Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T11:52:20.696Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

36 - Developmental origins of health and disease: ethical and social considerations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 August 2009

Ray Noble
Affiliation:
University College, London
Peter Gluckman
Affiliation:
University of Auckland
Mark Hanson
Affiliation:
University of Southampton
Get access

Summary

Introduction

The discovery of a link between low birthweight and adult disease has opened exciting and rewarding areas of research (Nathanielsz and Thornburg 2003). The ‘Barker hypothesis’ of fetal programming, where fetal adaptations to nutritional deprivation increase vulnerability to disorders in later life (Barker 1998), creates the prospect of new strategies to prevent adult diseases either by changing maternal nutrition or by new therapeutic approaches to fetal growth. With the focus on possible benefits of these strategies and the prospect of breaking the cycle of poverty and disease, there has been little consideration of associated ethical and social issues.

In this chapter I will argue that, as currently presented, the concept of the fetal origin of adult disease creates a pseudo-pathological condition by regarding low birthweight, even within the normal range, as impairment. It renders pathological that which we currently regard as normal. It seeks to fix that which may be damaged later (adult disease) by altering that which is not yet broken (fetal growth and function) (Flake 2003). It establishes and fosters a simplistic creed of ‘big babies good, small babies bad’, and it shifts the focus away from socioeconomic influences and places the onus of responsibility on women.

Furthermore, the aim of increasing mean birthweight and employing therapeutic strategies to protect the fetus may further intensify what some already argue is an intimidating environment, challenging the autonomy and rights of pregnant women (Roth 2000).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anon. (2001). Mens Health, 7 (9).
Barker, D. J. P. (1998). In utero programming of chronic disease. Clin. Sci., 95, 115–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bewley, S. (2002). Restricting the freedom of pregnant women. In Ethical Issues in Maternal–Fetal Medicine (ed. Dickenson, D. L.). Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, pp. 131–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cusk, R. (2001). A Life's Work: on Becoming a Mother. London: Fourth Estate.Google Scholar
Das, U. N. (2002). Long chain polyunsaturated fatty acids and fetal programming. Electronic letter. BMJ. www.bmj.com/cgi/eletters/324/7335/447.Google Scholar
Davey, Smith G. (2001). Reflections on the limitations to epidemiology. J. Clin. Epidemiol., 54, 325–31.Google Scholar
Delisle, H., Chandra-Mouli, V. and Benoist, B. (2001). Should adolescents be specifically targeted for nutrition in developing countries? To address which problems, and how? World Health Organization. www.who.int/child-adolescent-health.Google Scholar
Fall, C. H. D. (2003). The fetal and early origins of adult disease. Indian Pediatr., 40, 480–502.Google Scholar
Fall, C. H. D., Osmond, C., Barker, D. J. P., Clark, P. M. S., Stirling, Y. and Meade, T. W. (1995). Fetal and infant growth and cardiovascular risk factors in women. BMJ, 310, 428–32.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fathalla, M. F. (1994). Women's health: an overview. Int. J. Gynaecol. Obstet., 46, 105–18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Flake, A. W. (2003). Surgery in the human fetus: the future. J. Physiol., 547, 45–51.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gallagher, J. (1995). Collective bad faith: ‘protecting’ the Fetus. In Reproduction, Ethics, and the Law: Feminist Perspectives. (ed. Callahan, J. C.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, pp. 343–79.Google Scholar
Hales, C. N and Barker, D. J. P. (1992). Type 2 (non-insulin-dependent) diabetus mellitus: the thrifty phenotype hypothesis. Diabetologia, 35, 595–601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hales, C. N. and Barker, D. J. P. (2001). The thrifty phenotype hypothesis. Br. Med. Bull., 60, 5–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hales, C. N. and Ozanne, S. E. (2003). The dangerous road of catch-up growth. J. Physiol., 547, 5–10.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harding, J. E. (2001). The nutritional basis of the fetal origin of adult disease. Int. J. Epidemiol., 30, 15–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoet, J. J. and Hanson, M. A. (1999). Intrauterine nutrition: its importance during critical periods for cardiovascular and endocrine development. J. Physiol., 514, 617–27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
International Federation of Red Cross and Red Crescent Societies (1999). The public health – human rights dialogue. In Health and Human Rights (ed. Mann, J. M., Gruskin, S., Grodin, M. A. and Annas, G. J.). New York, NY: Routledge, pp. 46–53.Google Scholar
James, D. (1998). Recent advances: fetal medicine. BMJ, 316, 1580–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jonsson, U. (1995). Ethics and child nutrition. Food Nutr. Bull., 16, 293–8.Google Scholar
Mahowald, M. B. (1995). As if there were fetuses without women: a remedial essay. In Reproduction, Ethics, and the Law: Feminist Perspectives (ed. Callahan, J. C.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, pp. 199–218.Google Scholar
Marsland, D. (1995). Social Misconstruction: the Neglect of Biology in Contemporary British Sociology. Sociological Notes, 22. London: Libertarian Alliance.Google Scholar
Merialdi, M., Carroli, G., Villar, J.et al. (2003). Nutrtitional interventions during pregnancy for the prevention or treatment of impaired fetal growth: an overview of randomized controlled trials. J. Nutr., 133, 1626–31S.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nathanielsz, P. W. and Thornburg, K. L. (2003). Fetal programming: from gene to functional systems. An overview. J. Physiol., 547, 3–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nuffield Council on Bioethics (1999). The Ethics of Clinical Research in Developing Countries. London: Nuffield Council.
Ottawa Charter (1986). Ottawa Charter for Health Promotion. Presented at the first International Conference on Health Promotion, Ottawa, 1986.
Petersen, A. and Lupton, D. (1996). The New Public Health: Health and Self in the Age of Risk. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Ravelli, A. C. J., Meulen, J. H. P., Osmond, C., Barker, D. J. P. and Bleker, O. (1999). Obesity at the age of 50 years in men and women exposed to famine prenatally. Am. J. Clin. Nutr., 70, 811–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, R. (2001). The fetal origins of adult disease. BMJ, 322, 375–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rose, G. (1992). The Strategy of Preventive Medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roth, R. (2000). Making Women Pay: the Hidden Costs of Fetal Rights. New York, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rush D. (1989). Effects of changes in maternal energy and protein intake during pregnancy, with special reference to fetal growth. In Fetal Growth (ed. Sharp, F., Fraser, R. B. and Milner, R. D. G.). London: Royal College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists, pp. 203–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scholl, T. O., Hediger, M. L. and Ances, I. G. (1990). Maternal growth during pregnancy and decreased infant birth weight. Am. J. Clin. Nutr., 51, 790–3.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spencer, N. (2000). Poverty and Child Health, 2nd edn. Oxford: Radcliffe Medical Press.Google Scholar
Tones, K. (1988). Health education and the promotion of health: seeking wisely to empower. In Health and Empowerment: Research and Practice (ed. Kendall, S.). London: Arnold, pp. 57–88.Google Scholar
Townsend, P., Davidson, N. and Whitehead, M., eds. (1988). Inequalities in Health: The Black Report and the Health Divide. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
University of Southampton (2003). Centre for the Origins of Adult Disease. Press release, 5 June 2003.
Villar, J., Merialdi, M., Gulmezoglu, A. M.et al. (2003). Characteristics of randomized controlled trials included in systematic reviews of nutritional interventions reporting maternal morbidity, mortality, preterm delivery, intrauterine growth restriction and small for gestational age and birth weight outcomes. J. Nutr., 133, 1632–9S.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilkinson, R. (2000). Mind the Gap: Heirarchies, Health and Human Evolution. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.Google Scholar
World Health Organization (1978). Declaration of Alma-Ata. ‘Health for All’ series, no. 1. Geneva: WHO.
World Medical Association (1964). Declaration of Helisnki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects. Adopted by the 18th WMA General Assembly, Helsinki, Finland, June 1964.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×