Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-hgkh8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T13:51:31.255Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 July 2018

Hanno Sauer
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abramson, K. (2014). “Turning up the Lights on Gaslighting,” Philosophical Perspectives 28(1): 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F., and Steadman, A.. (2004). “Intentional Action in Ordinary Language: Core Concept or Pragmatic Understanding?Analysis 64(2): 7381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aharoni, E., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., and Kiehl, K. A.. (2012). “Can Psychopathic Offenders Discern Moral Wrongs? A New Look at the Moral/Conventional Distinction,” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 121(2): 484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alfano, M. (2013). Character as Moral Fiction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alfano, M. (2016). Moral Psychology: An Introduction. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Alfano, M., and Loeb, D.. (2014). “Experimental Moral Philosophy,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2017: 1–32.Google Scholar
Alfano, M., Beebe, J., and Robinson, B.. (2012). “The Centrality of Belief and Reflection in Knobe-Effect Cases,” The Monist 95(2): 264289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alicke, M. D. (1992). “Culpable Causation,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 63(3): 368378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alicke, M. D. (2000). “Culpable Control and the Psychology of Blame,” Psychological Bulletin 126(4): 556574.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Alzola, M. (2008). “Character and Environment: The Status of Virtues in Organizations,” Journal of Business Ethics 78(3): 343357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andow, J. (2016). “Reliable but Not Home Free? What Framing Effects Mean for Moral Intuitions,” Philosophical Psychology 29(6): 904911.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Appiah, A. (2008). Experiments in Ethics. Princeton, NJ: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, R. (2009). The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Avenanti, A., Sirigu, A., and Aglioti, S. M.. (2010). “Racial Bias Reduces Empathic Sensorimotor Resonance with Other-Race Pain,” Current Biology 20(11): 10181022.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ballantyne, N. (2015). “Debunking Biased Thinkers (Including Ourselves),” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1(1): 141162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bargh, J. A., and Chartrand, T. L.. (1999). “The Unbearable Automaticity of Being,” American Psychologist 54: 462479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartels, D. M., and Pizarro, D. A.. (2011). “The Mismeasure of Morals: Antisocial Personality Traits Predict Utilitarian Responses to Moral Dilemmas,” Cognition 121(1): 154161.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bauman, C. W., McGraw, P., Bartel, D., and Warren, C.. (2014). “Revisiting External Validity: Concerns about Trolley Problems and Other Sacrificial Dilemmas in Moral Psychology,” Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8(9): 536554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., and Nathan DeWall, C.. (2009). “Prosocial Benefits of Feeling Free: Disbelief in Free Will Increases Aggression and Reduces Helpfulness,” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 35(2): 260268.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beebe, J. R., and Buckwalter, W. (2010). “The Epistemic Side-Effect Effect,” Mind & Language 25(4): 474498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berker, S. (2009). “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 37(4): 293329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blair, R. J. R. (1995). “A Cognitive Developmental Approach to Morality: Investigating the Psychopath,” Cognition 57(1): 129.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bloom, P. (2011). “Family, Community, Trolley Problems, and the Crisis in Moral Psychology,” The Yale Review 99(2): 2643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloom, P. (2016). Against Empathy: The Case of Rational Compassion. New York: Harper-Collins.Google Scholar
Bogardus, T. (2013). “The Problem of Contingency for Religious Belief,” Faith and Philosophy 30(4): 371392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogardus, T. (2016). “Only All Naturalists Should Worry about Only One Evolutionary Debunking Argument,” Ethics 126(3): 636661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowles, S., and Gintis, H.. (2011). A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and Its Evolution. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brennan, J., and Jaworski, P. M.. (2015). “Markets without Symbolic Limits,” Ethics 125(4): 10531077.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brink, D. O. (1984). “Moral Realism and the Sceptical Arguments from Disagreement and Queerness,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62(2): 111125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A., and Powell, R.. (2015). “The Limits of Evolutionary Explanations of Morality and Their Implications for Moral Progress,” Ethics 126(1): 3767.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A., and Powell, R.. (2016). “Toward a Naturalistic Theory of Moral Progress,” Ethics 126(4): 9831014.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, R., and Kumar, V.. (2012). “Moral Reasoning on the Ground,” Ethics 122(2): 273312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carel, H. (2008). Illness: The Cry of the Flesh. Stocksfield: Acumen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (2011). “Disagreement, Question-Begging, and Epistemic Self-Criticism,” Philosopher’s Imprint 11(6): 122.Google Scholar
Clark, C. J., et al. (2014). “Free to Punish: A Motivated Account of Free Will Belief,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 106(4): 501513.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clarke-Doane, J. (2012). “Morality and Mathematics: The Evolutionary Challenge,” Ethics 122(2): 313340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke-Doane, J. (2014). “Moral Epistemology: The Mathematics Analogy,” Noûs 48(2): 238255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cosmides, L. (1989). “The Logic of Social Exchange: Has Natural Selection Shaped How Humans Reason? Studies with the Wason Selection Task,” Cognition 31: 187276.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cova, F. (2013). “Unconsidered Intentional Actions: An Assessment of Scaife and Webber’s ‘Consideration Hypothesis,’Journal of Moral Philosophy (1):122.Google Scholar
Cova, F., Dupoux, E., and Jacob, P.. (2012). “On Doing Things Intentionally,” Mind & Language 27(4):378409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cova, F., and Naar, H.. (2012a). “Side-Effect Effect Without Side Effects: The Pervasive Impact of Moral Considerations on Judgments of Intentionality,” Philosophical Psychology 25(6): 837854.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cova, F., and Naar, H.. (2012b). “Testing Sripada’s Deep Self Model,” Philosophical Psychology 25(5): 647659.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Cruz, H. (2016). “Numerical Cognition and Mathematical Realism,” Philosopher’s Imprint 16(16): 113.Google Scholar
Curry, O. S. (2016). “Morality as Cooperation: A Problem-Centred Approach.” In Shackelford, T. K. and Hansen, R. D. (eds.), The Evolution of Morality. Springer, 2751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cushman, F. (2008). “Crime and Punishment: Distinguishing the Roles of Causal and Intentional Analyses in Moral Judgment,” Cognition 108(2): 353380.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F. (2013a). “The Role of Learning in Punishment, Prosociality, and Human Uniqueness.” In Sterelny, K., Joyce, R., Calcott, B., and Fraser, B. (eds.), Cooperation and Its Evolution. MIT Press, 333372.Google Scholar
Cushman, F. (2013b). “Action, Outcome, and Value: A Dual-System Framework for Morality,” Personality and Social Psychology Review 17(3): 273292.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F. (2015). “Punishment in Humans: From Intuitions to Institutions,” Philosophy Compass 10(2): 117133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cushman, F., Knobe, J., and Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). “Moral Appraisals Affect Doing/Allowing Judgments,” Cognition 108(2): 353380.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F., Young, L., et al. (2006). “The Role of Conscious Reasoning and Intuition in Moral Judgment: Testing Three Principles of Harm,” Psychological Science 17(12): 10821089.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dalbauer, Nikolaus, and Hergovich, Andreas. (2013). “Is What Is Worse More Likely? — The Probabilistic Explanation of the Epistemic Side-Effect Effect,” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4(4):639657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics Without Principles. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darby, R. (2003). “The Masturbation Taboo and the Rise of Routine Male Circumcision: A Review of the Historiography,” Journal of Social History. 36(3): 737757.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darby, R. (2005). A Surgical Temptation: The Demonization of the Foreskin and the Rise of Circumcision in Britain. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darley, J. M., and Batson, C. D.. (1973). “From Jerusalem to Jericho: A Study of Situational and Dispositional Variables in Helping Behavior,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 27(1): 100108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darley, J. M., and Latane, B.. (1968). “Bystander Intervention in Emergencies: Diffusion of Responsibility,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 8(4p1): 377383.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., and Railton, P.. (1992). “Toward Fin de Siècle Ethics: Some Trends,” Philosophical Review 101(1): 115189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. (1879/2004). The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. Penguin.Google Scholar
Das, R. (2016). “Evolutionary Debunking of Morality: Epistemological or Metaphysical?Philosophical Studies 173(2): 417435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1976). The Selfish Gene. New York City: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Demaree-Cotton, J. (2016). “Do Framing Effects Make Moral Intuitions Unreliable?Philosophical Psychology 29(1): 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doris, J., and Plakias, A.. (2008). “How to Argue about Disagreement: Evaluative Diversity and Moral Realism.” In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.), Moral Psychology Volume 2, The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 303331.Google Scholar
Doris, J. M. (2009). “Skepticism about Persons,” Philosophical Issues 19(1): 5791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doris, J. M. (2009). “Genealogy and Evidence: Prinz on the History of Morals,” Analysis 69(4): 704713.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doris, J. M., and Stich, S. P.. (2005). “As a Matter of Fact : Empirical Perspectives on Ethics.” In Jackson, F. and Smith, M. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 114152.Google Scholar
Doris, J. M., and Murphy, D.. (2007). “From My Lai to Abu Ghraib: The Moral Psychology of Atrocity,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31(1): 2555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driver, J. (2008a). “Imaginative Resistance and Psychological Necessity,” Social Philosophy and Policy 25(1): 301313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driver, J. (2008b). “Attributions of Causation and Moral Responsibility.” In Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Moral Psychology. Vol. 2. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press: 423439.Google Scholar
Driver, J. (2016). “The Limits of the Dual-Process View.” In Liao, S. M. (ed.), Moral Brains. Oxford University Press, 150159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edmonds, D. (2015). Would You Kill the Fat Man? The Trolley Problem and What Your Answer Tells us about Right and Wrong. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. (2009). “How Is Moral Disagreement a Problem for Realism?Journal of Ethics 13(1): 1550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. (2014). “A Defense of Moral Deference,” Journal of Philosophy 111: 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, J. (2008). “Dual-Processing Accounts of Reasoning, Judgment, and Social Cognition,” Annu. Rev. Psychol 59: 255278.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Evans, J., and Stanovich, K. (2013). “Dual-Process Theories of Higher Cognition,” Perspectives on Psychological Science 8(3): 223241.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fitzpatrick, S. (2014). “Moral Realism, Moral Disagreement, and Moral Psychology,” Philosophical Papers 43(2): 161190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, O. J. (1991). Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Flanagan, O. (2017). The Geography of Morals: Varieties of Moral Possibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
FitzPatrick, W. J. (2015). “Debunking Evolutionary Debunking of Ethical Realism,” Philosophical Studies 172(4): 883904.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P. (1967). “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect,” Oxford Review 5: 515.Google Scholar
Foot, P. (2001). Natural Goodness. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraser, B., and Hauser, M. (2010). “The Argument from Disagreement and the Role of Cross-Cultural Empirical Data,” Mind & Language 25(5): 541560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M. (2013). “Styles of Moral Relativism. A Critical Family Tree.” In Crisp, R. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics. Oxford University Press, 793818.Google Scholar
Fried, B. H. (2012). “What Does Matter? The Case for Killing the Trolley Problem (or Letting It Die),” Philosophical Quarterly 62(248): 505529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gendler, T. S. (2000). “The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance,” The Journal of Philosophy 97(2): 5581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gert, J. (2015). “Disgust, Moral Disgust, and Morality,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 12(1): 3354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (2007). Gut Feelings: Short Cuts to Better Decision Making. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Gold, N., Colman, A., and Pulford, B.. (2014). “Cultural Differences in Responses to Real-Life and Hypothetical Trolley Problems,” Judgment and Decision Making 9(1): 6576.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gold, N., Pulford, B., and Colman, A.. (2014). “The Outlandish, the Realistic, and the Real: Contextual Manipulation and Agent Role Effects in Trolley Problems,” Frontiers in Psychology: Cognitive Science 5: 110.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Graber, A. (2012). “Medusa’s Gaze Reflected: A Darwinian Dilemma for Anti-Realist Theories of Value,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15(5): 589601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, J., Haidt, J., and Nosek, B. A.. (2009). “Liberals and Conservatives Rely on Different Sets of Moral Foundations,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 96(5): 1029.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, R., Wojcik, S., and Ditto, P. H.. (in press). “Moral Foundations Theory: The Pragmatic Validity of Moral Pluralism,” Advances in Experimental Social Psychology.Google Scholar
Graham, J., Nosek, B., and Haidt, J.. (in press). “The Moral Stereotypes of Liberals and Conservatives: Exaggeration across the Political Divide,” PLoS One.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2008). “The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul.” In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.), Moral Psychology. Vol. 3. The Neuroscience of Morality: Emotion, Brain Disorders, and Development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 3579.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2013). Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap between Us and Them. Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2014). “Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality: Why Cognitive (Neuro)Science Matters for Ethics,” Ethics 124(4): 695726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, J. D., et al. (2014). “Are ‘Counter-Intuitive,’ Deontological Judgments Really Counter-Intuitive? An Empirical Reply to Kahane et al. (2012),” Social Cognition & Affective Neuroscience 9(9): 13681371.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2016). “Reply to Driver and Darwall.” In Liao, S. M. (ed.), Moral Brains. Oxford University Press, 170181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2017). “The Rat-a-Gorical Imperative: Moral Intuition and the Limits of Affective Learning. Cognition.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, B. D., et al. (2001). “An fMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment,” Science 293: 21052108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greene, J. D., Cushman, F., et al. (2009). “Pushing Moral Buttons: The Interaction between Personal Force and Intention in Moral Judgment,” Cognition 111(3): 364371.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., et al. (2004). “The Neural Bases of Cognitive Conflict and Control in Moral Judgment,” Neuron 44: 389400.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haggard, P., and Eimer, M.. (1999). “On the Relation between Brain Potentials and the Awareness of Voluntary Movements,” Experimental Brain Research 126(1): 128133.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J. (2001). “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment,” Psychological Review 108(4): 814.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J. (2004). “The Emotional Dog Gets Mistaken for a Possum,” Review of General Psychology 8(4): 283290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J. (2012). The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Religion and Politics. London, Penguin.Google Scholar
Haidt, J., Koller, S., et al. (1993). “Affect, Culture, and Morality, or Is It Wrong to Eat Your Dog?Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65: 613628.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J., Rozin, P., McCauley, C., and Imada, S.. (1997). “Body, Psyche, and Culture: The Relationship between Disgust and Morality,” Psychology & Developing Societies 9(1): 107131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J., Björklund, F., et al. (2000). “Moral Dumbfounding: When Intuition Finds No Reason.” Unpublished Manuscript, University of Virginia.Google Scholar
Haidt, J., and Bjorklund, F.. (2008). “Social Intuitionists Answer Six Questions about Moral Psychology.” In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.), Moral Psychology. Vol. 2. The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 181217.Google Scholar
Haidt, J., and Graham, J.. (2007). “When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions That Liberals May Not Recognize,” Social Justice Research 20: 98116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J., and Hersh, M.. (2001). “Sexual Morality: The Cultures and Emotions of Conservatives and Liberals,” Journal of Applied Social Psychology 31: 191221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, L., Johansson, P., and Strandberg, T.. (2012). “Lifting the Veil of Morality: Choice Blindness and Attitude Reversals on a Self-Transforming Survey,” PLoS One 7(9): e45457.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haney, C., Banks, W., and Zimbardo, P.. (1973). “Interpersonal Dynamics of a Simulated Prison,” International Journal of Criminology and Penology 1: 6997.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (1975). “Moral Relativism Defended,” The Philosophical Review 84(2): 322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1999). “Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99(1999): 315331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (2009). “Skepticism about Character Traits,” Journal of Ethics 13(2/3): 235242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henrich, J. (2015). The Secret of Our Success: How Culture Is Driving Human Evolution, Domesticating Our Species, and Making Us Smarter. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., and Norenzayan, A.. (2010). “The Weirdest People in the World,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33(2–3):6183.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hindriks, F. (2008). “Intentional Action and the Praise-Blame Asymmetry,” The Philosophical Quarterly 58(233): 630641.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hindriks, F. (2014). “Normativity in Action: How to Explain the Knobe Effect and Its Relatives,” Mind & Language 29(1): 5172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holton, R. (2010). “Norms and the Knobe Effect,” Analysis 70(3): 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T., and Timmons, M.. (2007). “Morphological Rationalism and the Psychology of Moral Judgment,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10: 279295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical Intuitionism. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (2016). “A Liberal Realist Answer to Debunking Skeptics: The Empirical Case for Realism,” Philosophical Studies 173(7): 128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1739/2000). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (1999). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D., Iyer, R., and Haidt, J.. (2012). “Disgust Sensitivity, Political Conservatism, and Voting,” Social Psychological and Personality Science 3(5): 537544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isen, A. M., and Levin, P. F.. (1972). “Effect of Feeling Good on Helping: Cookies and Kindness,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 21(3): 384388.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Iyer, R., Koleva, S. P., Graham, J., Ditto, P. H., and Haidt, J.. (2012). “Understanding Libertarian Morality: The Psychological Dispositions of Self-Identified Libertarians,” PLoS One 7(8): e42366.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jacobson, D. (2012). “Moral Dumbfounding and Moral Stupefaction,” Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 2: 289316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, K. (2012). “The Politics of Intellectual Self-Trust,” Social Epistemology 26(2): 237251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, R. (2006). The Evolution of Morality. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kagan, S. (2001). “Thinking about Cases,” Social Philosophy and Policy 18(2): 4463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahan, D. M. (2012). “Ideology, Motivated Reasoning, and Cognitive Reflection: An Experimental Study,” Judgment and Decision Making 8: 407–24.Google Scholar
Kahane, G. (2011). “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments,” Noûs 45(1): 103125.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G. (2012). “On the Wrong Track: Process and Content in Moral Psychology,” Mind & Language 27(5):519545.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G. (2013). “Must Metaethical Realism Make a Semantic Claim?Journal of Moral Philosophy 10(2): 148178.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G. (2014). “Evolution and Impartiality,” Ethics 124(2): 327.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G. et al. (2012). “The Neural Basis of Intuitive and Counterintuitive Moral Judgement,” Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 7(4): 393402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, G. (2013). “The Armchair and the Trolley: An Argument for Experimental Ethics,” Philosophical Studies 162(2):421445.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G. (2015). “Sidetracked by Trolleys: Why Sacrificial Moral Dilemmas Tell Us Little (or Nothing) about Utilitarian Judgment,” Social Neuroscience 10(5): 551560.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G., Everett, J. A. C., Earp, B. D., Farias, M., and Savulescu, J.. (2015). “‘Utilitarian’ Judgments in Sacrificial Moral Dilemmas Do Not Reflect Impartial Concern for the Greater Good,” Cognition 134:193209.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, Fast and Slow. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Tversky, A., et al., eds. (1982). Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, F. M. (1993). Morality, Mortality. 1: Death and Whom to Save From It. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kamm, F. M. (2007). Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, F. M. (2009). “Neuroscience and Moral Reasoning: A Note on Recent Research,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 37(4): 330345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katsafanas, P. (2013). Agency and the Foundations of Ethics: Nietzschean Constitutivism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kellogg, J. H. (1887). Plain Facts for Old and Young: Embracing the Natural History and Hygiene of Organic Life. Burlington: Segner.Google Scholar
Kelly, D. (2011). Yuck!: The Nature and Moral Significance of Disgust. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennett, J. (2011). “Imagining Reasons,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 49: 181192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennett, J. (2012). “Living With One’s Choices Moral Reasoning In Vitro and In Vivo.” In Langdon, R. and Mackenzie, C. (eds.), Emotions, Imagination, and Moral Reasoning. New York, Psychology Press, 257278.Google Scholar
Kennett, J., and Fine, C.. (2009). “Will the Real Moral Judgment Please Stand Up?Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12(1):7796.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (2010) “Challenges for Secularism.” In Levine, George, ed., The Joy of Secularism: 11 Essays for How We Live Now. Princeton University Press, 2456.Google Scholar
Klein, C. (2011). “The Dual Track Theory of Moral Decision-Making: A Critique of the Neuroimaging Evidence,” Neuroethics 4(2): 143162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2003). “Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language,” Analysis 63(3): 190194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2004). “Folk Psychology and Folk Morality: Response to Critics,” Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24(2):270279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2006). “The Concept of Intentional Action: A Case Study in the Uses of Folk Psychology,” Philosophical Studies 130: 203231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2007). “Reason Explanation in Folk Psychology,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31: 90107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2010). “Person as Scientist, Person as Moralist,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33(4): 315329.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Knobe, J., and Burra, A.. (2006). “The Folk Concepts of Intention and Intentional Action: A Cross-Cultural Study,” Journal of Cognition and Culture 6(1–2): 113132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J., and Fraser, B.. (2008a). Causal Judgment and Moral Judgment: Two Experiments. In Moral Psychology. Vol. 2. Sinnott-Armstrong, W.. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press: 441448.Google Scholar
Knobe, J., and Fraser, B.. (2008b). “Causal Judgment and Moral Judgment: Two Experiments.” In Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.), Moral Psychology. Vol. 2. MIT Press, 441449.Google Scholar
Knobe, J., and Leiter, B.. (2007). “The Case for Nietzschean Moral Psychology.” In Leiter, B. and Sinhababu, N. (eds.), Nietzsche and Morality. Oxford University Press, 83109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J., and Mendlow, G.. (2004). “The Good, the Bad and the Blameworthy: Understanding the Role of Evaluative Reasoning in Folk Psychology,” Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24(2): 252258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knutson, K. M., Krueger, F., Koenigs, M., Hawley, A., Escobedo, J., Vasudeva, V., Adolphs, R., and Grafman, J.. (2010). “Behavioral Norms for Condensed Moral Vignettes,” Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 5: 378384.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Koenigs, M., and Tranel, D.. (2007). “Irrational Economic Decision-Making After Ventromedial Prefrontal Damage: Evidence from the Ultimatum Game,” The Journal of Neuroscience 27(4): 951956.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Koenigs, M., Young, L., et al. (2007). “Damages to the Prefrontal Cortex Increases Utilitarian Moral Judgments,” Nature 446(7138): 908911.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Köhler, S., and Ridge, M.. (2013). “Revolutionary Expressivism,” Ratio 26(4): 428449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koleva, S. P., Graham, J., Ditto, P., Iyer, R., and Haidt, J.. (2012). “Tracing the Threads: How Five Moral Concerns (Especially Purity) Help Explain Culture War Attitudes,” Journal of Research in Personality 46: 184194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koralus, P. and Alfano, M.. (2017). “Reasons-Based Moral Judgment and the Erotetic Theory.” In Bonnefon, J.-F. and Trémolière, B. (eds.), Moral Inferences. Routledge: New York. 77106.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kristjánsson, K. (2012). “Situationism and the Concept of a Situation,” European Journal of Philosophy 20 (S1): E52-E72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kumar, V. (2017a). Moral vindications. Cognition 167: 124134.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kumar, V. (2017b). Foul Behavior. Philosopher’s Imprint 17(15): 117.Google Scholar
Kumar, V. and May, J. (forthcoming). “How to Debunk Moral Beliefs.” Methodology and Moral Philosophy (eds.), Jussi Suikkanen & Antti Kauppinen. Routledge.Google Scholar
de Lazari-Radek, K., and Singer, P.. (2010). “Secrecy in Consequentialism: A Defence of Esoteric Morality,” Ratio 23(1): 3458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Lazari-Radek, K., and Singer, P.. (2012). The Objectivity of Ethics and the Unity of Practical Reason,” Ethics 123(1): 931.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leiter, B. (2007). “Against Convergent Moral Realism: The Respective Roles of Philosophical Argument and Empirical Evidence.” In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.), Moral Psychology Volume 2, The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 333337.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2005). “Imaginative Resistance and the Moral/Conventional Distinction,” Philosophical Psychology 18(2): 231241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, N. (2007). Neuroethics. Challenges for the 21st Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, N. (2015). “Less Blame, Less Crime? The Practical Implications of Moral Responsibility Skepticism,” Journal of Practical Ethics 3(2): 117.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2016). “Dissolving the Puzzle of Resultant Moral Luck,” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7(1): 127139.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Liao, S. M., Wiegmann, A., Alexander, J., and Vong, G.. (2012). “Putting the Trolley in Order: Experimental Philosophy and the Loop Case,” Philosophical Psychology 25(5): 661671.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Libet, B. W. (1985). “Unconscious Cerebral Initiative and the Role of Conscious Will in Voluntary Action,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8(4): 529566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacFarquhar, L. (2015). Strangers Drowning: Grappling with Impossible Idealism, Drastic Choices, and the Overpowering Urge to Help. Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Machery, E. (2008). “The Folk Concept of Intentional Action,” Mind & Language 23(2): 165189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Penguin.Google Scholar
Maibom, H. (2008). “The Mad, the Bad, and the Psychopath,” Neuroethics 1(3):167184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mallon, R. (2008). “Knobe versus Machery: Testing the Trade-Off Hypothesis,” Mind & Language 23(2): 247255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, R., and Barresi, J.. (2003). “Personal Identity and What Mattes in Survival: An Historical Overview.” In Martin, Raymond and Barresi, John (eds.), Personal Identity. Blackwell, 175.Google Scholar
Mason, E. (2013). “Objectivism and Prospectivism about Rightness,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 7(2): 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mason, K. (2010). “Debunking Arguments and the Genealogy of Religion and Morality,” Philosophy Compass 5(9): 770778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, J. (2014). “Does Disgust Influence Moral Judgment?Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92(1): 125141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, J. (forthcoming). Regard for Reason in the Moral Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
May, S. (Ed.). (2011). Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, S. (2004). “Moral Knowledge by Perception,” Philosophical Perspectives 18(1): 209228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, S. (2011). “Skepticism about Moral Expertise as a Puzzle for Moral Realism,” The Journal of Philosophy 108(3): 111137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGuire, J., Langdon, R., Coltheart, M., and Mackenzie, C.. (2009). “A Reanalysis of the Personal/Impersonal Distinction in Moral Psychology Research,” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45(3): 577580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mele, A. R., and Cushman, F.. (2007). “Intentional Action, Folk Judgments, and Stories: Sorting Things Out,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23: 184201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mercier, H., and Sperber, D.. (2017). The Enigma of Reason. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Merritt, M. (2009). “Aristotelean Virtue and the Interpersonal Aspect of Ethical Character,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 6(1): 2349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, C. D. (2013). “Defending Moral Realism from Empirical Evidence of Disagreement,” Social Theory and Practice 39(3): 373396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mikhail, J. (2007). “Universal Moral Grammar: Theory, Evidence, and the Future,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11(4): 143152.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Milgram, S. (1963). “Behavioral Study of Obedience,” The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 67(4): 371.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Miller, C. (2003). “Social Psychology and Virtue Ethics,” Journal of Ethics 7(4): 365392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mirza, O. (2011). “The Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism,” Philosophy Compass 6(1): 7889.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mizrahi, M. (2014). “Does the Method of Cases Rest on a Mistake?Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5(2): 183197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moll, J., Zahn, R., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Krueger, F., and Grafman, J.. (2005). “Opinion: The Neural Basis of Human Moral Cognition,” Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6: 799809.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moody-Adams, M. M. (2009). Fieldwork in Familiar Places: Morality, Culture, and Philosophy. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Musschenga, B. (2013). “The Promises of Moral Foundations Theory,” Journal of Moral Education 42(3): 330345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. (2006). “Bad Acts, Blameworthy Agents, and Intentional Actions: Some Problems for Juror Impartiality,” Philosophical Explorations 9(2): 203219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newman, G. E., De Freitas, J., and Knobe, J.. (2015). “Beliefs about the True Self Explain Asymmetries Based on Moral Judgment,” Cognitive Science 39(1): 96125.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. (2014). “Process Debunking and Ethics,” Ethics 124(4): 727749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S., and Knobe, J.. (2007). “Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions,” Noûs 41(4): 663685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S., and Ulatowski, J.. (2007). “Intuitions and Individual Differences: The Knobe Effect Revisited,” Mind & Language 22(4): 346365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S., Kumar, S., Lopez, T., Ayars, A., and Chan, H.. (2016). “Rational Learners and Moral Rules,” Mind & Language 31(5): 530554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickerson, R. S. (1998). “Confirmation Bias: A Ubiquitous Phenomenon in Many Guises,” Review of General Psychology 2(2): 175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nietzsche, F. The Gay Science. (Referred to as GS. Numerals refer to sections.)Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. On the Genealogy of Morality. (Referred to as GM. Numerals refer to sections.)Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., and Wilson, T. D.. (1977). “Telling More than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes,” Psychological Review 84(3): 231259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., and Wilson, T. D.. (1978). “The Accuracy of Verbal Reports about the Effects of Stimuli and Behavior,” Social Psychology 41(2): 118131.Google Scholar
Norcross, A. (2008). “Off Her Trolley? Frances Kamm and the Metaphysics of Morality,” Utilitas 20(1):6580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (2009). Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Hara, R. E., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., and Sinnott-Armstrong, N. A.. (2010). “Wording Effects on Moral Judgements,” Judgement and Decision Making 5(7): 547554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. A. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Paxton, J. M., Ungar, L., et al. (2012). “Reflection and Reasoning in Moral Judgment,” Cognitive Science 36(1): 163177.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pettit, D., and Knobe, J.. (2009). “The Pervasive Impact of Moral Judgment,” Mind & Language 24(5): 586604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phelan, M., and Sarkissian, H.. (2009). “Is the ‘Trade-off Hypothesis’ Worth Trading For?Mind & Language 24(2): 164180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, J., Luguri, J. B., and Knobe, J.. (2015). “Unifying Morality’s Influence on Non-Moral Judgments: The Relevance of Alternative Possibilities,” Cognition 145: 3042.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Phillips, J., Misenheimer, L., and Knobe, J.. (2011). “The Ordinary Concept of Happiness (and Others Like It),” Emotion Review 71(3): 929937.Google Scholar
Pinillos, N., Smith, N., et al. (2011). “Philosophy’s New Challenge: Experiments and Intentional Action,” Mind & Language 26(1): 115139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, S. (2011). The Better Angels of Our Nature: The Decline of Violence in History and Its Causes. Penguin UK.Google Scholar
Plakias, A. (2013). “The Good and the Gross,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16(2): 261278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and Proper Function. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (2009). “The Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism: An Initial Statement of the Argument,” Philosophy After Darwin: Classic and Contemporary Readings: 301–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Portmore, D. W. (2009). “Consequentializing,” Philosophy Compass 4(2): 329347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinz, J. (2006). “The Emotional Basis of Moral Judgments,” Philosophical Explorations 9(1): 2943.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinz, J. (2007). The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. (2009). “The Normativity Challenge: Cultural Psychology Provides the Real Threat to Virtue Ethics,” Journal of Ethics 13(2–3): 117144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinz, J. (2011). “Against Empathy,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 49(1): 214233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rai, T. S. and Fiske, A. P.. (2011). “Moral Psychology Is Relationship Regulation: Moral Motives for Unity, Hierarchy, Equality, and Proportionality,” Psychological Review 118: 5775.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Railton, P. (1986). “Moral Realism,” The Philosophical Review 95(2):163207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, P. (1998). “Moral Explanation and Moral Objectivity,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58: 175–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, P. (2014). “The Affective Dog and Its Rational Tale: Intuition and Attunement,” Ethics 124(4): 813859.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, P. (2017). “Moral Learning: Why Learning? Why Moral? And Why Now?Cognition 167: 172190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rini, R. A. (2013). “Making Psychology Normatively Significant,” Journal of Ethics 17(3): 257274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rini, R. (2015). “How Not to Test for Philosophical Expertise,” Synthese 192(2): 431452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rini, R. A. (2015). “Morality and Cognitive Science,” Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Rini, R. A. (2016). “Debunking Debunking: A Regress Challenge for Psychological Threats to Moral Judgment,” Philosophical Studies 173(3): 675697.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rini, R. A. (2017). “Why Moral Psychology Is Disturbing,” Philosophical Studies 174(6): 14391458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, B., Stey, P., and Alfano, M.. (2015). “Reversing the Side-Effect Effect: The Power of Salient Norms,” Philosophical Studies 172(1): 177206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roeser, S. (2011). Moral Emotions and Intuitions. Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, L., and Nisbett, R. E.. (1991). The Person and the Situation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Rossen, I., Lawrence, C., Dunlop, P., and Lewandowsky, S.. (2014) “Can Moral Foundations Theory Help to Explain Partisan Differences in Climate Change Beliefs?” Paper presented at the annual meeting of the ISPP 36th Annual Scientific Meeting, Lauder School of Government, Diplomacy and Strategy, IDC–Herzliya, Herzliya, Israel.Google Scholar
Rose, D., Livengood, J., Sytsma, J., and Machery, E.. (2012). “Deep Trouble for the Deep Self,” Philosophical Psychology 25(5): 629646.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Royzman, E. B., Kim, K., and Leeman, R. F.. (2015). “The Curious Tale of Julie and Mark: Unraveling the Moral Dumbfounding Effect,” Judgment and Decision Making 10(4): 296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saar, M. (2008). “Understanding Genealogy: History, Power, and the Self,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 2(3): 295314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. (2012a). “Psychopaths and Filthy Desks: Are Emotions Necessary and Sufficient for Moral Judgment?Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15(1): 95115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. (2012b). “Morally Irrelevant Factors: What’s Left of the Dual Process-Model of Moral Cognition?Philosophical Psychology 25(6): 783811.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. (2012c). “Educated Intuitions. Automaticity and Rationality in Moral Judgement,” Philosophical Explorations 15(3): 255275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. (2014). “It’s the Knobe Effect, Stupid!Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5(4): 485503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. (2017). Moral Judgments as Educated Intuitions. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. and Bates, T.. (2013). “Chairmen, Cocaine, and Car Crashes: The Knobe Effect as an Attribution Error,” Journal of Ethics 17(4): 305330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schinkel, A. (2009). “The Problem of Moral Luck: An Argument against Its Epistemic Reduction,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12(3): 267277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlosser, M. E. (2012a). “Free Will and the Unconscious Precursors of Choice,” Philosophical Psychology 25(3): 365384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlosser, M. E. (2012b). “Causally Efficacious Intentions and the Sense of Agency: In Defense of Real Mental Causation,” Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 32(3): 135160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlosser, M. E. (2014). “The Neuroscientific Study of Free Will: A Diagnosis of the Controversy,” Synthese 191(2): 245262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schnall, S., et al. (2008). “Disgust as Embodied Moral Judgment,” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 34(8): 10961109.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schultze-Kraft, M., et al. (2016). “The Point of No Return in Vetoing Self-Initiated Movements,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113(4): 10801085.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schwitzgebel, E., and Cushman, F.. (2012). “Expertise in Moral Reasoning? Order Effects on Moral Judgment in Professional Philosophers and Non-Philosophers,” Mind & Language 27(2): 135153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. (2012). “Evolutionary Debunking, Moral Realism and Moral Knowledge,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 7: i.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. (1907). The Methods of Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Singer, P. (1972). “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 1(3): 229243.Google Scholar
Singer, P. (1993). Practical Ethics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Singer, P. (2011). The Expanding Circle: Ethics, Evolution, and Moral Progress. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P. (2005). “Ethics and Intuitions,” The Journal of Ethics 9(3–4): 331352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinhababu, N. (2013). “Unequal Vividness and Double Effect,” Utilitas 25(3): 291315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). “Framing Moral Intuitions. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.), Moral Psychology, Vol. 2: The Cognitive Science of Morality. MIT Press, 4776.Google Scholar
Skarsaune, K. O. (2011). “Darwin and Moral Realism: Survival of the Iffiest,” Philosophical Studies 152(2): 229243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. (1987). “The Humean Theory of Motivation,” Mind 96(381): 3661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sneddon, A. (2009). “Normative Ethics and the Prospects of an Empirical Contribution to the Assessment of Moral Disagreement and Moral Realism,” Journal of Value Inquiry 43(4): 447455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. and Wilson, D. S.. (1998). Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Soon, C. S., Brass, M., Heinze, H. J., and Haynes, J. D.. (2008). “Unconscious Determinants of Free Decisions in the Human Brain,” Nature neuroscience 11(5): 543545.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Srinivasan, A. (2015). “The Archimedean Urge,” Philosophical Perspectives 29(1): 325362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sripada, C. and Konrath, S.. (2011). “Telling More Than We Can Know About Intentional Action,” Mind & Language 26(3): 353380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sripada, C. S. (2010). “The Deep Self Model and Asymmetries in Folk Judgments about Intentional Action,” Philosophical Studies 151: 159176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanovich, K. (2011). Rationality and the Reflective Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. (2012). The Evolved Apprentice. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stocker, M. (1976). “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories,” Journal of Philosophy 73(14): 453466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Street, S. (2006). “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value,” Philosophical Studies 127(1): 109166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Street, S. (2010). “What Is Constructivism in Ethics and Metaethics?Philosophy Compass 5(5): 363384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Street, S. (forthcoming). “Does Anything Really Matter or Did We Just Evolve to Think So?” In A. Byrne, J. Cohen, G. Rosen, and S. Shiffrin eds., The Norton Introduction to Philosophy. New York: Norton, 685–695.Google Scholar
Strohminger, N. (2014). “Disgust Talked about,” Philosophy Compass 9(7): 478493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strohminger, N. and Nichols, S.. (2014). “The Essential Moral Self,” Cognition 113(2014): 159171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sturgeon, N. (1985). “Moral Explanations.” In Copp, David and Zimmerman, David, eds., Morality, Reason and Truth. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 4978.Google Scholar
Taurek, J. M. (1977). “Should the Numbers Count?Philosophy & Public Affairs 6(4): 293316.Google ScholarPubMed
Tersman, F. (2008). “The Reliability of Moral Intuitions: A Challenge from Neuroscience,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86(3): 389405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, J. J. (1976). “Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem,” The Monist 59(2): 204217.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tiberius, V. (2014). Moral Psychology: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Timmons, M. (2012). Moral Theory: An Introduction. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Tobia, K., Buckwalter, W., and Stich, S.. (2013). “Moral Intuitions: Are Philosophers Experts?Philosophical Psychology 26(5): 629638.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tobia, K. P. (2015). “Personal Identity and the Phineas Gage Effect,” Analysis 75(3): 396405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tropman, E. (2014). “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments: Moral Realism, Constructivism, and Explaining Moral Knowledge,” Philosophical Explorations 17(2): 126140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uhlmann, E. L., and Cohen, G. L.. (2005). “Constructed Criteria: Redefining Merit to Justify Discrimination,” Psychological Science 16(6): 474480.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Uhlmann, E. L., Pizarro, D. A., Tannenbaum, D., and Ditto, P. H.. (2009). “The Motivated Use of Moral Principles,” Judgment and Decision Making 4(6): 479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, P. K. (1996). Living High and Letting Die: Our Illusion of Innocence. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uttich, K., and Lombrozo, T.. (2010). “Norms Inform Mental State Ascriptions: A Rational Explanation for the Side-Effect Effect,” Cognition 116: 87100.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Västfjäll, D., Slovic, P., and Mayorga, M.. (2015). “Pseudoinefficacy: Negative Feelings from Children Who Cannot Be Helped Reduce Warm Glow for Children Who Can Be Helped,” Frontiers in Psychology 6: 616.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Västfjäll, D., Slovic, P., Mayorga, M., and Peters, E.. (2014). “Compassion Fade: Affect and Charity Are Greatest for a Single Child in Need,” PLoS One 9(6): e100115.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Valdesolo, P., and DeSteno, D.. (2006). “Manipulations of Emotional Context Shape Moral Judgment,” Psychological Science 17(6): 476477.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vavova, K. (2015). “Evolutionary Debunking of Moral Realism,” Philosophy Compass 10(2): 104116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, D. (2000). The Possibility of Practical Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (2011). How We Get Along. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (2013). “Doables,” Philosophical Explorations (1): 116.Google Scholar
Vogler, C. (2002). Reasonably Vicious. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vranas, P. B. (2005). “The Indeterminacy Paradox: Character Evaluations and Human Psychology,” Noûs 39(1): 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Waal, F. (2006). Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Webber, J. (2013). “Character, Attitude and Disposition,” European Journal of Philosophy 21(1): 10821096.Google Scholar
Webber, J., and Scaife, R.. (2013). “Intentional Side-Effects of Action,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 10(2):179203.Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M. (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wheatley, T., and Haidt, J.. (2005). “Hypnotic Disgust Makes Moral Judgments More Severe,” Psychological Science 16(10): 780784.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wiggins, D. (1998). Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value (Vol. 6). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (2002). Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (2005). In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wong, D. (2006). Natural Moralities: A Defense of Pluralistic Relativism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, A. (2011). “Humanity as an End in Itself.” In Parfit, D. (ed.), On What Matters, Vol 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 5883.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, L., Cushman, F., et al. (2006). “Does Emotion Mediate the Relationship between an Action’s Moral Status and Its Intentional Status? Neuropsychological Evidence,” Journal of Cognition and Culture 6(1–2): 265278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, L., Cushman, F., Hauser, M., and Saxe, R.. (2007). “The Neural Basis of the Interaction between Theory of Mind and Moral Judgment,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 104(20): 82358240.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Young, L., Nichols, S., and Saxe, R.. (2010). “Investigating the Neural and Cognitive Basis of Moral Luck,” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1(3): 333349.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zimmerman, M. J. (2011). The Immorality of Punishment. Broadview Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Hanno Sauer, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
  • Book: Debunking Arguments in Ethics
  • Online publication: 19 July 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108529181.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Hanno Sauer, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
  • Book: Debunking Arguments in Ethics
  • Online publication: 19 July 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108529181.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Hanno Sauer, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
  • Book: Debunking Arguments in Ethics
  • Online publication: 19 July 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108529181.010
Available formats
×