Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-08T14:44:18.998Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 5 - Stem cells: what’s all the fuss about?

from PART II - Beginning of life

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Anthony Fisher
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Sydney
Get access

Summary

Whose stem cells?

Removing restrictions on federal funding of embryonic stem cell research was a priority for the Obama administration. This was a major policy shift, hailed as evidence of the President’s commitment to science and progress. Why the fuss about these tiny human cells? Because stem cells are said to be the ‘holy grail’ of regenerative medicine. Ordinary cells are of specific types, such as nerves, skin, heart muscle or other kinds, and can make only more of the same (‘unipotency’). Stem cells, by contrast, are relatively undifferentiated, having the prolonged capacity to multiply and, depending upon circumstances, to differentiate into various cell-types as needed (‘pluripotency’). Thus stem cells can regenerate damaged tissues: their therapeutic potential is enormous.

There are six potential sources for these stem cells currently ‘on the table’: human tissues where stem cells naturally occur; the placenta; other cells which can be reprogrammed to behave as stem cells; pseudo-human organisms; animal–human hybrids; and, finally, human embryos. I consider each in turn. The first is the natural source, used by the body itself since time began and by medicine for the past few decades. These are called somatic or adult stem cells, though they can in fact be taken from people of all ages, not merely adults. Stem cells have been found in almost every body tissue, such as skin, muscle, fat, bone marrow, blood, major organs, brain, nerves, ear, nose and mouth. Sometimes these cells can be derived from the intended recipient, avoiding any immune-rejection difficulties. At other times they are taken from donors. In each case these stem cells are derived without harming anyone and are, in the view of the Catholic Church and many others, far preferable ethically to other routes proposed for deriving stem cells.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

President’s Council on BioethicsAlternative Sources of Human Pluripotent Stem CellsWashington, DC 2005Google Scholar
Clarke, D. L.Generalized potential of adult neural stem cellsScience 288 2000 1660CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Howell, J. C.Pluripotent stem cells identified in multiple murine tissuesAnn New York Acad Sci 996 2003 158CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Preston, S. L.The new stem cell biology: something for everyoneMol Pathol 56 2003 86CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Southern Cross Bioethics InstituteBriefing Note on Stem CellsAdelaideSCBI 2005Google Scholar
Westphal, S. P.Ultimate stem cell discoveredNew Scientist 41 2008 85Google Scholar
Syrjala, K.Late effects of hematopoietic cell transplantation among 10-year adult survivors compared with case-matched controlsJ Clinical Oncology 23 2005 6596CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Burt, RichardClinical applications of blood-derived and marrow-derived stem cells for non-malignant diseasesJAMA 299 2008 925CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miranda, GonzaloThe Stem Cell Dilemma: For the Good of All Human Beings?BoncourtFoundation Guilé 2002Google Scholar
Prentice, David 2009
Southern Cross Bioethics InstituteBriefing Note on Stem CellsAdelaideSCBI 2005 www.i-sis.org.uk/HUASC.phpwww.stemcellresearch.orgwww.clinicaltrials.govGoogle Scholar
Carey, B.Reprogramming of murine and human somatic cells using a single polycistronic vectorProc Nat Acad Sci 106 2008 157CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henderson, J. T.Lazarus’ gate: challenges and potential of epigenetic reprogramming of somatic cellsClinical Pharm Therapeutics 83 2008 889CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakagawa, M.Generation of induced pluripotent stem cells without Myc from mouse and human fibroblastsNature Biotechnology 26 2008 101CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nishikawa, S.The promise of human induced pluripotent stem cells for research and therapyNature Reviews Molecular Cell Biology 9 2008 725CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Okita, K.Generation of germline-competent induced pluripotent stem cellsNature 448 2007 313CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Park, I.-H.Reprogramming of human somatic cells to pluripotency with defined factorsNature 451 2008 141CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Takahashi, K.Induction of pluripotent stem cells from adult human fibroblasts by defined factorsCell 131 2007 1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wernig, M.In vitro reprogramming of fibroblasts into a pluripotent ES-cell-like stateNature 448 2007 318CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yamanaka, S.Induction of pluripotent stem cells from mouse fibroblasts by four transcription factorsCell Proliferation 41 2008 51CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levin, Y.Bioetech: what to expectFirst Things 191 2009 17Google Scholar
Aarkes, H.Production of pluripotent stem cells by oocyte-assisted reprogramming: with signatoriesNCBQ 5 2005 579Google Scholar
Condic, M.Alternative sources of pluripotent stem cells: altered nuclear transferCell Proliferation 41 2008 7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hurlbut, W. B.Altered nuclear transfer as a morally acceptable means for the procurement of human embryonic stem cellsAlternative Sources and NCBQ 5 2005 145Google ScholarPubMed
President’s Council on BioethicsThe moral retrieval of ES cellsEthics & Medics 30 2005 1Google Scholar
Breveni, T. A.Gandolfi, F.Parthenotes as a source of embryonic stem cellsCell Proliferation 41 2008 20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, J. A.Embryonic stem cell lines derived from human blastocystsScience 282 1998 1145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cervantes, R. B.Embryonic stem cells and somatic cells differ in mutation frequency and typeProc Nat Acad Sci 99 2002 3586CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Condic, M.What we know about embryonic stem cellsFirst Things 169 2007 25Google Scholar
Maitra, A.Genomic alterations in cultured human embryonic stem cellsNature Genetics 37 2005 1099CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scolding, N.Stem-cell therapy: hope and hypeThe Lancet 365 2005 9477CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sherley, J. L.Human embryonic stem cell research: no way around a scientific bottleneckJ Biomed Biotech 2 2004 71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Condic, M.Getting stem cells rightFirst Things 180 2008 10Google Scholar
Doerflinger, R.The problem of deception in embryonic stem cell researchCell Proliferation 41 2008 65CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Healy, B. 2009
2005
Shenfield, F.Semantics and ethics of human embryonic stem-cell researchThe Lancet 365 2005 9477CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, J. W.Of stem cells and fairy talesDaily Standard 2004Google Scholar
Torda, A.Stem-cell hard sell gets ahead of itselfSydney Morning Herald 2004Google Scholar
Alberts, BruceMolecular Biology of the CellNew YorkGarland 2008Google Scholar
Anderson, D. M.Mosby’s Medical DictionarySt. LouisMosby 2009Google Scholar
Arey, L. B.Developmental AnatomyPhiladelphiaSaunders 1974Google Scholar
Brookes, M.Zietman, A.Clinical EmbryologyFloridaCRC 1998Google Scholar
Carlson, BruceHuman Embryology and Developmental BiologySt. LouisMosby 1999Google Scholar
Colombo, R.The Human Embryo before ImplantationLibreria Editrice Vaticana 2007Google Scholar
Condic, M.When Does Human Life Begin? A Scientific PerspectiveThornwood, NYWestchester Institute 2008Google Scholar
Hamilton, W. J.Mossman, H. W.Human EmbryologyCambridgeW. Heffer 1972CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irving, DianneThe impact of scientific misinformation on other fields: philosophy, theology, biomedical ethics, public policyAccountability in Research 2 1993 243CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Irving, D.The Human Development Hoax: Time to Tell The Truth!Clinton, MIGold Leaf 1997Google Scholar
Kischer, C. W.When does human life begin? The final answerLQ 70 2003 326Google ScholarPubMed
Larsen, W.Essentials of Human EmbryologyNew YorkChurchill Livingstone 1998Google Scholar
Larsen, W.Human EmbryologyNew YorkChurchill Livingstone 2001Google Scholar
Moore, K.Persaud, T. V.The Developing Human: Clinically Oriented EmbryologyPhiladelphiaSaunders/Elsevier 2008Google Scholar
O’Rahilly, R.Müller, F.Human Embryology and TeratologyNew YorkJohn Wiley 2001Google Scholar
Patten, B. M.Carlson, B. M.Foundations of EmbryologyNew YorkMcGraw-Hill 2002Google Scholar
Pearson, H.Developmental biology: your destiny, from day oneNature 418 2002 1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Serra, A.Colombo, R.Identity and Status of the Human EmbryoLibreria Editrice Vaticana 1998Google Scholar
Sweeney, L.Basic Concepts in EmbryologyNew YorkMcGraw-Hill 1998Google Scholar
Yanagimachi, R.The Physiology of ReproductionNew YorkRaven 1988Google Scholar
Benedict, 2006
John, 1961
Benedict, 2010
Benedict, 2005
Benedict, 2006
CDF 1987
Ratzinger, JosephGod and the WorldSan FranciscoIgnatius 2002Google Scholar
Benedict, 2008
US Conference of Catholic BishopsOn Embryonic Stem Cell ResearchWashington, DCUSCCB 2008Google Scholar
US Conference of Catholic Bishops Secretariat of Pro-Life ActivitiesStem Cell Research and Human Cloning: Questions and AnswersWashington, DCUSCCB 2008Google Scholar
Bishops’, CatholicParish Resource Pack to Raise Awareness about the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Bill, Including Possible Changes to the Law on AbortionLondonCBCEW 2007Google Scholar
Kass, L.The wisdom of repugnanceNew Republic 216 1997 17Google ScholarPubMed
Hwang, W. S.Evidence of a pluripotent human embryonic stem cell line derived from a cloned blastocystScience 303 2004 1669CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Walsh, B.A cloning cover-upTime 2007 7Google Scholar
President’s Council on BioethicsHuman Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical InquiryWashington, DCPCB 2002Google Scholar
Ashley, B.deBlois, J.O’Rourke, K.Health Care Ethics: A Catholic Theological AnalysisWashington, DCGeorgetown University Press 2006Google Scholar
Colson, C.Cameron, N.Human Dignity in the Biotech CenturyDowners Grove, ILInterVarsity 2004Google Scholar
Fitzgerald, K.Health Care Ethics: Critical Issues for the 21st CenturyGaithersburg, MDAspen 1998Google Scholar
Leies, J.Handbook on Critical Life IssuesBostonNCBC 2004Google Scholar
McConnaha, S.Blessed are the pluripotent: New Testament guidance for the embryonic stem cell debateNCBQ 5 2005 707Google ScholarPubMed
May, W. E.Catholic Bioethics and the Gift of Human LifeHuntington, INOur Sunday Visitor 2008Google Scholar
Pacholczyk, T.Live the Truth: The Moral Legacy of John Paul II in Catholic Health CarePhiladelphiaNCBC 2006Google Scholar
Pence, G.Flesh of My Flesh: The Ethics of Cloning HumansLanham, MDRowman and Littlefield 1998Google Scholar
Tobin, B.Gleeson, G.The embryo stem cell debateCMQ 54 2003 8Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×