from Part 5 - Citizenship, Participation, and Punishment
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 12 July 2019
In his book Equality, Stuart White points out that political equality in a democracy is a response to a particular condition of all states: all political systems are “systems of command” and, inevitably, some people have the power to give binding commands to subjects because they have authority as officials within the state. Political equality becomes the distinctive characteristic of democratic political systems, White points out, in that it gives each citizen equal power to issue binding commands within the system of domination in the state. And it does so most basically by giving each citizen one vote and an equal right to participate through free expression and association (White 2007, 25–26). Simply put then, political equality exists when the citizens are equal in exercising the authority to give commands to the state under which they are also equals as subjects.
What renders this aspect of political equality complicated is the fact that there is a built-in tension in this simple definition, a tension that is at once conceptual and political-sociological. The citizens of a democracy are ostensibly equal with regard to giving commands to the state through authorizing legislation, but the state can only give commands if it has sufficient power over the subjects, that is, it has sufficient domination, to impose these commands on all citizens. So if legitimacy in a democracy depends on political equality and popular sovereignty, the power of citizens and the domination necessary to realize this power will always be in tension—unless these politically equal citizens identify with the commands the state gives as their commands. The problem this poses for both the theory and practice of democracy is how to relate the horizontal relations of equal citizens to one another in the exercise of popular sovereignty to the government's vertical exercise of power so that the latter does not undermine the former.
This most fundamental problem in democratic theory was first explicitly articulated by Rousseau. However, it was Alexis de Tocqueville—an avid reader of the Social Contract and The Discourse on the Origins of Inequality—who adapted it to the complex conditions of modern politics in an age of equality.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.