it fails, it fails as follows. Suppose ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a model appearing in the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction over ${\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\kappa }$ is a cutpoint cardinal of ${\mathcal {N}}$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {N}}$ has no Woodin cardinals above ${\kappa }$ . We now seek a Z-validated strategy for ${\mathcal {N}}$ that acts on iterations above ${\kappa }$ . If such a strategy does not exist, then we must have a tree ${\mathcal {T}}$ on ${\mathcal {N}}$ above $\kappa $ which does not have a Z-validated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure. Let then ${\mathcal {N}}_1^-={\mathrm m}({\mathcal {T}})$ . It follows that if we perform a fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction over ${\mathcal {N}}_1^-$ , we will not reach a ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {T}}$ . Let then ${\mathcal {N}}_1$ be the one cardinal extension of ${\mathcal {N}}_1^-$ built by the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction over ${\mathcal {N}}_1^-$ . We thus have that ${\mathcal {N}}_1{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

We now want to see that ${\mathcal {N}}_1$ has a window-based iterability. Let then $\eta _1\in ({\kappa }, {\delta }({\mathcal {T}}))$ be a regular cardinal of ${\mathcal {N}}_1$ , and we want to argue that ${\mathcal {N}}_1|\eta _1$ is iterable. The strategy we seek is again a Z-validated strategy. If it does not exist, then we get a tree ${\mathcal {T}}_1$ on ${\mathcal {N}}_1|\eta _1$ such that ${\mathcal {T}}_1$ does not have a Z-validated ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure. The construction above produced ${\mathcal {N}}_2$ extending ${\mathrm m}({\mathcal {T}}_1)$ . The goal now is to show that ${\mathcal {N}}_2$ has window-based iterability. Failure of such a strategy produced $\eta _2\in ({\kappa }, {\delta }({\mathcal {T}}_1))$ , ${\mathcal {T}}_2$ based on ${\mathcal {N}}_2$ that is above ${\kappa }$ and a model ${\mathcal {N}}_3$ extending ${\mathrm m}({\mathcal {T}}_2)$ . The process outlined above cannot last $\omega $ many steps, for if it did, we will have a sequence $({\mathcal {N}}_i, {\mathcal {T}}_i: i<\omega )$ and a reflected version of this sequence cannot have a well-founded direct limit along the realizable branches.

There is yet another issue that we need to deal with which is not connected with the stacking construction but has to do with other aspects of the construction. We will need arguments that will show window-based iterability in V can somehow be reflected inside the sts premice alluded above. To show this, we will need to break into cases and examine exactly how we ended up with the model we seek. For this reason, we isolate the following hypothesis.

$\mathsf {Hypo}:$ For some X containing ${\mathcal {R}}$ , there is a sound Z-validated almost excellent mouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ over X that is based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

The following essentially follows from the main results of [Reference Neeman31].

Proposition 12.1. Assume $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ . Then for any X containing ${\mathcal {R}}$ , letting ${\delta }$ be the least Woodin cardinal such that $X\in V_{\delta }$ , no model of the Z-validated sts construction of $V_{\delta }$ that is based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ and is done over X reaches an almost excellent hybrid premouse.

12.1. The prototypical branch existence argument

Here, we present an argument due to John Steel that we will use over and over again. The argument is general and can be used in many settings. We will refer to this argument as the prototypical branch existence argument. In the sequel, when we need to prove something via the same argument, we will just say that ‘the prototypical branch existence argument shows…’.

The prototypical branch existence argument

Suppose ${\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal, $X\in V_{\delta }$ is a set such that ${\mathcal {R}}\in X$ and $({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\alpha }: {\alpha }\leq {\delta })$ are the models of the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction done over X. Fix ${\alpha }\leq {\delta }$ and suppose that ${\mathcal {N}}_{\alpha }$ has no Woodin cardinals (as an sts premouse over X). Let ${\mathcal {T}}$ be a normal Z-validated iteration of ${\mathcal {N}}_{\alpha }$ such that for every limit ${\beta }<lh({\mathcal {T}})$ , if $c_{\beta }=[0, {\beta }]_T$ , then ${\mathcal {Q}}(c_{\beta }, {\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\beta })$ exists and is Z-validated. Suppose that ${\mathcal {T}}$ has limit length and there is a Z-validated sts mouse ${\mathcal {Q}}$ such that ${\mathrm m}({\mathcal {T}}){\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {Q}}$ and $rud({\mathcal {Q}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’. Then there is a branch b of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ exists and is equal to ${\mathcal {Q}}$ .

The argument proceeds as follows. Fix some $\lambda \in S_0-{\delta }$ and let $\pi _U: M_U\rightarrow H_{\zeta }$ be a $(\mu , {\lambda }, Z)$ -good hull such that ${\mathcal {T}}, {\mathcal {Q}}\in rng(\pi )$ . Let $\nu =\vert {M_U}\vert $ and let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , \nu )$ be generic. Then there is a maximal branch c of ${\mathcal {T}}_U$ , ${\beta }\leq {\alpha }$ and a (weak) embedding $\sigma :{\mathcal {M}}^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}_c\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}_{\beta }$ such that if c is nondropping, then ${\beta }={\alpha }$ and $\pi _U=\sigma \circ \pi ^{{\mathcal {T}}_U}$ . Arguing as in Proposition 9.5, we get that c must be a cofinal branch and that ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ must exist and be equal to ${\mathcal {Q}}_U$ . It follows then that $c\in M_U$ . Hence, $\pi _U(c)$ is as desired.

Remark 12.2. It is important to keep in mind that the argument does not work when ${\mathcal {N}}_{\alpha }$ has Woodin cardinals, as then ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}}_U)$ may not exist. Thus, this argument cannot in general be used to show that levels of $K^c$ are short-tree iterable.

12.2. One step construction

Suppose X is a set such that ${\mathcal {R}}\in X$ . The main goal of this section is to produce a short-tree-iterable Z-suitable sts hod premouse over X. Here, short-tree iterability is in the sense of the ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ analysis (cf. [Reference Steel, Woodin, Kechris, Löwe and Steel14]).

Definition 12.3. Suppose ${\mathcal {P}}$ is a Z-validated sts premouse over X based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ . We say ${\mathcal {P}}$ is almost Z -good if ${\mathcal {P}}$ , as an sts premouse over X, has a unique Woodin cardinal ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {P}}=({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}})^\#$ ,

  2. 2. if ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a sound Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal {P}}$ , then ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

We say ${\mathcal {P}}$ is Z -good if ${\mathcal {P}}$ has a unique Woodin cardinal ${\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ such that

  1. 1. $({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}})^\#$ is almost Z-good,

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {P}}=Lp^{Zv, sts}({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}})$ ,

  3. 3. for every regular cardinal $\eta <{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ , ${\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ has a Z-validated strategy.

We say that the Z-good ${\mathcal {P}}$ is fully backgrounded if for some maximal window w and for some $\xi \in w$ , ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}$ is a model appearing in the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction of $V_{\eta }$ which uses extenders with critical point $>\xi $ .

Proposition 12.4. Assume $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ . There is a Z-good fully backgrounded sts premouse over X based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

We spend this entire subsection proving Proposition 12.4. We will do it in two steps. In the first step, we will produce a fully backgrounded almost Z-good ${\mathcal {N}}$ . Then we will obtain a fully backgrounded Z-good ${\mathcal {P}}$ . We start with the first step.

Lemma 12.5. Assume $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ . There is an almost Z-good fully backgrounded sts premouse over X based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

Proof. Let ${\delta }$ be the least Woodin cardinal of V such that $X\in V_{\delta }$ . Let $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi \leq \Omega ^*)$ be the models of the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction of $V_{\delta }$ done over X (based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ ). Because we are assuming $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ , $\Omega ^*={\delta }$ . We claim the following.

Claim. There is $\xi \leq {\delta }$ such that ${\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }$ is an almost Z-good sts premouse.

Proof. Suppose for every $\xi <{\delta }$ , ${\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }$ is not almost Z-good. We show that ${\mathcal {N}}=({\mathcal {N}}_{\delta })^\#$ is an almost Z-good sts premouse. A standard reflection argument shows that $\rho _{\omega }({\mathcal {N}})<{\delta }$ . Suppose then ${\mathcal {N}}$ is not almost Z-good and fix ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {N}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}$ ,

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {M}}$ is sound above ${\delta }$ ,

  3. 3. $\rho _{\omega }({\delta })<{\delta }$ ,

  4. 4. ${\mathcal {M}}$ is Z-validated and has a Z-validated $Ord$ -strategy.

As we are are assuming $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ , ${\delta }$ is not a limit of Woodin cardinals in ${\mathcal {N}}$ . Let then $\pi : {\mathcal {M}}^*\rightarrow {\mathcal {M}}$ be such that letting $\mathrm {crit }(\pi )=\nu $ , $\pi (\nu )={\delta }$ and ${\mathcal {N}}$ has no Woodin cardinals in the interval $[\nu , {\delta })$ .

Working inside ${\mathcal {N}}$ , let ${\mathcal {N}}'$ be the output of the $({\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {R}}^b, S^{\mathcal {N}})$ -authenticated construction done over ${\mathcal {N}}|\nu +1$ using extenders with critical points $>\nu $ . Let ${\mathcal {M}}'$ be the result of translating ${\mathcal {M}}$ over to ${\mathcal {N}}'$ via the S-construction (see [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 6.4]). Similarly, for each ${\mathcal {N}}$ -cardinal $\xi>\nu $ such that $({\mathcal {N}}|\xi )^\#{\vDash } \text {`}\xi $ is a Woodin cardinal’, let ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ witness that our proposition fails for $({\mathcal {N}}|\xi )^\#$ . For each such $\xi $ , let ${\mathcal {M}}^{\prime }_{\xi }$ be the result of translating ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ over to ${\mathcal {N}}'|\xi $ .

We now compare ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ with the construction producing ${\mathcal {N}}'$ . In this comparison, only ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ is moving. We claim that this comparison lasts ${\delta }+1$ -steps producing a tree ${\mathcal {T}}$ on ${\mathcal {M}}^*$ with last model ${\mathcal {M}}'$ . Indeed, given ${\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ , where ${\alpha }\leq {\delta }$ is a limit ordinal, if ${\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha }){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ is a Woodin cardinal’, then ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }'$ is defined. Because ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-validated sts mouse, we must have a unique cofinal well-founded branch $b_{\alpha }$ of ${\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha }$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ is defined and is equal to ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }'$ . We then pick this branch $b_{\alpha }$ at stage ${\alpha }$ .

It must now be clear that the existence of ${\mathcal {T}}$ violates universality; this implies by standard results that there must be a superstrong cardinal in ${\mathcal {N}}$ . The reader may consult [Reference Sargsyan34, Lemma 5.4].

The claim finishes the proof.

We now start the proof of Proposition 12.4. Towards a contradiction, we assume that there is no fully backgrounded Z-good sts premouse over X based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Let ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ be a fully backgrounded almost Z-good sts premouse over X based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

Below, given ${\mathcal {S}}$ , ${\delta }^{\mathcal {S}}$ will always denote the largest Woodin of ${\mathcal {S}}$ and $w^{\mathcal {S}}$ will denote the maximal window w of ${\mathcal {S}}$ such that ${\delta }^w={\delta }^{\mathcal {S}}$ .

We now by induction produce an infinite sequence $({\mathcal {N}}_i, \nu _i, {\mathcal {T}}_i: i<\omega )$ such that

  1. 1. for every $i<\omega $ , ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ is a fully backgrounded almost Z-good sts premouse over X based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ ,

  2. 2. for every $i<\omega $ , $\nu _i$ is a successor cardinal of ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ ,

  3. 3. for every $i<\omega $ , ${\mathcal {T}}_i$ is a normal Z-validated iteration of ${\mathcal {N}}_i|\nu _i$ such that ${\mathcal {T}}_i$ has no cofinal well-founded branch b such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}}_i)$ exists and is a Z-validated mouse,

  4. 4. for every $i<\omega $ , ${\mathcal {N}}_{i+1}={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}}_i)$ .

A simple reflection argument shows that such a sequence cannot exist. The fact that for $i>0$ , ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ is fully backgrounded is irrelevant for the reflected argument alluded in the previous sentence. It is enough that ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ is fully backgrounded.

Assume then we have built ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ , and we now describe the procedure for getting $(\nu _i, {\mathcal {T}}_i, {\mathcal {N}}_{i+1})$ . Because ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ is not Z-good, there is a $\nu _i\in w^{{\mathcal {N}}_i}$ which is a successor cardinal of ${\mathcal {N}}_i$ and ${\mathcal {N}}_i|\nu _i$ does not have a Z-validated strategy.

Let $\eta $ be some Woodin cardinal such that ${\mathcal {N}}_i\in V_{\eta }$ and let $\xi _{\eta }<\eta $ be such that ${\mathcal {N}}_i\in H_{\xi _{\eta }}$ and there are no Woodin cardinals in the interval $(\xi _{\eta }, \eta )$ . Let $({\mathcal {M}}^\eta _{\alpha }, {\mathcal {S}}^\eta _{\alpha }: {\alpha }\leq \eta )$ be the models of the fully backgrounded Z-validated sts construction of $V_{\eta }$ done over X using extenders with critical points $>\xi _{\eta }$ .

As ${\mathcal {N}}_i\in H_{\xi }$ , in the comparison of ${\mathcal {W}}=_{def}{\mathcal {N}}_i|\nu _i$ with the construction $({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^\eta , {\mathcal {S}}^\eta _{\alpha }: {\alpha }\leq \eta )$ , only ${\mathcal {W}}$ moves. We now analyze the tree on ${\mathcal {W}}$ . Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}^\eta $ is the tree on ${\mathcal {W}}$ built via the above comparison and suppose ${\mathcal {T}}^\eta $ has a limit length. We now have two cases.

Case1. Suppose there is ${\alpha }$ such that ${\mathcal {S}}^\eta _{\alpha }{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’. It follows from the prototypical argument that there must be a cofinal branch b of ${\mathcal {T}}$ such that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ exists and is a Z-validated mouse. We then extend ${\mathcal {T}}^\eta $ by adding b.

Case2. Suppose there is no ${\alpha }\leq \eta $ such that ${\mathcal {S}}^\eta _{\alpha }{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’. In this case, we stop the construction and set ${\mathcal {N}}_{i+1}={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ and ${\mathcal {T}}_i={\mathcal {T}}$ .

We stop the construction if either Case2 holds or for some ${\alpha }$ , ${\mathcal {M}}^\eta _{\alpha }$ is the last model of ${\mathcal {T}}$ and $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ exists.

We now claim that for some $\eta $ , the construction of ${\mathcal {T}}^\eta $ stops because of Case2. Assume otherwise. Then for each Woodin cardinal $\eta $ , we have ${\alpha }_{\eta }$ and an embedding $\pi :{\mathcal {W}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {M}}^\eta _{{\alpha }_{\eta }}$ . As ${\mathcal {W}}$ has no Woodin cardinals, it follows that for every $\eta $ , ${\mathcal {W}}$ is $\xi _{\eta }$ -iterable via a Z-validated strategy. As $Ord=\bigcup _{\eta } \xi _{\eta }$ , we have that ${\mathcal {W}}$ is $Ord$ -iterable via a Z-validated strategy. Hence, for some $\eta $ , Case2 must be the cause for stopping the construction of ${\mathcal {T}}^\eta $ . Below, we drop $\eta $ from subscripts.

To finish the proof of Proposition 12.4, we need to show that ${\mathcal {N}}_{i+1}$ is almost Z-good. This easily follows from universality. Because ${\delta }({\mathcal {T}} )$ is Woodin in ${\mathcal {S}}_{\eta }$ , we must have that ${\mathcal {N}}_{i+1}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {S}}_{\eta }$ . If now ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a ${\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ -sound Z-validated sts mouse, then because ${\mathcal {T}}$ has no ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure, we must have that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})\geq {\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ and ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’ (as otherwise the prototypical argument would yield a branch of ${\mathcal {T}}$ ).

12.3. Stacking suitable sts mice

In this section, assuming $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ , we build an almost excellent hybrid premouse. We achieve this by stacking fully backgrounded Z-good sts premice. As we said in the introduction to this section, we will make sure that a stationary set of measurable cardinals will remain measurable in the model produced by our construction. This will be achieved by adding each such measures by brute force.

By induction, we define a sequence $\vec {{\mathcal { K}}}=({\mathcal { K}}_{\alpha }: {\alpha }\in \Omega )$ , called a Z-good stack,Footnote 115 such that

  1. 1. ${\mathcal { K}}_0$ is a fully backgrounded Z-good sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ ,

  2. 2. for every ${\alpha }$ , ${\mathcal { K}}_{{\alpha }+1}$ is a fully backgrounded Z-good sts hod premouse over ${\mathcal { K}}_{\alpha }$ ,

  3. 3. if ${\alpha }$ is a limit ordinal and $Ord\cap \bigcup _{{\beta }<{\alpha }}{\mathcal { K}}_{\beta }\not \in S$ , then ${\mathcal { K}}_{\alpha }=Lp^{Zv, sts}(\bigcup _{{\beta }<{\alpha }}{\mathcal { K}}_{\beta })$ ,

  4. 4. if ${\alpha }$ is a limit ordinal and ${\lambda }=_{def}Ord\cap \bigcup _{{\beta }<{\alpha }}{\mathcal { K}}_{\beta } \in S$ , then letting U be a normal measure on ${\lambda }$ and setting ${\mathcal { K}}^{\prime }_{\alpha }=\bigcup _{{\beta }<{\alpha }}{\mathcal { K}}_{\beta }$ and ${\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime }_{\alpha }=\pi _U({\mathcal { K}}^{\prime }_{\alpha })|({\lambda }^{++})^{\pi _U({\mathcal { K}}^{\prime }_{\alpha })}$ , ${\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime \prime }_{\alpha }=({\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime }_{\alpha }, E)$ where E is the $({\lambda }, ({\lambda }^{+})^{\pi _U({\mathcal { K}}^{\prime }_{\alpha })})$ -extender derived from $\pi _U$ and ${\mathcal { K}}_{\alpha }$ is the core of ${\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime \prime }_{\alpha }$ .

We call $\vec {{\mathcal { K}}}$ the $(f.b. Z)$ -validated stack. The construction of $\vec {{\mathcal { K}}}$ is straightforward. However, we need to verify the following three statements.

(S1) For ${\alpha }<{\beta }$ , if ${\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal { K}}_{\alpha }$ , then no level of ${\mathcal { K}}_{\beta }$ projects across ${\delta }$ and ${\mathcal { K}}_{\beta }{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

(S2) If $Ord\cap \bigcup _{{\beta }<{\lambda }}{\mathcal { K}}_{\beta } \in S$ , then ${\lambda }$ is a measurable cardinal in ${\mathcal { K}}_{{\lambda }+1}$ .

(S3) The class of ${\lambda }$ such that $Ord\cap \bigcup _{{\beta }<{\lambda }}{\mathcal { K}}_{\beta } \in S$ is stationary.

We now prove the above three clauses by proving a sequence of lemmas.

Lemma 12.6. For every ${\alpha }$ , ${\mathcal { K}}_{\alpha }$ is a Z-validated mouse. If ${\alpha }\in S$ is such that $Ord\cap \bigcup _{{\beta }<{\lambda }}{\mathcal { K}}_{\beta } \in S$ , then ${\mathcal { K}}^{\prime }_{\alpha }$ , ${\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime }_{\alpha }$ , ${\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime \prime }_{\alpha }$ are also Z-validated mice.

Lemma 12.6 is a consequence of [Reference Neeman31, Corollary 3.16]. This corollary shows that if U is a good hull, then the pre-images of the relevant objects have iteration strategies that pick realizable branches, which implies that they have Z-approved strategies.

Lemma 12.7. (S1) holds.

Proof. Fix ${\alpha }<{\beta }$ and ${\delta }$ as in the statement of (S1). Suppose ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal { K}}_{{\beta }}$ is such that $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})< {\delta }$ . It follows from our construction that for some ${\gamma }+1\leq {\alpha }$ , ${\delta }={\delta }^{{\mathcal { K}}_{{\gamma }+1}}$ . Let $p=p_{n+1}({\mathcal {M}})$ be the standard parameter of ${\mathcal {M}}$ and n be least such that $\rho _{n+1}({\mathcal {M}})=\rho ({\mathcal {M}})<{\delta }$ . Let ${\mathcal {W}}$ be the canonical decoding structure of $Hull_1^{{\mathcal {M}}^n}({\delta }\cup \{p\})$ , where ${\mathcal {M}}^n$ is the n-th reduct of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . As ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-validated sts premouse and ${\mathcal { K}}_{{\gamma }+1}$ is Z-suitable, we must have that $rud({\mathcal {W}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal’. Hence, $\rho ({\mathcal {W}})={\delta }$ , a contradiction. A similar argument shows that ${\mathcal { K}}_{\beta }{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

Lemma 12.8. (S2) holds.

Proof. First, we claim that $\rho ({\mathcal { K}}_{\lambda })>{\lambda }$ . Lemma 12.7 shows that $\rho ({\mathcal { K}}_{\lambda })\geq {\lambda }$ . Assume then that $\rho ({\mathcal { K}}_{\lambda })={\lambda }$ . Let ${\mathcal {W}}=Core({\mathcal { K}}_{\lambda })$ and U be the normal measure on ${\lambda }$ . Because of our definition of $\vec {{\mathcal { K}}}$ , we have that

$$ \begin{align*} Ult(V, U){\vDash} {\mathcal{ K}}^{\prime\prime}_{\lambda}=Lp^{Zv, sts}({\mathcal{ K}}^{\prime}_{\lambda}). \end{align*} $$

Let now F be the last extender of ${\mathcal {W}}$ . As ${\vert {\mathcal {W}}\vert }={\lambda }$ , we have $\sigma : Ult({\mathcal {W}}, F)\rightarrow \pi _U({\mathcal {W}})$ such that $\sigma \in Ult(V, U)$ . It follows that

$$ \begin{align*} Ult(V, U){\vDash} Ult({\mathcal{W}}, F) \text{ is a } Z\text{-validated sts premouse over } {\mathcal{ K}}^{\prime}_{\lambda}. \end{align*} $$

Hence, $Ult({\mathcal {W}}, F){\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime }_{\lambda }$ implying that ${\mathcal {W}}\in {\mathcal { K}}^{\prime \prime }_{\lambda }$ . Thus, $\rho ({\mathcal { K}}_{\lambda })>{\lambda }$ .

The same argument shows that if ${\mathcal {M}}{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal { K}}_{{\lambda }+1}$ , then $\rho ({\mathcal {M}})>{\lambda }$ . Thus, ${\lambda }$ must be a measurable cardinal in ${\mathcal { K}}_{{\lambda }+1}$ .

(S3) is trivial. It then follows that $\bigcup _{{\alpha }\in Ord}{\mathcal { K}}_{\alpha }$ is an almost excellent hybrid premouse.

12.4. The conclusion assuming $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$

We remind our reader that we have gotten to this point by assuming that $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ holds. The following summarizes the results of the previous subsection.

Corollary 12.9. Assume $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ . Then there is an honest Z-suitable ${\mathcal {R}}$ and a Z-validated almost excellent class size premouse ${\mathcal { K}}$ based on ${\mathcal {R}}$ satisfying the following conditions.

  1. 1. For each maximal window w of ${\mathcal { K}}$ and for each $\eta \in (\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ that is a regular cardinal in ${\mathcal { K}}$ , ${\mathcal { K}}$ has a Z-validated iteration strategy $\Sigma $ that acts on normal iterations that are based on ${\mathcal { K}}|\eta $ and are above $\nu ^w$ .

  2. 2. For each maximal window w of ${\mathcal { K}}$ , ${\mathcal { K}}|{\delta }^w$ is a fully backgrounded Z-good sts premouse over ${\mathcal { K}}|\nu ^w$ .

  3. 3. For each Woodin cardinal ${\delta }$ of ${\mathcal { K}}$ and for each Z-validated sound sts mouse ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that ${\mathcal { K}}|{\delta }{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}$ , ${\mathcal {M}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }$ is a Woodin cardinal’.

The next proposition completes the proof Theorem 1.4 and Theorem 1.7 assuming $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ .

Proposition 12.10. Assume $\neg \mathsf {Hypo}$ . Then there is a class size excellent hybrid premouse.

We spend the rest of this subsection proving Proposition 12.10. Let ${\mathcal {R}}$ and ${\mathcal { K}}$ be as in Corollary 12.9. We claim that, in fact, ${\mathcal { K}}$ is excellent. To see this, let w be a maximal window of ${\mathcal { K}}$ and let $\eta \in (\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ be a regular cardinal of ${\mathcal { K}}$ . We want to see that in ${\mathcal { K}}$ , ${\mathcal { K}}|\eta $ has an iteration strategy that acts on normal iterations that are above $\nu ^w$ . Let $\Sigma $ be the Z-validated strategy of ${\mathcal { K}}|\eta $ that acts on normal iterations that are above $\nu ^w$ . It is enough to show that $\Sigma {\restriction } {\mathcal { K}}$ is definable over ${\mathcal { K}}$ .

We work inside ${\mathcal { K}}$ . Given a normal iteration ${\mathcal {T}}$ of ${\mathcal { K}}|\eta $ that is above $\nu ^w$ , we will say ${\mathcal {T}}$ has a correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure if letting $(u, \zeta , ({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi \leq {\delta }^u))$ be such that

  1. 1. u is the least maximal window of ${\mathcal { K}}$ with the property that ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal { K}}|{\delta }^u$ ,

  2. 2. $\zeta \in (\nu ^u, {\delta }^u)$ is such that ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal { K}}|\zeta $ ,

  3. 3. $({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi <{\delta }^u)$ are the models of the fully backgrounded $({\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {R}}^b, S^{\mathcal { K}})$ -authenticated sts construction of ${\mathcal { K}}|{\delta }^u$ done over ${\mathrm m}({\mathcal {T}})$ using extenders with critical points $>\zeta $ ,

for some $\xi <{\delta }^u$ , ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }{\vDash }\text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’. We then say that ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ is the correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {T}}$ . We have that ${\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }$ has a Z-validated iteration strategy, and hence, if it exists, it is unique (i.e., does not depend on $\zeta $ ).

Continuing our work in ${\mathcal { K}}$ , given ${\mathcal {T}}$ as above, we say ${\mathcal {T}}$ is correctly guided if for every limit ${\alpha }<lh({\mathcal {T}})$ , letting $b=[0, {\alpha }]_{\mathcal {T}}$ , ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}}{\restriction } {\alpha })$ exists and is the correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure of ${\mathcal {T}}$ . The following lemma finishes the proof of Proposition 12.10.

Lemma 12.11. Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal { K}}$ is a normal iteration of ${\mathcal { K}}|\eta $ of limit length that is according to $\Sigma $ . Then ${\mathcal {T}}$ is correctly guided, and if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is of limit length, then ${\mathcal {T}}$ has a correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure.

Proof. The second part of the conclusion of the lemma implies the first as we can apply it to the initial segments of ${\mathcal {T}}$ . Thus, assume that ${\mathcal {T}}$ is correctly guided and is of limit length. Let $b=\Sigma ({\mathcal {T}})$ . Then ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ exists and is Z-validated. Set ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ .

Let $(u, \zeta , ({\mathcal {M}}_{\xi }, {\mathcal {N}}_{\xi }: \xi \leq {\delta }^u))$ be as in the definition of the correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure. Towards a contradiction, assume that letting ${\mathcal {N}}=_{def}{\mathcal {M}}_{{\delta }^u}$ , ${\mathcal {N}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’. Notice that ${\mathcal { K}}|{\delta }^u$ is generic over ${\mathcal {N}}$ , implying that we can translate ${\mathcal { K}}$ via S-constructions into an sts premouse over ${\mathcal {N}}$ ; call it ${\mathcal { K}}'$ . We have that ${\mathcal { K}}'{\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’ and ${\mathcal { K}}'$ is almost excellent.

Next, we compare ${\mathcal {Q}}$ with ${\mathcal { K}}'$ . All of the extenders on the extender sequence of ${\mathcal { K}}'$ have fully backgrounded certificates, which implies that in the aforementioned comparison, only the ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -side moves. Let $\Lambda $ be the unique Z-validated strategy of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ and let ${\mathcal {U}}$ be the tree on ${\mathcal {Q}}$ of limit length such that ${\mathrm m}({\mathcal {U}})={\mathcal { K}}'|{\delta }^u$ . Set $c=\Lambda ({\mathcal {U}})$ and ${\mathcal {M}}={\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {U}})$ .Footnote 116

Notice now that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is ${\delta }^u$ -sound, ${\delta }^u$ is a cutpoint in ${\mathcal {M}}$ and ${\mathcal {M}}$ has no extenders with critical point ${\delta }^u$ . Moreover, ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal { K}}'|{\delta }^u$ , and therefore, it can be translated into a Z-validated sts mouse ${\mathcal {X}}$ over ${\mathcal { K}}|{\delta }^u$ . We must then have that $rud({\mathcal {X}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^u$ is a Woodin cardinal’. But then $rud({\mathcal {M}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^u$ is a Woodin cardinal’, a contradiction.

Notice now that for ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal { K}}$ , we have the following equivalences.

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {T}}\in dom(\Sigma )$ if and only if ${\mathcal { K}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {T}}$ is correctly guided’,

  2. 2. $\Sigma ({\mathcal {T}})=b$ if and only if ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ exists and ${\mathcal { K}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {T}})$ is the correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for ${\mathcal {T}}$ ’.

12.5. Excellent hybrid premouse from $\mathsf {Hypo}$

Finally, we show how to get an excellent hybrid premouse from $\mathsf {Hypo}$ . This will complete the proof of Theorem 1.4 and Theorem 1.7. Suppose then ${\mathcal {R}}$ is an honest Z-suitable hod premouse, X is a set such that ${\mathcal {R}}\in X$ and ${\mathcal {M}}$ is an almost excellent Z-validated sts premouse over X. In particular, ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a model of $\mathsf {ZFC}$ . It must be clear from our construction that we can assume that X has a well-ordering in $L[X]$ . Let then ${\kappa }=({\vert {X}\vert }^+)^{\mathcal {M}}$ . Let ${\delta }$ be the least Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {M}}$ that is $>{\kappa }$ and let ${\mathcal {N}}$ be the output of the fully backgrounded $({\mathcal {R}}, {\mathcal {R}}^b, S^{\mathcal {M}})$ -authenticated sts construction of ${\mathcal {M}}|{\delta }$ done over ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Once again, using S-constructions, we can translate ${\mathcal {M}}$ over to an sts mouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ over ${\mathcal {N}}$ such that ${\mathcal {P}}[{\mathcal {M}}|{\delta }]={\mathcal {M}}$ . Moreover, ${\mathcal {P}}$ is almost excellent and is a Z-validated sts mouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ . Because good hulls of ${\mathcal {P}}$ are iterable via a Z-approved strategy, we can assume, by minimizing if necessary, that ${\mathcal {P}}$ is minimal in the sense that for each $\eta \in ({\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}, Ord\cap {\mathcal {P}})$ , ${\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ is not an almost excellent sts premouse over ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

The rest of the proof follows the same argument as the one given in the previous subsection. We show that ${\mathcal {P}}$ is, in fact, excellent. As before, this amounts to showing that for a window w of ${\mathcal {P}}$ such that ${\delta }^w>{\delta }^{\mathcal {R}}$ , and for any $\eta \in (\nu ^w, {\delta }^w)$ , if $\eta $ is a regular cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ , then ${\mathcal {P}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\mathcal {P}}|\eta $ has $Ord$ -iteration strategy’. Towards a contradiction, assume not.

Let U be a good hull such that ${\mathcal {P}}\in U$ . Set ${\mathcal {S}}={\mathcal {P}}_U$ , ${\mathcal {W}}={\mathcal {R}}_U$ and ${\lambda }=\eta _U$ . Let $\Lambda $ be the Z-approved strategy of ${\mathcal {S}}$ and let $\Sigma $ be the fragment of $\Lambda $ that acts on normal iterations of ${\mathcal {S}}|{\lambda }$ that are above $\nu ^{w_U}$ . The following lemma can be proved via a proof almost identical to the proof of Lemma 12.11. We define correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure and correctly guided exactly the same way as we defined them in the previous subsection, except the definition now takes place in ${\mathcal {S}}$ .

Lemma 12.12. Suppose ${\mathcal {T}}\in {\mathcal {S}}$ is a normal iteration of ${\mathcal {S}}|\eta $ of limit length that is according to $\Sigma $ . Then ${\mathcal {T}}$ is correctly guided and if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is of limit length, then ${\mathcal {T}}$ has a correct ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure.

There is only one difference between the proofs of Lemma 12.11 and Lemma 12.12. In the proof of Lemma 12.11, we concluded that $rud({\mathcal {X}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }^u$ is a Woodin cardinal’ using the fact that $({\mathcal { K}}|{\delta }^u)^\#$ is Z-suitable sts premouse. Here, we no longer have such a fact, but here we can use minimality of ${\mathcal {P}}$ to derive the same conclusion.

As in the previous subsection, Lemma 12.12 easily implies that $\Sigma {\restriction } {\mathcal {P}}$ is definable over ${\mathcal {P}}$ . This completes the proof of Theorem 1.4 and Theorem 1.7.

13. Open problems and questions

The rather mild assumption that the class of measurable cardinals is stationary is used in various ‘pressing down’ arguments in the proof of Theorem 1.4 and Theorem 1.7, and also in stabilization arguments like those of Theorem 5.2. This assumption is probably not needed, though proving some sort of stabilization lemma like the aforementioned one is probably necessary.

Question 13.1. Are the following theories equiconsistent?

  1. 1. $\mathsf {Sealing} $ + ‘There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals’.

  2. 2. $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB} $ + ‘There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals’.

  3. 3. $\mathsf {Tower\ \ Sealing} $ + ‘There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals’.

As mentioned above, CMI becomes very difficult past $\mathsf {Sealing}$ . A good test question for CMI practitioners is the following.

Open Problem 13.2. Prove that Con $(\mathsf {PFA})$ implies Con( $\mathsf {WLW}$ ).

We know from the results above that $\mathsf {WLW}$ is stronger than $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and is roughly the strongest natural theory at the limit of traditional methods for proving iterability. We believe it is plausible to develop CMI methods for obtaining canonical models of $\mathsf {WLW}$ from just $\mathsf {PFA}$ .Footnote 117

Remark 13.3.

  1. 1. By the above discussion, we also get in $V={\mathcal {P}}[g]$ that for every generic h, $(\Gamma ^{\infty }_h)^\#$ exists and by Lemma 3.2, $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_h) \vDash \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}} + \Theta $ is regular. So we have the following strengthening of $\mathsf {Sealing}$ : $\mathsf {Sealing}^+ $ for all V-generic g, in $V[g]$ , $L(\Gamma ^{\infty },\mathbb {R}) \vDash \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}} + \Theta $ is regular. We call this theory $\mathsf {Sealing}^+$ .

  2. 2. The conclusion of $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ can be weakened to the following: For all V-generic g, there is $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^{V[g]}$ such that $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}^{V[g]}){\vDash } \mathsf {LSA}$ and $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ is contained in $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}^{V[g]})$ . We call this theory $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}^-$ .

  3. 3. The results of this paper show the following. Let $T=$ ‘there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary’. Then the following theories are equiconsistent:

    1. (a) $\mathsf {Sealing}+T$ .

    2. (b) $\mathsf {Sealing}^++T$ .

    3. (c) $\mathsf {Tower\ \ Sealing} + T$ .

    4. (d) $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}+T$ .

    5. (e) $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}^-+T$ .

    6. (f) $\mathsf {Weak\ \ Sealing} + T$ .

    7. (g) $\mathsf {Sealing}^{-} + T$

We end the paper with the following conjecture; if true, it would be an ultimate analog of the main result of [Reference Steel50].

Conjecture 13.4. Suppose there are unboundedly many Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary. Then the following are equivalent.

  1. 1. $\mathsf {Sealing}$ .

  2. 2. $\mathsf {Sealing}^{+}$ .

  3. 3. $\mathsf {Weak\ Sealing}$ .

  4. 4. $\mathsf {Sealing}^{-}$ .

  5. 5. $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ .

Acknowledgement

We would like to thank Hugh Woodin for many comments made about the earlier drafts of this paper, and especially for pointing out an easier argument demonstrating that $\mathsf {LSA-over-uB}$ is not equivalent to $\mathsf {Sealing}$ and for bringing the $\mathsf {Tower\ Sealing}$ to our attention. We also thank Ralf Schindler for useful suggestion regarding our use of second-order set theory. The authors are grateful for the referees’ enormous efforts to make the manuscript better. The authors would like to thank the NSF for its generous support. The first author was supported by NSF Career Award DMS-1352034 and by NCN Grant WEAVE-UNISONO, Id: 567137. The second author is supported by NSF Grant No DMS-1565808 and DMS-1849295.

Competing interest

None.

Footnotes

1 Cohen proved that $\mathsf {ZFC} +\neg \mathsf {CH}$ is consistent. Earlier, Gödel showed that $\mathsf {ZFC+CH}$ is consistent by showing that $\mathsf {CH}$ holds in the constructible universe L. Forcing can also be used to show that $\mathsf {ZFC+CH}$ is consistent.

2 A set of reals is analytic if it is a projection of a closed set. A co-analytic set is the complement of an analytic set.

3 As open sets are unions of open intervals, it must be clear that they can be easily interpreted in any extension of the reals.

4 The superscript $\infty $ in this notation, which is due to Woodin, makes sense as one can define ${\kappa }$ -universally Baire sets as those sets whose continuous preimages in all $<{\kappa }$ size topological spaces have the property of Baire. We then set $\Gamma ^{\kappa }$ to be the collection of all of these sets. Clearly, $\Gamma ^{\infty }=\cap _{\kappa }\Gamma ^{\kappa }$ .

5 The meaning of $A_h$ is explained below. It is the canonical extension of A to $V[h]$ .

6 Given a cardinal ${\kappa }$ , we say $T\subseteq \bigcup _{n<\omega } \omega ^n \times {\kappa }^n$ is a tree on ${\kappa }$ if T is closed under initial segments. Given a tree T on ${\kappa }$ , we let $[T]$ be the set of its branches (i.e., $b\in [T]$ if $b\in \omega ^\omega \times {\kappa }^\omega $ and letting $b=(b_0, b_1)$ ) for each $n\in \omega $ , $(b_0{\restriction } n, b_1{\restriction } n)\in T$ . We then let $p[T]=\{ x\in {\mathbb {R}}: \exists f((x, f)\in [T])\}$ .

7 Solovay defined what is now called the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ (see [Reference Woodin61, Definition 9.23]). It is a closed sequence of ordinals with the largest element $\Theta $ , where $\Theta $ is the least ordinal that is not a surjective image of the reals. One then obtains a hierarchy of axioms by requiring that the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ has complex patterns. $\mathsf {LSA}$ is an axiom in this hierarchy. The reader may consult [Reference Sargsyan32] or [Reference Woodin61, Remark 9.28].

8 The requirement in these axioms that there is a strong cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals is only possible if $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}){\vDash } \mathsf {LSA}$ .

9 Unfortunately, the authors do not know a reference for this theorem of Woodin. But it can be proven via the methods of [Reference Larson23] and [Reference Steel47].

10 The exact condition is that club of countable Skolem hulls are generically correct.

11 $\mathsf {Sealing\ Dichotomy}$ is well known among inner model theorists; we do not mean that we were the first to notice it.

12 $lh(E)$ is the length of E’. We note that when discussing Mitchell-Steel extender models, $lh(E)$ is the cardinal successor of the natural length of E. The natural length of E is the supremum of generators of E. For more details, see [Reference Steel53].

13 Our goal here is to avoid philosophical discussions, but if we were to go in this direction, we would call this view approach to $\mathsf {IMPr}$ Steel’s Program.

14 In some contexts, $K^c$ theory can also be used. See [Reference Jensen, Schimmerling, Schindler and Steel13]. But solving $\mathsf {IMPr}$ via a $K^c$ theory will not, in general, provide such bridges between frameworks. The $K^c$ approach will not, in general, connect say $\mathsf {PFA}$ with the $\mathsf {Solovay\ Hierarchy}$ . See Conjecture 1.11.

15 For example, the reader may try to understand the meaning of $W^*_{\alpha }$ in [Reference Steel46].

16 This is the minimal transitive model W of $\mathsf {ZF}$ such that $V\subseteq W$ and ${\mathbb {R}}^*\in W$ . It can be shown that ${\mathbb {R}}^W={\mathbb {R}}^*$ .

17 This is the poset that collapses ${\kappa }$ to be countable.

18 This is the poset that collapses everything $<{\kappa }$ to be countable.

19 That this way of stating the desired closeness is natural is a consequence of several decades of research carried out on ${\mathrm {HOD}}$ of models of determinacy. See the fragment of the introduction titled HOD analysis.

20 In some cases, we work in $V[g]$ for $g\subseteq Coll(\omega ,\kappa )$ for some $\kappa $ . In other cases, we may work in $V[g]$ for $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\kappa )$ . Whether one does $\mathsf {CMI}$ at $\kappa $ or below $\kappa $ is hypothesis-dependent.

22 This is why we assume that $\kappa $ is a limit of strong cardinals, as this hypothesis implies what we stated.

23 This condition happens quite often.

24 Fix a pairing function $\pi :\Theta ^2\rightarrow \Theta $ . Given $A\subseteq \mathcal {C}({\mathcal { H}}^-)$ , we say A is a code if $M_A=(\Theta , E_A)$ is a well-founded model where $E_A\subseteq \Theta ^2$ is given by $({\alpha }, {\beta })\in E_A\iff \pi ({\alpha }, {\beta })\in A$ . If $A\in \mathcal {C}({\mathcal { H}}^-)$ is a code, then let ${\mathcal {M}}_A$ be the transitive collapse of $M_A$ . Then ${\mathcal { H}}$ is the union of models of the form ${\mathcal {M}}_A$ .

25 Recall that above we were doing CMI below ${\kappa }$ and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <{\kappa })$ . Also, $\kappa =\omega _1^{V[g]}$ .

26 In this case, $\mathcal {H}$ is defined in $V(\mathbb {R}^*)$ , where $\mathbb {R}^* = \bigcup _{\alpha <\kappa } \mathbb {R}^{V[h\cap Col(\omega ,\alpha )]}$ and $h\subseteq Coll(\omega ,<\kappa )$ is V-generic.

27 Example of $\phi (\gamma )$ is: ‘ $\gamma $ is a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals’.

28 ‘No Long Extender’

29 The exact theorem was that if ${\mathcal {P}}$ is an lsa type hod premouse, ${\delta }$ is the largest Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {P}}$ , ${\kappa }<{\delta }$ is the least $<{\delta }$ -strong cardinal that reflects the set of $<{\delta }$ -strong cardinals and $\mu $ is a $<{\delta }$ -strong cardinal larger than ${\kappa }$ . Then in ${\mathcal {P}}$ , $\mathsf {UB-Covering}$ must fail at $\mu $ . This theorem was presented at the Fourth European Set Theory Conference in Mon Sant Benet in 2013.

30 This proof of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 10.3.1] shows that the common part of a divergent models of $AD$ contains a minimal model of $\mathsf {LSA}$ .

31 This theorem is probably due to Woodin. The outline of the proof is as follows. By an unpublished theorem of Woodin (but see [Reference Sargsyan35, Theorem 1.9]), $\kappa $ is a measurable cardinal, as it is a regular cardinal. It follows that there is an $\omega $ -club C consisting of members of the Solovay sequence such that for all ${\lambda }\in C$ , ${\mathrm {HOD}}{\vDash } \text {`}{\lambda }$ is regular’. Hence, $L(\Gamma _{\lambda }, \mathbb {R}){\vDash } \text {`}\mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}} + {\lambda }=\Theta +\Theta $ is regular’. For the proof of the last inference see [Reference Caicedo, Larson, Sargsyan, Schindler, Steel and Zeman5, Theorem 2.3].

32 Thus, $\pi ^\Sigma _{{\mathcal {P}}, \infty }(\eta )={\kappa }$ .

33 $\Sigma $ must also satisfy some form of generic interpretability (i.e., there must be a way to interpret $\Sigma $ on the the generic extensions of ${\mathcal {M}}_1^{\#, \Sigma }$ ).

34 This can be proved by a $\Sigma ^2_1$ -reflection argument.

35 It follows from the theory of Suslin cardinals under $AD$ that ${\kappa }$ cannot be the largest Suslin cardinal; see [Reference Jackson10, Chapter 3].

36 The difference between a mouse and a mouse over y is the same as the difference between L and $L[x]$ .

37 ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_c$ is a direct limit along the models of c. ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {T}})$ is the largest initial segment of ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_c$ such that $Q(c, {\mathcal {T}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is a Woodin cardinal’. It is only defined provided that ${\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal for some function definable over ${\mathcal {M}}^{\mathcal {T}}_c$ .

38 $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}},b}$ is the restriction of the iteration embedding to ${\mathcal {P}}^b$ . See [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], just after Definition 2.7.21, for a more detailed definition. Note that in some cases, $\pi ^{{\mathcal {T}},b}$ may exist, but $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}$ may not.

39 One can then prove that there is such an ${\mathcal {N}}$ that projects to X.

40 This means that if $E\in \vec {E}^{\mathcal {M}}$ , then $\nu \not \in (\mathrm {crit }(E), index(E))$ .

41 This can be written as $\mathcal {J}_1({\mathcal {Q}}){\vDash } \text {`}{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ is not a Woodin cardinal’.

42 In general, the theory of ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures does not have much to do with sts mice. It will help if the reader develops some understanding of [Reference Steel53, Chapter 6.2 and Definition 6.11].

43 It is not up to us to decide whether $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})\in m(\Lambda )$ or $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})\in b(\Lambda )$ . The short-tree strategy itself decides this.

44 Simply because ‘being a pullback’ is a transitive property.

45 A non-tame hod premouse is one that has an extender overlapping a Woodin cardinal.

46 The definition of ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ appears in Definition 2.7. The fact that $\Lambda $ has branch condensation follows from generic interpretability. Because ${\mathcal {P}}|\xi {\vDash }$ ‘the generic interpretation of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ has branch condensation’, we have the same holds over ${\mathcal {N}}$ .

47 [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 3.1.8] introduces the short-tree component of an iteration strategy. Roughly speaking, $\Lambda ^{stc}({\mathcal {T}})=b$ if and only if letting $\Lambda ({\mathcal {T}})=c$ , either (i) $b=c$ , $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_c$ is undefined or $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_c({\delta }^{\mathcal {N}})>{\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ or (ii) $b={\mathrm m}^+({\mathcal {T}})$ and $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_c$ is defined and $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}}_c({\delta }^{\mathcal {N}})={\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ .

48 The proof of this clause is very similar to the proof of Lemma 2.11.

49 That is, $[0, lh({\mathcal {T}})-1]_{\mathcal {T}}\cap D^{\mathcal {T}}=\emptyset $ the final model iteration does not drop.

50 According to [Reference Neeman31, Theorem 4.9.1], the size of the poset that adds $\pi _i$ to ${\mathcal {P}}_i$ is less than the generators of ${\mathcal {U}}_{\leq {\mathcal {P}}_i}$ , which is contained in $\pi _i(\nu ^{s_i})$ .

51 ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ was introduced in Definition 2.7.

52 Suppose ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ is not $\Sigma $ -maximal and let ${\mathcal {U}}$ be the ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ -to- ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ tree. Let $b=\Sigma ({\mathcal {U}})$ . We then have that ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {U}})$ exists and so ${\mathcal {N}}_0$ could not be the final model of the fully backgrounded hod pair construction of ${\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^w[g]$ . It follows from the universality of the fully backgrounded constructions that continuing the construction further we will construct ${\mathcal {Q}}(b, {\mathcal {U}})$ . The reader may wish to consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 4].

53 p is a stack of two normal trees.

54 $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ is the internal strategy predicate of ${\mathcal {P}}$ , which by itself is not a total iteration strategy but can be uniquely extended to a total iteration strategy. By ‘ $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ -iterate’, we mean an iterate according to the total extension of $S^{\mathcal {P}}$ . The reader may consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 5].

55 Recall that by a result of Martin, Steel and Woodin for a $\lambda $ a limit of Woodins, $Hom_{<{\lambda }}$ coincides with the $<{\lambda }$ -universally Baire sets. See [Reference Steel47, Theorem 2.1] and [Reference Steel47, Chapter 2].

56 We will identify Code $(\Sigma )$ with $\Sigma $ itself in this paper.

57 There is only one such iteration ${\mathcal {T}}_{\xi }$ .

58 It is not correct to say that $\Sigma \in {\mathcal {P}}$ . The correct language is that $\Sigma $ is a definable class of ${\mathcal {P}}$ and $\Sigma ^g$ is a definable class of ${\mathcal {P}}[g]$ .

59 This is sometimes called the ‘old’ derived model. $D({\mathcal {M}},\lambda ,u)$ has the form $L(\mathbb {R}^*_u, Hom^*_u)$ , where $\mathbb {R}^*_u = \bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda } \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {M}}[u{\restriction } \alpha ]}$ and $Hom^*_u$ is the collection of $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}^*_u$ in ${\mathcal {M}}(\mathbb {R}^*_u)$ such that there are $< \lambda $ -complementing trees $T,U\in {\mathcal {M}}[u{\restriction } \beta ]$ for some $\beta <\lambda $ such that $p[T]^{{\mathcal {M}}(\mathbb {R}^*_u)} = A = \mathbb {R}^*_u - p[U]$ .

60 We take the ultrapower by $E_i$ to have more cutpoint Woodin cardinals.

61 Note that there is a generic $k'\subseteq Coll(\omega ,<\lambda )$ for ${\mathcal {M}}[x]$ such that $\mathbb {R}^*_k = \mathbb {R}^*_{k'}$ .

62 In ${\mathcal {P}}[g*h]$ , let $k\subseteq Coll(\omega ,\mathbb {R})$ be generic and let $(x_i : i<\omega )$ be the generic enumeration of the reals. The iteration i is the direct limit of the system $({\mathcal {M}}_m, i_{m,m+1}: m<\omega )$ , where ${\mathcal {M}}_0 = {\mathcal {M}}[x]$ , for each m, $i_{m,m+1}:{\mathcal {M}}_m \rightarrow {\mathcal {M}}_{m+1}$ is the $x_m$ -genericity iteration that makes $x_m$ generic at the image of $\delta _m$ .

63 The supremum of Wadge ranks of the sets of reals in $\Gamma ^b({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Lambda )$ .

64 $\mathbb {Q}_{<\delta }$ and $\mathbb {P}_{<\delta }$ are the countable and full stationary tower forcings.

65 Recall that Martin and Woodin showed that under ${\mathsf {AD}}$ , $\mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}$ is equivalent to the statement that every set of reals has a scale. See [Reference Martin and Woodin27]. Also, by results of Martin, Steel and Woodin, assuming class of Woodin cardinals, every uB set is determined. See [Reference Steel47].

66 In [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], $\mathbb {P} = Col(\omega ,\omega _2)$ , but in our case, since $\mu $ is measurable, all results in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 12] hold in our context. The point is that we can work with stationaraily many hulls $X\prec H_{\xi }$ for some $\xi>>\Omega $ such that $X\cap \mu =\gamma $ is an inaccessible cardinal, $X^{<\gamma }\subseteq X$ , and their corresponding uncollapse map $\pi _X: M_X\rightarrow H_{\xi }$ . Or equivalently, we work with the ultrapower embedding $j_U: V \rightarrow Ult(V,U)$ , noting that $j_U$ lifts to a generic elementary embedding on $V[G]$ . By results in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38], $\Sigma $ has strong branch condensation and is strongly $\Delta $ -fullness preserving.

67 And hence, a stationary class of measurable cardinals that are limits of Woodin cardinals.

68 This is a consequence of the proof of $\square $ . ${\mathcal {N}}$ is a direct limit of $({\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }, j_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}: {\alpha }<{\beta }, {\alpha }, {\beta }\in D)$ , where $D\subseteq Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}}$ is cofinal in $Ord\cap {\mathcal {M}}$ and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }{\trianglelefteq } {\mathcal {M}}$ .

69 Notice that this is the easy version of the proof of square; the construction of [Reference Jensen11] is all we need.

70 Below, we often confuse strategies with their interpretations in relevant generic extensions or in relevant inner models. However, in some cases, the distinction between the two strategies is important, and in those situations, we will either separate the two strategies or point out that the distinction is important.

71 Notice that $\Sigma _{Y_0}=\Psi $ .

72 That is, if ${\mathcal {S}}'{\trianglelefteq }^c_{hod}{\mathcal {S}}$ , then $(Y\cap j({\mathcal {P}}|{\delta }^{\mathcal {P}}))\not \subseteq {\mathrm rge}(\pi ^{\Phi }_{{\mathcal {S}}' \infty })$ . Complete layers are those layers ${\mathcal {S}}'$ of ${\mathcal {S}}$ for which ${\delta }^{{\mathcal {S}}'}$ is a Woodin cardinal of ${\mathcal {S}}$ or is a limit of Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {S}}$ .

73 For details, the reader may wish to check [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Theorem 9.2.6].

74 We confuse $\Pi $ with its extension to $N[g]$ . Similarly, we think of $\overline {\Pi }^+$ as a strategy in N as well as in $N[g]$ . Same comment applies below to $\overline {\Pi }$ and $\overline {\Phi }$ .

75 See proof of Claim 2 in the proof of [Reference Sargsyan33, Lemma 10.4].

76 This follows from the fact that $\Pi $ witnesses that ${\mathcal {P}}^+$ is a $\Psi $ -hod mouse and $m{\restriction } {\mathcal {P}}=id$ .

77 Because $\vert {\overline {{\mathcal {P}}^+}\vert }=\mu $ .

78 This is because (K) implies that ${\mathcal {N}}$ is ordinal definable in ${\mathcal {Q}}^+$ , and therefore, ${\mathcal {N}}\in {\mathcal {Q}}$ .

79 See Definition 5.1.

80 This is an instance of the Mouse Set Conjecture, which is not known in full generality. However, we are working towards establishing the equiconsistency in Theorem 1.4. But the target large cardinal is weak, and so Mouse Capturing holds in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ . See [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 10.2].

81 This condition follows from other conditions.

82 See [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 2.7.1]. ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is meek if either it has successor type or ${\mathcal {Q}}={\mathcal {Q}}^b$ . Otherwise, we say ${\mathcal {Q}}$ is non-meek.

83 A stack of normal iteration trees.

84 Thus, no normal component of ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}$ can be split into two normal components.

85 The embedding $\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}$ is defined similarly to $\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}, b}$ ; it is essentially the embedding $\pi ^{{\vec {\mathcal {T}}}}_{{\alpha }, {\beta }}{\restriction } {\mathcal {M}}_{\alpha }^b$ . See [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Chapter 2.8].

86 In the sense of [Reference Sargsyan34, Definition 1.30].

87 This in particular means that the strategy indexed on the sequence of ${\mathcal {M}}$ is a strategy for ${\mathcal {R}}$ .

88 That is, $R^{p_i}$ has a maximum element ${\alpha }$ and ${\mathcal {T}}_i=(p_i)_{\geq {\alpha }}$ .

89 Notice that in this case, there is a branch b such that ${\vec {\mathcal {T}}}^\frown \{b\}$ is correctly guided and Z-realizable.

90 See Definition 7.11.

91 See Definition 7.8.

92 Hence, ${\mathcal {M}}$ is not Z-validated.

93 Hence, p is not Z-validated.

94 See Definition 7.11 and Definition 7.2.

95 This is a consequence of the fact that $\vec {{\mathcal {V}}}$ is small.

96 See Definition 7.13.

97 This discussion shows that Z-approved ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structures are the same provided they are based on a $\#$ -type lsa hod premouse which is not infinitely descending.

98 See Definition 7.5.

99 l is specified as in Definition 9.2.

100 The proof of this fact is in Section 12; it shows that if a level ${\mathcal {S}}$ of the construction has no Woodin cardinals, then if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is a tree on ${\mathcal {S}}$ , then sufficently closed hulls of ${\mathcal {T}}$ will have branches determined by the pre-image of ${\mathcal {Q}}({\mathcal {T}})$ .

101 $\mathcal {C}({\mathcal {N}}_{\eta })$ is the core of ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }$ .

102 $<_{{\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }}$ is the canonical well-ordering of ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ .

103 This, in particular, implies that $b\in {\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ .

104 Recall the Internal Definability of Authentication. In this case of the construction, the branch b is chosen by a procedure internal to ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ and does not depend on any external factors. Because of this, proving Z-validity is not obvious at all. Also see the Anomaly in 3.b of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 4.2.1].

105 It is not hard to see that if ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ is Z-validated and ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }=\mathcal {J}_1({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta })$ , then ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }$ is Z-validated. It is possible that ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ is Z-validated but ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }$ is not, but these possibilities are covered by Break3 and Break4. Also notice that if ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }=({\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }, G)$ , where G is an extender and ${\mathcal {M}}_{\eta }$ is Z-validated, then ${\mathcal {N}}_{\eta }$ is Z-validated.

106 See Definition 9.4. Break4 is similar to the Anomaly in 3.b of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang38, Definition 4.2.1].

107 See Definition 8.1.

108 Here, ${\mathcal {T}}_U$ is a tree on ${\mathcal {W}}_U$ , but it is based on ${\mathcal {R}}_U$ .

109 As $\mathrm {crit }(i)>{\delta }(j({\mathcal {T}}_U))$ , $i(j({\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U)))=j({\mathcal {Q}}(b_U, {\mathcal {T}}_U))$ .

110 See Definition 9.12.

111 Note that there may not be any ${\mathcal {Q}}$ -structure for p.

112 The real reason for a failure of such constructions is failure of universality or solidity both of which are consequences of iterability.

113 ‘mo’ stands for the ‘Mitchell Order’.

114 Here and below, by $J[\vec {E}, \Sigma _i]$ , we mean the fully backgrounded construction relative to $\Sigma _i$ . $J[\vec {E}, \Sigma _i](A)$ is the aforementioned construction done over A.

115 There can be many such stacks.

116 Notice that ${\mathcal {Q}}(c, {\mathcal {U}})$ must exist as ${\mathcal {Q}}$ projects to ${\delta }({\mathcal {T}})$ .

117 The second author observes that assuming $\mathsf {PFA}$ and that there is a Woodin cardinal, there is a canonical model of $\mathsf {WLW}$ . The proof is not via CMI methods but just an observation that the full-backgrounded construction as done in [Reference Neeman31] reaches a model of $\mathsf {WLW}$ . The Woodin cardinal assumption is important here. The argument would not work if one assumes just $\mathsf {PFA}$ and/or a large cardinal milder than a Woodin cardinal (e.g., a measurable cardinal or a strong cardinal).

References

Adolf, D., ‘ $A{D}_{\mathbb{R}}+\theta$ is regular from choiceless patterns of singulars’, available at https://universalweasel.files.wordpress.com/2018/07/allsing.pdf.Google Scholar
Audrito, G. and Viale, M., ‘Absoluteness via resurrection’, J. Math. Log. 17(2) (2017), 1750005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baumgartner, J. E.. ‘Applications of the proper forcing axiom’, in Handbook of Set-Theoretic Topology (North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1984), 913959.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Becker, H. S. and Moschovakis, Y. N., ‘Measurable cardinals in playful models’, in Cabal Seminar 77–79 (Proc. Caltech-UCLA Logic Sem., 1977–79) (Lecture Notes in Math.) vol. 839 (Springer, Berlin, 1981), 203214.Google Scholar
Caicedo, A. E., Larson, P., Sargsyan, G., Schindler, R., Steel, J. and Zeman, M., ‘Square principles in ${\mathbb{P}}_{\mathrm{max}}$ extensions’, Israel J. Math. 217(1) (2017), 231261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feng, Q., Magidor, M. and Woodin, H., ‘Universally Baire sets of reals’, in Set Theory of the Continuum (Berkeley, CA, 1989) (Math. Sci. Res. Inst. Publ.) vol. 26 (Springer, New York, 1992), 203242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., Magidor, M. and Shelah, S., ‘Martin’s maximum, saturated ideals, and nonregular ultrafilters. I’, Ann. of Math. (2) 127(1) (1988), 147. 111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., Magidor, M. and Shelah, S., ‘Martin’s maximum, saturated ideals and nonregular ultrafilters. II’, Ann. of Math. (2) 127(3) (1988), 521545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hauser, K., ‘The consistency strength of projective absoluteness’, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 74(3) (1995), 245295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, S., ‘Structural consequences of AD’, in Handbook of Set Theory. Vols. 1, 2, 3 (Springer, Dordrecht, 2010), 17531876.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, R. B., ‘The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy’, Ann. Math. Logic 4 (1972), 229308. With a section by Jack Silver.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, R., ‘Inner models and large cardinals’, Bull. Symb. Log. 1(4) (195), 393407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, R., Schimmerling, E., Schindler, R. and Steel, J., ‘Stacking mice’, J. Symb. Log. 74(01) (2009), 315335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R. and Woodin, W. H., ‘HOD as a core model’, in Kechris, A. S., Löwe, B. and Steel, J. R., eds., Ordinal Definability and Recursion Theory: The Cabal Seminar, Volume III (Cambridge University Press, 2016), 257346.Google Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Martin, D. A. and Moschovakis, Y. N., eds., Cabal Seminar 79–81 (Lecture Notes in Mathematics) vol. 1019 (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1983).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Martin, D. A. and Steel, J. R., eds., Cabal Seminar 81–85 (Lecture Notes in Mathematics) vol. 1333 (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1988).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Löwe, B. and Steel, J. R., eds., Games, Scales, and Suslin Cardinals. The Cabal Seminar. Vol. I (Lecture Notes in Logic) vol. 31 (Association for Symbolic Logic, Chicago, IL; Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Löwe, B. and Steel, J. R., eds., Wadge Degrees and Projective Ordinals. The Cabal Seminar. Volume II (Lecture Notes in Logic) vol. 37 (Association for Symbolic Logic, La Jolla, CA; Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Löwe, B. and Steel, J. R., eds., Ordinal Definability and Recursion Theory. The Cabal Seminar. Vol. III (Lecture Notes in Logic) vol. 43 (Association for Symbolic Logic, Ithaca, NY; Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2016). Including reprinted papers from the Caltech-UCLA Cabal seminars held in Los Angeles, CA.Google Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Martin, D. A. and Moschovakis, Y. N., eds., Cabal Seminar 77–79 (Lecture Notes in Mathematics) vol. 839 (Springer, Berlin, 1981).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S. and Moschovakis, Y. N., eds., Cabal Seminar 76–77 (Lecture Notes in Mathematics) vol. 689 (Springer, Berlin, 1978).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Neal Ketchersid, R., ‘Toward $A{D}_{\mathbb{R}}$ from the continuum hypothesis and an ω1-dense ideal’, PhD Thesis, University of California, Berkeley. ProQuest LLC, Ann Arbor, MI, 2000.Google Scholar
Larson, P. B., The Stationary Tower (University Lecture Series) vol. 32 (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2004). Notes on a course by W. Hugh Woodin.Google Scholar
Martin, D. A. and Solovay, R. M., ‘Internal Cohen extensions’, Ann. Math. Logic 2(2) (1970), 143178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, D. A. and Steel, J. R., ‘Iteration trees’, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 7(1) (1994), 173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, D. A. and Steel, J. R., ‘Projective determinacy’, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA 85(18) (1988), 65826586.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Martin, D. A. and Woodin, W. H., ‘Weakly homogeneous trees’, in Games, Scales, and Suslin Cardinals. The Cabal Seminar. Vol. I (Lect. Notes Log.) vol. 31 (Assoc. Symbol. Logic, Chicago, IL, 2008), 421438.Google Scholar
Mitchell, W. J. and Steel, J. R., Fine Structure and Iteration Trees (Lecture Notes in Logic) vol. 3 (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moschovakis, Y. N., ‘Ordinal games and playful models’, in Cabal Seminar 77–79 (Proc. Caltech-UCLA Logic Sem., 1977–79) (Lecture Notes in Math) vol. 839 (Springer, Berlin-New York, 1981), 169201.Google Scholar
Neeman, I., ‘Optimal proofs of determinacy’, Bull. Symb. Log. 1(3) (1995), 327339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neeman, I., ‘Inner models in the region of a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals’, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 116(1–3) (2002), 67155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G., ‘Descriptive inner model theory’, Bull. Symb. Log. 19(1) (2013), 155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G., ‘Covering with universally Baire operators’, Adv. Math. 268 (2015), 603665.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G., Hod Mice and the Mouse Set Conjecture (Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society) vol. 236 (American Mathematical Society, 2015).Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G., ‘AD ${}_{\mathbb{R}}$ implies that all sets of reals are θ universally Baire’, Arch. Math. Logic 60(1–2) (2021), 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G., ‘Covering with Chang models over derived models’, Adv. Math. 384 (2021), 21. Id/No 107717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G., ‘Negative results on precipitous ideals on ω1’, J. Symb. Log (2022), 1–20.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., ‘The largest Suslin axiom’, available at https://arxiv.org/abs/2112.04396.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., ‘Non-tame mice from tame failures of the unique branch hypothesis’, Canad. J. Math. 66(4) (2014), 903923.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., ‘A core model induction past the largest suslin axiom’, 2019. In preparation.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., ‘Sealing from iterability’, Trans. Am. Math. Soc., Ser. B 8 (2021), 229248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schimmerling, E., ‘The ABC’s of mice’, Bull. Symb. Log. 7(4) (2001), 485503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlutzenberg, F. and Trang, N., ‘The fine structure of operator mice’, 2016, submitted, available at https://sites.google.com/site/schlutzenberg/home-1/research/papers-and-preprints.Google Scholar
Schlutzenberg, F. and Trang, N., ‘Scales in hybrid mice over $\mathbb{R}$ ’, 2016, submitted, available at math.uci.edu/~ntrang.Google Scholar
Shoenfield, J. R., ‘The problem of predicativity’, in Essays on the Foundations of Mathematics (Magnes Press, Hebrew Univ., Jerusalem, 1961), 132139.Google Scholar
Steel, J. R., ‘PFA implies ADL(R)’, J. Symb. Log. 70(4) (2005), 12551296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., ‘The derived model theorem’, in Logic Colloquium 2006 (Lect. Notes Log.) vol. 32 (Assoc. Symbol. Logic, Chicago, IL, 2009), 280327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R. and Schindler, R. D., ‘The core model induction’, available at https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/.Google Scholar
Steel, J. R., The Core Model Iterability Problem (Lecture Notes in Logic) vol. 8 (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R, ‘Core models with more Woodin cardinals’, J. Symb. Log. 67(3) (2002), 11971226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., ‘Local ${K}^c$ constructions’, 2003, available at math.berkeley.edu/~steel/papers/Publications.html.Google Scholar
Steel, J. R., ‘Derived models associated to mice’, in Computational Prospects of Infinity. Part I. Tutorials (Lect. Notes Ser. Inst. Math. Sci. Natl. Univ. Singap.) vol. 14 (World Sci. Publ., Hackensack, NJ, 2008), 105193. Available at author’s website.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R, ‘An outline of inner model theory’, in Handbook of Set Theory (2010), 15951684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., ‘Gödel’s program’, in Interpreting Gödel (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 2014), 153179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., A Comparison Process for Mouse Pairs (Lect. Notes Log.) vol. 51 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Ithaca, NY: Association for Symbolic Logic (ASL), 2023).Google Scholar
Todorcevic, S., ‘Generic absoluteness and the continuum’, Math. Res. Lett. 9(4) (2002), 465471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trang, N., ‘ $PFA$ and guessing models’, Israel J. Math. 215 (2016), 607667. Available at www.math.unt.edu/~ntrang/.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viale, M., ‘Category forcings, MM ${}^{+++}$ , and generic absoluteness for the theory of strong forcing axioms’, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 29(3) (2016), 675728.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, T. M., ‘Universally Baire sets and generic absoluteness’, J. Symb. Log. 82(4) (2017), 12291251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodin, H., ‘Iteration hypotheses and the strong sealing of universally Baire sets’, 2018. Slides from Reflections on Set Theoretic Reflection, available at http://www.ub.edu/RSTR2018/slides.htm.Google Scholar
Woodin, W. H., The Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, and the Nonstationary Ideal (De Gruyter Series in Logic and its Applications) vol. 1, revised edn. (Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodin, W. H., ‘In search of Ultimate- $L$ : the 19th Midrasha Mathematicae Lectures’, Bull. Symb. Log. 23(1) (2017), 1109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhu, Y., ‘Realizing an ${}^{+}$ model as a derived model of a premouse’, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 166(12) (2015), 12751364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar