Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-20T12:48:59.067Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

20 - Commitment

from Part VI - Dynamic games

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2012

Aviad Heifetz
Affiliation:
Open University of Israel
Get access

Summary

Commitment to action

In section 19.3.1, we described the Stackelberg model, in which one firm is the first to decide what quantity to produce, while the other firm decides what quantity it will produce only after having observed how much the first firm has produced. We saw that at the unique subgame perfect equilibrium of the game, the leading firm effectively chooses the combination of quantities that will maximize its profits from among all the combinations of quantities on its rival’s reaction curve. But in this combination of quantities, the quantity that the first firm produces does not constitute a best reply to the quantity that the second firm ultimately produces: if, after the second firm has chosen its strategy at a Stackelberg equilibrium, the first firm were to get a chance to change its mind and produce a smaller quantity than it had already produced, then it would certainly prefer to do so. Thus, the leading firm’s advantage is reflected in the fact that by its action, it can commit and bind itself to an action that at the end of the day is not necessarily optimal for it. The leading firm’s loss redounds to its advantage, since its commitment to an “over-aggressive” strategy leads its rival to behave “submissively.”

In the decision problem of a unique decision maker, the decision maker can derive no advantage from deciding to adopt an action which will prove, in retrospect, to have been suboptimal for her. One of the most important insights of game theory is that in strategic situations, a player’s ability to commit to her strategy – a strategy that is not necessarily optimal, given the reactions of her rivals – can secure her an important advantage.

Type
Chapter
Information
Game Theory
Interactive Strategies in Economics and Management
, pp. 333 - 352
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Robinson, J. A.Ragnar, T.Verdier, T. 2006 Political Foundations of the Resource CurseJournal of Development Economics 79 447CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×