Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vvkck Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T03:23:28.800Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Other atomists, other skeptics, and other Epicureans: the problem of determining the context of Gassendi's career

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 September 2009

Get access

Summary

Ever since Bernier's popular French translation of his work in the 1670s, Gassendi has had to be defended against an unusual charge, the charge that he was only a historian of philosophy. Scholars have pinned this label to his work not because they did not recognize his skills as a philosopher and scientist but because at a certain point in assessing his philosophical and scientific achievements, they have sought to explain why those achievements do not merit unqualified praise. If Gassendi is significant as a theorizer about atoms, he can be faulted for the apparent naïveté of the experiments he used to test his theories. If he is significant for advancing arguments against Aristotle's metaphysics, he may be counted as just one of a growing number of sixteenth- and seventeenth-century philosophers who were critical of the standard university curriculum. If he is significant as a skeptic during a period of the revival of Pyrrhonian and Academic skepticism in Europe, he suffers from an implicit comparison with his contemporary, Descartes, whose skepticism proved to be more fruitful in the development of modern epistemology than his. However, interpreters of his writings have been reluctant simply to call Gassendi second-rate. The sheer volume, complexity, and scope of his Opera omnia do command a respect which goes beyond the limited acknowledgment of his contributions to empiricism in philosophy and to the newly mathematized physics, both of which captivated the attention of intellectuals in the half-century after his death in 1655.

Type
Chapter
Information
Gassendi the Atomist
Advocate of History in an Age of Science
, pp. 3 - 22
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×