Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-zzh7m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T07:00:00.919Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Semiotic freedom: an emerging force

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Jesper Hoffmeyer
Affiliation:
University of Copenhagen
Paul Davies
Affiliation:
Arizona State University
Niels Henrik Gregersen
Affiliation:
University of Copenhagen
Get access

Summary

The term “information” has become nearly omnipresent in modern biology (and medicine). One would probably not exaggerate if the famous saying of evolutionary biologist Theodosius Dobhzhansky, that “nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution” should nowadays be reframed as “nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of information.” But are those two concepts, evolution and information, somehow internally related? And if so, how?

Information in evolution

In textbooks, newspapers, and even scientific papers, the meanings of the terms “evolution” and “information” are generally supposed to be well known, and they are rarely explained. And yet, there is no general consensus in science, or even in biology, about what they really mean. For instance, the preferred exemplar (in the Kuhnian sense) of evolution by natural selection is that of industrial melanism. In woodlands, where industrial pollution has killed the lichens and exposed the dark brown tree trunks, dark forms of the peppered moth – melanics – are supposedly better camouflaged against predation from birds than are the light gray forms that predominated before the Industrial Revolution. The observation by 1950 that darker forms had largely displaced lighter forms was thus taken as evidence for natural selection in action. This exemplar does indeed illustrate the effect of natural selection, but whether it shows evolution depends on your idea of evolution. Thus, if by the term “evolution” is meant something like “the origin of species,” then it is remarkable that no speciation has actually taken place here, and it is not obvious that any speciation would indeed occur in a case like this. So, populations do indeed change as a result of natural selection, but is this mechanism also behind speciation and evolution at large? The majority of biologists certainly feel assured that macroevolution – that is, evolution above the level of species – is in fact the tardy result of an infinitely ongoing microevolution (adaptation in populations), but there remains serious disagreement on this (Depew and Weber, 1995; Gould, 2002).

Type
Chapter
Information
Information and the Nature of Reality
From Physics to Metaphysics
, pp. 236 - 260
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bruni, L. E. (2007). Cellular semiotics and signal transduction. In Cellular Semiotics and Signal Transduction, ed. Barbieri, M.Dordrecht: Springer, 365–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, D. T. (1974). “Downward causation” in hierarchically organised biological systems. In Downward Causation, eds Ayala, F. I. and Dobzhansky, T.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 179–186.Google Scholar
Clayton, P., and Kauffman, S. (2006). On emergence, agency, and organization. Biology and Philosophy, 21: 501–521.Google Scholar
Deacon, T. (1997). The Symbolic Species. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Deacon, T., and Sherman, J. (2008). The pattern which connects pleroma to creatura: The autocell bridge from physics to life. In A Legacy for Living Systems: Gregory Bateson as Precursor to Biosemiotics, ed. Hoffmeyer, J.. Dordrecht: Springer, 59–76.Google Scholar
Deely, J. (2007). Intentionality and Semiotics: A Story of Mutual Fecundation. Scranton, PA: University of Scranton Press.Google Scholar
Depew, D. J., and Weber, B. H. (1995). Darwinism Evolving: Systems Dynamics and the Genealogy of Natural Selection. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gibbs, W. (2001). Cybernetic cells. Scientific American, August, 285: 52–57.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gordon, D. M. (1995). The development of organization in an ant colony. American Scientist, 83: 50–57.Google Scholar
Gordon, D. (1999). Ants at Work. How an Insect Society is Organized. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gray, R., Griffiths, P., and Oyama, S. (2001). Cycles of Contingency. Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Griffiths, P. E., and Gray, R. D. (1994). Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 91 (6): 277–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmeyer, J. (1996). Signs of Meaning in the Universe. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Hoffmeyer, J. (1998). Semiosis and biohistory: A reply. Semiotica, 120 (3/4): 455–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmeyer, J., and Kull, H. (2003). Baldwin and biosemiotics: What intelligence is for. In Evolution and Learning, eds Weber, B. and Depew, D. J.. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 253–272.Google Scholar
Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Biosemiotics. An Examination into the Signs of Life and the Life of Signs. Scranton, PA: University of Scranton Press.Google Scholar
Kauffman, S. (1993). Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kauffman, S. A. (2000). Investigations. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McFall-Ngai, M. J., and Ruby, E. G. (1998). Sepiolids and vibrios: When first they meet. BioScience, 48: 257–265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, S. (1996). Biological information: A skeptical look at some central dogmas of molecular biology. In The Philosophy and History of Molecular Biology: New Perspectives, ed. Sarkar, S.. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 187–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scriver, C. R., and Waters, P. J. (1999). Monogenic traits are not simple. Trends in Genetics, 15(7): 267–272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ulanowicz, R. E. (2009). A Third Window: Natural Foundations for Life. Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology. The New Synthesis. London: Belknap Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×