Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-05-15T00:22:39.548Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Opponent Processing, Linear Models, and the Veridicality of Color Perception

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2010

Zoltán Jakab
Affiliation:
Békésy Postdoctoral Fellow, Budapest University of Technology and Economics
Andrew Brook
Affiliation:
Carleton University, Ottawa
Kathleen Akins
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
Get access

Summary

Two Contrasting Intuitions About Color

In roughly the last 15 years, it has become increasingly clear that philosophy and color science have some conflicting views about the nature of color. A philosophical view of color emerged in color science more or less as a collateral effect of the practice in that discipline. In philosophy first arose the need to precisely formulate what many believed was the commonsense view of color. This did happen, and later on the theory became a crucial part of a rather popular theory of mind. Other philosophers, however, were more interested in rigorously framing the view that they saw emerging from color science. Let us take a first look at the two approaches.

It seems to be a fairly widely held view among color scientists that color is at least as much “in the eye of the beholder” as on the surfaces of objects or in the light reaching our retinas. In other words, features of our color experience are crucially determined, and correspondingly explained, by the neuronal processing in our visual systems, as opposed to the environmental properties themselves that are the canonical causes of color experience. There exist, to be sure, color stimuli, or “physical colors,” that reliably and predictably evoke experiences as of color. However, color science has been taken by certain philosophers and color scientists to suggest that these stimuli offer little help in understanding the nature of color experience.

Type
Chapter
Information
Cognition and the Brain
The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement
, pp. 336 - 378
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akins, K. (1996). Of Sensory Systems and the “Aboutness” of Mental States. Journal of Philosophy, 93, 337–372CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Akins, K., and Hahn, M. (2000). The Peculiarity of Color. In Davis, Steven (Ed.): Color Perception: Philosophical, Psychological, Artistic and Computational Perspectives. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Ayama, M., Nakatsue, T., and Kaiser, P. K. (1987). Constant hue loci of unique and binary balanced hues at 10, 100, and 1000 Td. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 4, 1136–1144CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Block, N. (1997). Inverted Earth. In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (Eds.): The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Block, N. (1999). Sexism, racism, ageism, and the nature of consciousness. Philosophical Topics, 26 (1–2), 39–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (Eds.) (1997). The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Bradley, P., and Tye, M. (2001). Of colors, kestrels, caterpillars and leaves. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 469–487CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brainard, D. H., and Wandell, B. A. (1986). Analysis of the retinex theory of color vision. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 3, 1651–1661CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Byrne, A., and Hilbert, D. R. (2003). Color realism and color science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 3–64Google ScholarPubMed
Byrne, A., and Hilbert, D. R. (Eds.) (1997). Readings on Color, Vol. 1. The Philosophy of Color. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Campbell, J. (1997). A Simple View of Color. In Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R. (Eds.): Readings on Color, Vol. 1. The Philosophy of Color. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 177–190Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. (1997). Externalism and Experience. In Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Güzeldere, Güven (Eds.): The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, BrownGoogle Scholar
DeValois, R. L., and DeValois K. K. (1997). Neural Coding of Color. In Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R. (Eds.): Readings on Color, Vol. 2. The Science of Color. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 93–140Google Scholar
DeValois, R. L., Smith, C. J., Kitai, S. T., and Karoly, S. J. (1958). Responses of single cells in different layers of the primate lateral geniculate nucleus to monochromatic light. Science, 127, 238–239CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diamond, S. (Ed.) (1974). The Roots of Psychology. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Fairchild, M. D. (1998). Color Appearance Models. Reading, Mass.: Addison-WesleyGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, O. (1992). Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1990). Why Should the Mind Be Modular? In Fodor, J., A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow. Indianapolis: HackettGoogle Scholar
Haugeland, J. (1978). The nature and plausibility of cognitivism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 2, 215–260. Also in John Haugeland (Ed.): Mind Design. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1981, 1–34
Helmholtz, H. ⅴ. (1911). Physiological Optics, 3d ed., vol. 2. Ed. J. P. C. Southall, Optical Society of America, Rochester (1924). Reprinted, New York: Dover, 1962
Hilbert, D. R. (1987). Color and Color Perception: A Study in Anthropocentric Realism. Stanford, Calif.: Center for the Study of Language and InformationGoogle Scholar
Hilbert, D. R. (1992). What is color vision? Philosophical Studies, 68, 351–370CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilbert, D. R., and Kalderon M. E. (2000). Color and the Inverted Spectrum. In Davis, Steven (Ed.): Color Perception: Philosophical, Psychological, Artistic and Computational Perspectives. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Hunt, R. G. W. (1982). A model of colour vision for predicting colour appearance. Color Research and Application, 7 (2), 95–112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurvich, L. M. (1981). Color Vision. Sunderland, Mass.: Sinauer AssociatesGoogle Scholar
Hurvich, L. M. (1997). Chromatic and Achromatic Response Functions. In Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R. (Eds.): Readings on Color, Vol. 2. The Science of Color. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 67–91Google Scholar
Hurvich, L. M., and Jameson, D. (1955). Some quantitative aspects of an opponent-colors theory. II. Brightness, saturation, and hue in normal and dichromatic vision. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 45, 602–616CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ikeda, M., and Uehira, I. (1989). Unique hue loci and implications. Color Research and Application, 14, 318–324CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Indow, T. (1988). Multidimensional studies of Munsell solid. Psychological Review, 95 (4), 456–470CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Indow, T., and Aoki, N. (1983). Multidimensional mapping 178 Munsell colors. Color Research and Application, 5 (3), 145–152CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Izmailov, C. A., and Sokolov, E. N. (1991). Spherical model of color and brightness discrimination. Psychological Science, 2 (4), 249–259CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. (2000). Philosophizing About Color. In Davis, Steven (Ed.): Color Perception: Philosophical, Psychological, Artistic and Computational Perspectives. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F., and Pargetter, R. (1997). An Objectivist's Guide to Subjectivism About Color. In Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R. (Eds.): Readings on Color, Vol. 1. The Philosophy of Color. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 67–79Google Scholar
Jakab, Z. (2001). Color experience: Empirical evidence against representational externalism. Ph.D. thesis, Carleton University, Ottawa. Available at: http://www.carleton.ca/iis/TechReports
Jakab, Z. (2003). For a truly colored world: Review of Michael Tye: Consciousness, Color, and Content (MIT Press, 2000). Color Research and Application, 28 (5), 384–391CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jakab, Z., and McLaughlin, B. (2003). Why not color physicalism without color absolutism? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26 (1), 34–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jameson, D., and Hurvich, L. M. (1955). Some quantitative aspects of an opponent-colors theory: I. Chromatic responses and spectral saturation. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 45, 546–552CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jameson, D., and Hurvich, L. M. (1968). Opponent-response functions related to measured cone photopigments. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 58, 429–430CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jameson, K., and D'Andrade, R. (1997). It's Not Really Red, Green, Yellow, Blue: An Inquiry into Perceptual Color Space. In Hardin, C. L. and Maffi, Luisa (Eds.): Color Categories in Thought and Language. New York: Cambridge University Press, 295–319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judd, D. B. (1967). Interval scales, ratio scales, and additive for the sizes of differences perceived between members of geodesic series. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 57, 380–386CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirk, R. (1994). Raw Feeling. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Kuehni, R. G. (2000). Uniform color space modeled with cone responses. Color Research and Application, 25 (1), 56–633.0.CO;2-9>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuehni, R. G. (2001). Determination of unique hues using Munsell color chips. Color Research and Application, 26 (1), 61–663.0.CO;2-P>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Land, E. H. (1977). The retinex theory of color vision. Scientific American, 237 (6), 108–128CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Laxar, K., Miller, D. L., and Wooten, B. R. (1988). Long-term variability in the spectral loci of unique blue and unique yellow. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 5, 1983–1985CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacAdam, D. L. (1997). The Physical Basis of Color Specification. In Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R. (Eds.): Readings on Color, Vol. 2. The Science of Color. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 33–63Google Scholar
Maloney, L. T. (1986). Evaluation of linear models of surface spectral reflectance with small numbers of parameters. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 3 (10), 1673–1683CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maloney, L. T. (1999). Physics-based models of surface color perception. In Gegenfurtner, K. R. and Sharpe, L. T. (Eds.): Color Vision: From Genes to Perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 387–418Google Scholar
Maloney, L. T. (2002). Illuminant estimation as cue combination. Journal of Vision, 2, 493–504CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maloney, L. T. (2003). Surface Color Perception and Environmental Constraints. In Mausfeld, R. and Heyer, D. (Eds.): Colour Vision: From Light to Object. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Maloney, L. T., and Wandell, B. A. (1986). Color constancy: A method for recovering surface reflectance. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 3 (1, January), 29–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maloney, L. T., and Yang, J. N. (2003). Maximum likelihood difference scaling. Journal of Vision, 3 (8), 573–585CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Matthen, M. (1988). Biological functions and perceptual content. Journal of Philosophy, 85 (1), 5–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthen, M. (1999). The Disunity of Color. Philosophical Review, 108 (1), 47–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthen, M. (2001). What colors? Whose colors? Consciousness and Cognition, 10 (1), 117–124CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Matthen, M., and Levy, E. (1984). Teleology, error, and the human immune system. Journal of Philosophy, 81 (7), 351–372CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCann, J. J., McKee, S. P., and Taylor, T. H. (1976). Quantitative studies in retinex theory: A comparison between theoretical predictions and observer responses to the “Color Mondrian” experiments. Vision Research, 16, 445–458CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, B. (1995). Disposition. In Kim, Jaegwon and Sosa, Ernest (Eds.): A Companion to Metaphysics. Oxford and Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell, 121–124CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, B. P. (2003). Color, Consciousness, and Color Consciousness. In Smith, Quentin (Ed.): New Essays on Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 97–152Google Scholar
MacLeod, D. I. A., and Boynton, R. M. (1979). Chromaticity diagram showing cone excitations by stimuli of equal luminance. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 69, 1183–1186CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meyer, G. W. (1988). Wavelength selection for synthetic image generation. Computer Vision, Graphics, and Image Processing, 41, 57–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Müller, J. (1826a). Zur vergleichenden Physiologie des Geichtssinnes des Menschen und der Thiere. Leipzig: CnoblochGoogle Scholar
Müller, J. (1826b). Über die phantastischen Geichtserscheinungen (On Visual Fantasy Phenomena). Coblenz (pp ⅲ–ⅳ; 4–7; 33–35)Google Scholar
Müller, J. (1833–1837). Handbuch der Physiologie des Menschen, 2 vols. Coblenz: Holscher. (Translated by William Baly as Elements of Physiology, 2 vols. London, 1838–1842.)Google Scholar
Müller, J. (1843). Elements of Physiology, Vol. 2. Philadelphia: Lea and Blanchard, Book 5, parts 1–8Google Scholar
Pisoni, D. B. (1973). Auditory and phonetic memory codes in the discrimination of consonants and vowels. Perception and Psychophysics, 13 (2), 253–260CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pisoni, D. B., and Lazarus, J. H. (1974). Categorical and noncategorical modes of speech perception along the voicing continuum. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 55 (2), 328–333CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pisoni, D. B., and Tash, J. (1974). Reaction times to comparisons within and across phonetic categories. Perception and Psychophysics, 15 (2), 285–290CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Raffman, D. (1995). On the Persistence of Phenomenology. In Metzinger, Thomas (Ed.): Conscious Experience. Thoverton, UK: Imprint Academic, 293–308Google Scholar
Sekuler, R., and Blake, R. (2002). Perception. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Shepard, R. N. (1997). The Perceptual Organization of Colors: An Adaptation to Regularities of the Terrestrial World? In Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R. (Eds.): Readings on Color, Vol. 2. The Science of Color. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 311–356Google Scholar
Sivik, L. (1997). Color Systems for Cognitive Research. In Hardin, C. L. and Maffi, Luisa (Eds.): Color Categories in Thought and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 163–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sternheim, C. E., and Boynton, R. M. (1966). Uniqueness of perceived hues investigated with a continuous judgmental technique. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 72, 770–776CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stiles, W. S. (1961). Adaptation, chromatic adaptation, colour transformation. Anales Real Soc. Espan. Fis. Quim., Series A, 57, 149–175Google Scholar
Stroud, B. (2000). The Quest for Reality – Subjectivism and the Metaphysics of Color. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Takasaki, H. (1966). Lightness change of grays induced by change in reflectance of gray background. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 56, 504–509CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thompson, E. (1995). Colour Vision: A Study in Cognitive Science and the Philosophy of Perception. London and New York: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E. (2000). Comparative Color Vision: Quality Space and Visual Ecology. In Davis, Steven (Ed.): Color Perception: Philosophical, Psychological, Artistic and Computational Perspectives. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E., Palacios, A. G., and Varela, F. J. (1992). Ways of coloring: Comparative color vision as a case study for cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 1–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. (1995). Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Wandell, B. A. (1995). Foundations of Vision. Sunderland, Mass.: Sinauer AssociatesGoogle Scholar
Werner, J. S., and Wooten, B. R. (1979). Opponent chromatic mechanisms: Relation to photopigments and hue naming. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 69, 422–434CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Westland, S., and Thomson, M. (1999). Spectral Colour Statistics of Surfaces: Recovery and Representation. Derby: Colour & Imaging Institute, Kingsway House East, Derby UniversityGoogle Scholar
Whittle, P. (1992). Brightness, discriminability, and the “Crispening Effect.”Vision Research, 32, 1493–1507CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wuerger, S. M., Maloney, L. T., and Krauskopf, J. (1995). Proximity judgments in color space: Tests of a Euclidean color geometry. Vision Research, 35 (6), 827–835CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wyszecki, G., and Stiles, W. S. (1982). Color Science: Concepts and Methods, Quantitative Data and Formulae. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Wyszecki, G., and Stiles, W. S. (2000). Color Science: Concepts and Methods, Quantitative Data and Formulae. 2d ed. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Young, T. (1802). On the theory of light and colors. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond., 92, 12–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×