Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T16:05:05.352Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Constitutionalism without Supermajorities

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Melissa Schwartzberg
Affiliation:
New York University
Get access

Summary

Although supermajority rules originally emerged as an alternative to unanimity to address the risk of human fallibility, in the modern era, supermajority rules are typically used to remedy the risks associated with unfettered majority decision making. Drawing on the work of Condorcet, we have seen that the strongest justification for supermajority rules is to bias decision making to reduce the probability of serious moral or epistemic error. Condorcet developed two key arguments on behalf of supermajority rules. First, supermajority rules bias our decisions when consequence of acting wrongly is much greater than not acting at all; when one option (acquittal) is clearly preferable to an erroneous choice (false conviction), as in Condorcet’s example of the jury; or perhaps when a rule is proposed that would generate inequality among the citizens. Second, because more individuals must be persuaded, supermajority rules prevent hasty decision making and ensure full consideration of reasons.

To mitigate such risks, of course, is a central goal of constitutionalism. One key aim of constitutionalism is to introduce a strong status quo bias into democratic decision making. This is, first, because stability is intrinsically desirable, as it affords the security of expectations. Second, a status quo bias enables ordinary political life, including legislation, to operate without constant renegotiation of the terms. An unstable framework hinders political and economic development, and potentially generates interminable conflict over the core structures of politics. But constitutionalism also seeks to reduce familiar normative risks: the threat of “tyranny of the majority,” of violations of the rights of minorities in particular, of a partisan majority acting to alter the terms of the political arrangement to enhance its reelection prospects, and so on.

Type
Chapter
Information
Counting the Many
The Origins and Limits of Supermajority Rule
, pp. 146 - 181
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×