Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5b777bbd6c-7sgmh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-06-25T16:00:09.319Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 4 - Existence, ontological commitment, and fictional entities

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Peter van Inwagen
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

Meinong has famously (or notoriously) said, “There are objects of which it is true that there are no such objects.” What could have led him to make such an extraordinary statement? He was, or so he saw matters, driven to say that there were objects of which it was true that there were no such objects by data for which only the truth of this extraordinary statement could account. These data were of two sorts: linguistic and psychological. The linguistic data consisted of sentences like the following and what seemed to be obvious facts about them:

The Cheshire Cat spoke to Alice

The round square is an impossible object

Pegasus was the winged horse captured by Bellerophon.

The obvious facts were these: first, each of these sentences is or expresses a truth; secondly, the result of writing ‘There is no such thing as’ and then the subject of any of these sentences is, or expresses, a truth. (I so use ‘subject’ that the subject of ‘the Taj Mahal is white’ is ‘the Taj Mahal’ and not the Taj Mahal. I use ‘there is no such thing as’ to mean ‘there is no such thing as, and there never was or will be any such thing as’.) Thus, for example, it is true that the Cheshire Cat spoke to Alice, and it is also true that there is no such thing as the Cheshire Cat. We have, therefore, the following general truth:

There are true subject-predicate sentences (i.e. subject-predicate sentences that express truths when uttered in appropriate contexts) such that the result of writing ‘there is no such thing as’ and following this phrase with the subject of any of these sentences is true.

Type
Chapter
Information
Existence
Essays in Ontology
, pp. 87 - 115
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Meinong, Alexius, “Über Gegenstandstheorie,” Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe, ed. Haller, Rudolf and Kindinger, Rudolf in collaboration with Roderick M. Chisholm [Graz: Akademische Druck und Verlagsanstalt, 1969–73]), p. 490Google Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick M., “Beyond Being and Non-Being,” New Readings in Philosophical Analysis, ed. Feigl, Herbert, Sellars, Wilfrid, and Lehrer, Keith (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1972), pp. 15–22, at p. 15Google Scholar
Walton, Kendall L., Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), pp. 416–419Google Scholar
Lewis, David, “Noneism and Allism?”, Mind 99 (1990): 23–31Google Scholar
I refer the reader to “Why I Don't Understand Substitutional Quantification,” Philosophical Studies 39 (1981): 281–285
Ontology, Identity, and Modality: Essays in Metaphysics (Cambridge University Press, 2001)
Routley, Richard, Exploring Meinong's Jungle and Beyond: An Investigation of Noneism and the Theory of Items, monograph 3, Philosophy Department, Research School of Social Sciences (Canberra: Australian National University, 1980)Google Scholar
Parsons, Terence, “A Meinongian Analysis of Fictional Objects,” Grazer Philosophische Studien 1 (1975): 73–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Non-Existent Objects (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980)
Castaneda, Hector-Neri, “Fiction and Reality: Their Relations and Connections,” Poetics 8 (199): 31–62CrossRef
Howell, Robert (“Fictional Objects: How they Are and How they Aren't,” Poetics 8 [1979]: 129–77, at 130)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, The Nature of Necessity [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974]Google Scholar
Crittenden, CharlesUnreality: The Metaphysics of Fictional Objects (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991)Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter, “Creatures of Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977): 299–308Google Scholar
“Fiction and Metaphysics,” Philosophy and Literature 7 (1983): 67–77
“Pretense and Paraphrase,” The Reasons of Art, ed. McCormick, Peter J. (University of Ottawa Press, 1985), pp. 414–422
Quine, classic essay “On What There Is,” in his From a Logical Point of View, 2nd edn. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1961), pp. 1–19Google Scholar
Word and Object (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1960)
Church, Alonzo, “Ontological Commitment,” Journal of Philosophy 55 (1958): 1008–1014CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Richard, “Ontology and the Theory of Meaning,” Philosophy of Science 21 (1954): 316–325CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philosophical Essays (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 1–12
, David and Lewis, Stephanie classic paper “Holes” (Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48 [1970]: 206–212CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, Philosophical Papers, volume I [Oxford University Press, 1983], pp. 3–9)Google Scholar
Gellner, Ernest, “The Last Pragmatist, or the Behaviourist Platonist,” Spectacles and Predicaments: Essays in Social Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 199–208, at p. 203Google Scholar
“Creatures of Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977): 299–308
Ontology, Identity, and Modality: Essays in Metaphysics [Cambridge University Press, 2001], pp. 37–56
in van Inwagen, Peter, “The Nature of Metaphysics,” Contemporary Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics, ed. Laurence, Stephen and Macdonald, Cynthia (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998), pp. 11–21Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, Nicholas, Worlds and Works of Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie I., “The Artifactual Theory of Fiction,” paper presented at Empty Names, Fiction, and the Puzzles of Non-Existence, CSLI conference, Stanford University, 1998, and Fiction and Metaphysics (Cambridge University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Zalta, Edward, Abstract Objects (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Intensional Logic and the Metaphysics of Intensionality (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988)
Salmon, Nathan in “Nonexistence,” Noûs 32 (1998): 277–319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David marvelously subtle “Truth in Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (1978): 37–46Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, Nicholas, Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): esp. 187–188

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×