Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2012
Introduction
What role does one’s community play in determining one’s meaning – in fixing the content of what is available to individual members of that community to do or to say? Heidegger, for one, has argued that our activities are heavily constrained by social factors. We always act within a public realm, which is already organized and interpreted in a determinate way. As a consequence, Heidegger explains, we are “constantly delivered over to this interpretedness, which controls and distributes the possibilities” available to us for action (GA 2: H. 167). Indeed, Heidegger argues that our being “delivered over” to the public interpretation of things is an inescapable feature of human existence. What is true of action in general is also true for our use of language. Heidegger claims that in language itself there is hidden an “understanding of the disclosed world” (GA 2: H. 168). So not just our possibilities for practical engagement with the things and people around us but even the possible range of what we can say is subject in some way to others.
One consequence of social constraints on language, Heidegger believes, is a tendency on the part of speakers to fall into a superficial imitation of the kinds of things that others in their linguistic community say. He calls such speech Gerede, which is generally translated as “idle talk.” Gerede is the everyday mode of Rede, which is generally translated as “discourse.” For reasons to be explained later, I will translate Rede as “conversation,” and Gerede as “idle conversation.” Heidegger tells us that in idle conversation, one understands things “only approximately and superficially”: “one does not so much understand those entities about which one converses [das beredete Seiende], but rather one listens only to what is said in the conversation as such [das Geredete als solches]” (GA 2: H. 168). Or, as he puts it elsewhere, this kind of idle conversation “releases one from the task of true understanding” (GA 2: H. 169).
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.