Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T17:44:40.790Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Learning from Error, Severe Testing, and the Growth of Theoretical Knowledge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 January 2010

Deborah G. Mayo
Affiliation:
Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University
Aris Spanos
Affiliation:
Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University
Get access

Summary

I regard it as an outstanding and pressing problem in the philosophy of the natural sciences to augment the insights of the new experimentalists with a correspondingly updated account of the role or roles of theory in the experimental sciences, substantiated by detailed case studies.

(Chalmers, 1999, p. 251)

Background to the Discussion

The goal of this chapter is to take up the aforementioned challenge as it is posed by Alan Chalmers (1999, 2002), John Earman (1992), Larry Laudan (1997), and other philosophers of science. It may be seen as a first step in taking up some unfinished business noted a decade ago: “How far experimental knowledge can take us in understanding theoretical entities and processes is not something that should be decided before exploring this approach much further” (Mayo, 1996, p. 13). We begin with a sketch of the resources and limitations of the “new experimentalist” philosophy.

Learning from evidence, in this experimentalist philosophy, depends not on appraising large-scale theories but on local experimental tasks of estimating backgrounds, modeling data, distinguishing experimental effects, and discriminating signals from noise. The growth of knowledge has not to do with replacing or confirming or probabilifying or “rationally accepting” large-scale theories, but with testing specific hypotheses in such a way that there is a good chance of learning something – whatever theory it winds up as part of.

Type
Chapter
Information
Error and Inference
Recent Exchanges on Experimental Reasoning, Reliability, and the Objectivity and Rationality of Science
, pp. 28 - 57
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ben Haim, Y. (2001), Information-Gap Decision Theory: Decisions Under Severe Uncertainty, Academic Press, San Diego, CA.Google Scholar
Chalmers, A. (1999), What Is This Thing Called Science? 3rd ed., Open University Press, and University of Queensland Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, A. (2002), “Experiment and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge,” pp. 157–70 in Proceedings of the International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science (Vol. 1 of the 11th International Congress of Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Cracow, August 1999), Gardenfors, P., Wolenski, J., and Kijania-Placek, K. (eds.). Kluwer, Dordrecht, The Netherlands.Google Scholar
Cox, D.R. (2006), Principles of Statistical Inference, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damour, T., and Taylor, T.H. (1991), “On the Orbital Period Change of the Binary Pulsar PSR 1913 + 16,” Astrophysical Journal, 366: 501–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorling, J. (1979), “Bayesian Personalism, the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, and Duhem's Problem,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 10: 177–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, J. (1992), Bayes or Bust: A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Fitelson, B. (2002), “Putting the Irrelevance Back into the Problem of Irrelevant Conjunction,” Philosophy of Science, 69: 611–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence, Princeton University Press, Princeton.Google Scholar
Good, I.J. (1983), Good Thinking, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.Google Scholar
Jeffreys, W., and Berger, J. (1992), “Ockham's Razor and Bayesian Analysis,” American Scientist, 80: 64–72.Google Scholar
Kass, R.E., and Wasserman, L. (1996), “Formal Rules of Selecting Prior Distributions: A Review and Annotated Bibliography,” Journal of the American Statistical Association, 91: 1343–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kyburg, H.E.. (1993), “The Scope of Bayesian Reasoning,” in Hull, D., Forbes, M., and Okruhlik, K. (eds.), PSA 1992, Vol. II, East Lansing, MI.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and Its Problems, University of California Press, Berkeley.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1997), “How About Bust? Factoring Explanatory Power Back into Theory Evaluation,” Philosophy of Science, 64:303–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lobo, J. (1996), “Sources of Gravitational Waves,” pp. 203–22 in Hall, G.S. and Pulham, J.R. (eds.), General Relativity: Proceedings of the Forty-Sixth Scottish Universities Summer School in Physics, SUSSP Publications, Edinburgh, and Institute of Physics, London.Google Scholar
Mayo, D.G. (1991), “Novel Evidence and Severe Tests.” Philosophy of Science, 58(4): 523–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.G. (1996), Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.G. (1997a), “Duhem's Problem, the Bayesian Way, and Error Statistics, or ‘What's Belief Got to Do with It?’” and “Response to Howson and Laudan,” Philosophy of Science, 64: 222–44, 323–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.G. (1997b), “Severe Tests, Arguing from Error, and Methodological Underdetermination,” Philosophical Studies, 86: 243–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.G. (2000), “Experimental Practice and an Error Statistical Account of Evidence.” Philosophy of Science 67, (Proceedings). Edited by Howard, D.. Pages S193–S207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.G. (2002), “Theory Testing, Statistical Methodology, and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge,” pp. 171–90 in Proceedings of the International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science (Vol. 1 of the 11th International Congress of Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Cracow, August 1999), Gardenfors, P., Wolenski, J., and Kijania-Placek, K. (eds.). Kluwer, Dordrecht, The Netherlands.Google Scholar
Mayo, D.G. (2006), “Critical Rationalism and Its Failure to Withstand Critical Scrutiny,” pp. 63–96 in Cheyne, C. and Worrall, J. (eds.), Rationality and Reality: Conversations with Alan Musgrave, Springer, Dordrecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.G., and Spanos, A. (2006), “Severe Testing as a Basic Concept in a Neyman–Pearson Philosophy of Induction,” British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 57(2): 323–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, M., and Morgan, M. (eds.) (1999), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Suppes, P. (1969), “Models of Data,” pp. 24–35 in Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Will, C.M. (1980), “General Relativity,” pp. 309–21 in Ehlers, J., Perry, J.J., and Walker, M. (eds.), Ninth Texas Symposium on Relativistic Astrophysics, New York Academy of Sciences, New York.Google Scholar
Will, C.M. (1986), Was Einstein Right?Basic Books, New York (reprinted 1993).Google Scholar
Will, C.M. (1993), Theory and Experiment in Gravitational Physics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Will, C.M. (1996), “The Confrontation Between General Relativity and Experiment. A 1995 Update,” pp. 239–81 in Hall, G.S. and J, Pulham, General Relativity: Proceedings of the Forty Sixth Scottish Universities Summer School in Physics, SUSSP Publications, Edinburgh, and Institute of Physics, London.Google Scholar
Will, C.M. (2004), “The Confrontation Between General Relativity and Experiment,” Living Reviews in Relativity, http://relativity.livingreviews.org/Articles/lrr-2001-4/title.html.
Will, C.M. (2005), “Relativity at the Centenary,” Physics World, 18: 27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1989), “Fresnel, Poisson and the White Spot: The Role of Successful Predictions in the Acceptance of Scientific Theories,” pp. 135–57 in Gooding, D., Pinch, T., and Schaffer, S. (eds.), The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. (1993), “Falsification, Rationality and the Duhem Problem: Grünbaum vs Bayes,” pp. 329–70 in Earman, J., Janis, A.I., Massey, G.J., and Rescher, N. (eds.), Philosophical Problems of the Internal and External Worlds, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×