Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-12T23:44:09.649Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 November 2018

James M. Ambury
Affiliation:
King's College, Pennsylvania
Andy German
Affiliation:
Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel
Get access

Summary

In this chapter, the author addresses how Plato’s treatment of self-knowledge in the late dialogues ought to impact our views on the placement and authenticity of the Alcibiades I. While this dialogue identifies self-knowledge as knowledge of soul, a dialogue such as the Philebus seems far more concerned with self-ignorance. Indeed, its threefold division of self-ignorance actually seems to render problematic the exclusive equivalence of self-knowledge with knowledge of soul. The author argues that there is nothing in the Alcibiades I that would suggest a theoretical affinity between it and the hiatus-avoiding dialogues such as the Sophist, Statesman, Timaeus, Critias, Philebus, Laws, and the Clitophon (if it is indeed by Plato). Generally, the later dialogues signal a fundamental shift in Plato’s thinking on self-knowledge. Whereas earlier dialogues contained a positive doctrine of self-knowledge – which entails a deep awareness of the core of human being that is the ground of virtuous life – the later dialogues give self-knowledge a predominantly negative valence; i.e., it is a condition of freedom from false convictions and their accompanying, mistaken belief that one knows.
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Aeschylus, . 1977. The Oresteia. Translated by Fagles, Robert. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Anonymous. 2011. Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy. Translated by Westerink, L. G.. Wiltshire, UK: Prometheus Trust.Google Scholar
Anthologie Grecque (Anthologie Palatine). 1960. Vol. 4. Edited by Waltz, Pierre. Paris: Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1936. Physics. Edited by Ross, W. D.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1957. Metaphysica. Edited by Jaeger, Werner. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1957. On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath. Translated by Hett, W. S.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Aronadio, Francesco, ed. 2008. Dialoghi spuri di Platone. Torino: Unione tipografico-editrice Torinese.Google Scholar
Bailly, Jacques. 2004. The Socratic Theages: Introduction, English Translation, Greek Text and Commentary. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag.Google Scholar
Burnet, John, ed. 1900–1907. Platonis Opera. 6 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, Myles F. 1990. The Theaetetus of Plato, trans. Levett, M. J., revised by Burnyeat, Myles. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Cooper, John, ed. 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Denyer, Nicholas, ed. 2001. Plato: Alcibiades. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dover, Kenneth, ed. 1980. Plato: Symposium. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Duke, E. A., Hicken, W. F., Nicholl, W. S. M, Robinson, D. B., and Strachan, J. C. G., eds. 1995. Platonis Opera: Tomus I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Euripides, . 1960. Iphigenia in Tauris. In Greek Tragedies. Vol. 2. Translated by Green, David and Lattimore, Richmond. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gill, Mary L., and Ryan, Paul, trans. 1996. Plato: Parmenides. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Hamilton, Edith, and Cairns, Huntington, eds. 1961. Plato: The Collected Dialogues, Including the Letters. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Herodotus, . 1992. The Histories. Translated by Blanco, Walter. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Hesiod, . 2000. Works and Days. In Homeric Hymns, Epic Cycle, Homerica. Translated by Evelyn-White, Hugh G.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hippocrates, . 1978. Hippocratic Writings. Translated by Chadwick, J. and Mann, W. N.. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Homer, . 1996. The Odyssey. Translated by Fagles, Robert. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Homer, . 1997. Iliad. Translated by Lombardo, Stanley. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Johnson, David M., trans. 2003. Socrates and Alcibiades: Four Texts. Newburyport, MA: Focus.Google Scholar
Joyal, Mark. 2000. The Platonic Theages: An Introduction, Commentary and Critical Edition. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.Google Scholar
Olympiodorus, . 1982. Commentary on the First Alcibiades of Plato. Edited by Westerink, L. G.. Amsterdam: Hakkert. Original edition, 1956.Google Scholar
Olympiodorus, . 2016. On Plato First Alcibiades 10–28. Translated by Griffin, Michael. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Pindar, . 1882. “Fragment 131.” In Selected Odes. Translated by Seymour, Thomas D.. Boston, MA: Gin, Heath, & Co.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1914. Apology. Translated by Fowler, H. N.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1914. Phaedo. Translated by Fowler, H. N.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1921. Theaetetus. Translated by Fowler, H. N.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1924. Meno. Translated by Lamb, W. R.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1925. Symposium. Translated by Fowler, H. N.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1926. Laws. Translated by Bury, R. G.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1927a. Charmides. Translated by Lamb, W. R.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1927b. Alcibiades I. Translated by Lamb, W. R.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1932. Gorgias. Translated by Lamb, W. R.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1970. Symposium. Translated by Groden, Suzy. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1973. Laches and Charmides. Translated by Sprague, Rosamond Kent. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill & Co.Google Scholar
Plato, . 1991. Republic. Translated by Bloom, Allan. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Plato, . 2003: Rempublicam. Edited by Slings, S. R.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Plotinus, . 1966. Enneads. Translated by Armstrong, A. H.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Proclus, . 1899–1901. Procli Diadochi in Platonis rem publicam commentarii. Edited by Kroll, W.. 2 vols. Leipzig: Teubner (reprint, Amsterdam: Hakkert, 1965).Google Scholar
Proclus, . 1971. Commentary on the First Alcibiades of Plato. Translated by O’Neil, William. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Proclus, . 1995. The Platonic Theology. Translated by Taylor, Thomas. Wiltshire, UK: Prometheus Trust.Google Scholar
Proclus, . 2007. On Plato Cratylus. Translated by Duvick, Brian. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Sophocles, . 1994. Philoctetes. In Sophocles, volume II. Translated by Jones, Hugh-Lloyd. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sprague, Rosamund Kent, ed. 1972. The Older Sophists. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Thucydides, . 1900. Historiae: Tomus Prior. Edited by Jones, H. S.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
West, Thomas G., and West, Grace Starry, trans. 1986. Plato: Charmides. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Yunis, Harvey, ed. 2011. Plato: Phaedrus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Adam, James. [1902] 1963. The Republic of Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor. 1982. “Freudian Theory and the Pattern of Fascist Propaganda.” In The Essential Frankfurt School Reader. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Ambury, James M. 2011. “The Place of Displacement: The Elenchus in Plato’s Alcibiades I.” Ancient Philosophy 31 (2): 241260.Google Scholar
Ambury, James M. 2014. “Socratic Character: Proclus on the Function of Erotic Intellect.” In The Neoplatonic Socrates, edited by Layne, Danielle A. and Tarrant, Harold, 109117. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Ambury, James M. 2015. “Plato’s Conception of Soul as Intelligent Self-Determination.” International Philosophical Quarterly 55 (3): 299313.Google Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1981. Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1985. “Self-Knowledge in Early Plato.” In Platonic Investigations, edited by O’Meara, Dominic, 111138. Washington: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1988. “Self-Love in Aristotle.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 27: 118.Google Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1999. Platonic Ethics, Old and New. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, John M. 2004. “After the Ascent: Plato on Becoming like a God.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 26: 171–83.Google Scholar
Asmis, Elizabeth. 1986. “Psychagogia in Plato’s Phaedrus.” Illinois Studies in Classical Philology 11: 153172.Google Scholar
Avnon, Dan. 1995. “Know Thyself: Socratic Companionship and Platonic Community.” Political Theory 23: 304329.Google Scholar
Ballard, Edward. 1965. Socratic Ignorance: An Essay on Platonic Self-Knowledge. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Baltzly, Dirk. 2004. “The Virtues and ‘Becoming like a God’: Alcinous to Proclus.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 26: 297322.Google Scholar
Baracchi, Claudia. 2014. “One Good: The Mathematics of Ethics.” Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 25 (2): 1949.Google Scholar
Belfiore, Elizabeth S. 2012. Socrates’ Daimonic Art: Love for Wisdom in Four Platonic Dialogues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Benardete, Seth. 1953. “The Daimonion of Socrates: A Study of Plato’s Theages.” Master’s thesis, University of Chicago.Google Scholar
Benardete, Seth. 1984. Plato’s Sophist. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Benardete, Seth. 2007. Plato’s Theaetetus: Part I of the Being of the Beautiful. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Benatouïl, Thomas. 2006. Faire usage: le pratique du stoïcisme. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Benitez, Eugenio, and Guimaraes, Livia. 1993. “Philosophy as Performed in Plato’s Theaetetus.” The Review of Metaphysics 47 (2): 297328.Google Scholar
Benson, Hugh. 2003. “A Note on Socratic Self-Knowledge in the Charmides.” Ancient Philosophy 23: 3147.Google Scholar
Bentley, Russell. 2005. “On Plato’s Phaedrus: Politics beyond the City Walls.” Polis 22: 230248.Google Scholar
Bersani, L., and Phillips, A. 2008. Intimacies. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Biral, A. 1997. Platone e la conoscenza di sé. Roma-Bari: Laterza.Google Scholar
Blondell, Ruby 2002. The Play of Character in Plato’s Dialogues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bobonich, Christopher. 2013. Plato’s Laws: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bosanquet, Bernard. 1895. A Companion to Plato’s Republic for English Readers. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Bowery, Anne Marie. 2007. “Know Thyself: Socrates as Storyteller.” In Philosophy in Dialogue: Plato’s Many Devices, edited by Scott, Gary Alan, 82110. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Boyle, A. J. 1974. “Plato’s Divided Line. Essay II: Mathematics and Dialectic.” Apeiron 8: 721.Google Scholar
Brandwood, Leonard. 1990. The Chronology of Plato’s Dialogues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, Thomas C., and Smith, Nicholas D. 1983. “The Origin of Socrates’ Mission.” Journal of the History of Ideas 44: 657666.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, Thomas C., and Smith, Nicholas D. 1984. “The Paradox of Socratic Ignorance in Plato’s Apology.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1 (2): 125131.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, Thomas C., and Smith, Nicholas D. 1989. Socrates on Trial. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, Thomas C., and Smith, Nicholas D. 1994. Plato’s Socrates. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brill, Sara. 2016. “Greek Philosophy in the 21st Century.” Oxford Handbooks Online. Last modified June 2016. Available at www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199935390.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780199935390-e-70?rskey=TYtNSl&result=1.Google Scholar
Brown, Eric A. 2000. “Justice and Compulsion for Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers.” Ancient Philosophy 20 (1): 117.Google Scholar
Bruell, Christopher. 1997. “Socratic Politics and Self-Knowledge: An Interpretation of Plato’s Charmides.” Interpretation 6: 141203.Google Scholar
Brunschwig, Jacques. 1996. “La Déconstruction du «Connais-toi toi-même» dans l’Alcibiade Majeur.” Recherches sur la Philosophie et le Langage 18: 6184.Google Scholar
Brunschwig, Jacques. 1999. “Revisiting Plato’s Cave.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 19: 145173.Google Scholar
Burger, Ronna. 1980. Plato’s Phaedrus: A Defense of a Philosophic Art of Writing. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.Google Scholar
Burkert, Walter. 1985. Greek Religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Burnet, John. 1923. The Socratic Doctrine of the Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, Myles F. 1997. “Culture and Society in Plato’s Republic.” The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 20: 217324. http://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/b/Burnyeat99.pdf.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, Myles F. 2000. “Plato on Why Mathematics Is Good for the Soul.” Proceedings of the British Academy 103: 181.Google Scholar
Cain, Rebecca Bensen. 2007. The Socratic Method: Plato’s Use of Philosophical Drama. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Capra, Andrea. 2014. Plato’s Four Muses: The Phaedrus and the Poetics of Philosophy. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies.Google Scholar
Carone, Gabriella. 1998. “Socrates’ Human Wisdom and Sōphrosunē in Charmides 164cff.” Ancient Philosophy 18: 267286.Google Scholar
Carvalho, John. 2014. “Socrates’ Refutation of Apollo: A Note on Apology 21b7–c2.” Journal of Ancient Philosophy 8: 4056.Google Scholar
Chroust, Anton-Hermann. 1965. “The Organization of the Corpus Platonicum in Antiquity.” Hermes 93 (1): 3446.Google Scholar
Cobb, William S. 1992. “Plato’s Theages.” Ancient Philosophy 12: 267284.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1999. Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cornford, Francis M. 1932. “Mathematics and Dialectic in the Republic VI–VII (II).” Mind 41 (162): 173190.Google Scholar
Courcelle, Pierre, 1974. Connais-toi toi-mēme de Socrate à Saint Bernard. Paris: Etudes Augustiniennes.Google Scholar
Cross, R. C., and Woozley, A. D. 1964. Plato’s Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
DeHaas, Frans. 2010. “Know Thyself: Plato and Aristotle on Awareness.” In Ancient Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Anima, edited by van Reel, Gerd and Déstree, Pierre, 4970. Leuven: Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Detienne, Marcel. 1999. The Masters of Truth in Archaic Greece. Translated by Lloyd, Janet. New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Dillon, John M. 2003. The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy, 347–274 B.C. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dixsaut, Monique. 2002. Métamorphoses de la Dialectique dans les Dialogues de Platon. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Dorter, Kenneth. 1990. “Diaresis and the Tripartite Soul in the Sophist.” Ancient Philosophy 10: 4161.Google Scholar
Eisenstadt, Michael. 1981. “A Note on Charmides 168e9–169a1.” Hermes 109: 126128.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. R. F. 1987. Listening to the Cicadas: A Study of Plato’s Phaedrus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Forster, Michael. 2007. “Socratic Ignorance.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 32: 135.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1978. The History of Sexuality, volume 1. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Freud, Sigmund. 1990. Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego. Translated by Strachey, J. W. W.. New York: Norton Press.Google Scholar
Friedländer, Paul. 1958. Plato: An Introduction. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Friedländer, Paul. 1964. Plato, volume II: The Dialogues First Period. Translated by Meyerhoff, Hans. New York: Pantheon.Google Scholar
Friedländer, Paul. 1969. Plato, volume III: The Dialogues, Second and Third Periods. Translated by Meyerhoff, Hans. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1980. Dialogue and Dialectic: Eight Hermeneutical Studies on Plato. Translated by Smith, P. Christopher. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1986. The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy. Translated by Smith, P. Christopher. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
German, Andy. 2017. “Is Socrates Free? The Theaetetus as Case Study.” British Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (4): 621641.Google Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd P. 1992. “The Ignorance of Socrates.” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 66: 123135.Google Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd P. 2003. Knowing Persons: A Study in Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd P. 2015. “Ideas of Good?” In Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato, edited by Nails, Debra and Tarrant, Harold, 225242. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica.Google Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd P. 2016. “The ‘Neoplatonic’ Interpretation of Plato’s Parmenides.” International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 10 (1): 6594.Google Scholar
Giannopoulou, Zina. 2015. “Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Theaetetus and Alcibiades I.” Boston Area Colloquium for Ancient Philosophy 30: 7393.Google Scholar
Gill, Christopher. 1985. “Plato and the Education of Character.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 67: 126.Google Scholar
Gill, Christopher. 2007. “Self-knowledge in Plato’s Alcibiades.” In Reading Ancient Texts, volume I: Presocratics and Plato, edited by Stern-Gillet, Suzanne and Corrigan, Kevin, 95112. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Gill, Mary L. 2012. Philosophos: Plato’s Missing Dialogue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gonzalez, Francisco J. 1995. “Self-Knowledge, Practical Knowledge and Insight.” In The Third Way: New Directions in Platonic Studies, edited by Gonzalez, Francisco, 155188. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Gonzalez, Francisco J. 1998. Dialectic and Dialogue: Plato’s Practice of Philosophical Inquiry. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Gooch, Paul W. 1971. “‘Vice Is Ignorance’: The Interpretation of Sophist 226a–231b.” Phoenix 25: 124133.Google Scholar
Gordon, Jill. 1999. Turning toward Philosophy: Literary Device and Dramatic Structure in Plato’s Dialogues. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Gordon, Jill. 2012. Plato’s Erotic World: From Cosmic Origins to Human Death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Graver, M. 2008. The Stoics on Emotions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Griswold, Charles. 1981. “Self-Knowledge and the ‘ἰδέα’ of the Soul in Plato’s Phaedrus.” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 86 (4): 477494.Google Scholar
Griswold, Charles. 1986. Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Phaedrus. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Grote, George. 1888. Plato and the Other Companions of Sokrates, volume 1. London: J. Murray.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1992. “Themes in Post-Metaphysical Thinking.” In Philosophical Interventions in the Unfinished Project of Enlightenment, edited by Honneth, Axel, McCarthy, Thomas, Offe, Klaus, and Wellmer, Albrecht, 2853. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hackforth, Reginald. 1942. “Plato’s Divided Line and Dialectic.” Classical Quarterly 36: 19.Google Scholar
Hackforth, Reginald. 1946. “Moral Evil and Ignorance in Plato’s Ethics.” Classical Quarterly 40: 118120.Google Scholar
Hadot, Pierre. 1995. Philosophy as a Way of Life. Translated by Chase, Michael. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Halper, Edward. 2000. “Is Knowledge of Knowledge Possible? Charmides 167a–169d.” In Plato: Euthydemus, Lysis, Charmides. Proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Platonicum, edited by Robinson, Thomas and Brisson, Luc, 309316. Sankt Augustin: Akademia Verlag.Google Scholar
Howland, Jacob. 2004. The Republic: The Odyssey of Philosophy. Philadelphia, PA: Paul Dry Books.Google Scholar
Hyland, Drew A. 1981. The Virtue of Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato’s Charmides. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.Google Scholar
Hyland, Drew A. 1995. Finitude and Transcendence in the Platonic Dialogues. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Hyland, Drew A. 2011. “Aporia, the Longer Road, and the Good.” Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 32 (1): 145175.Google Scholar
Irwin, Terrence. 1995. Plato’s Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, David. 1999. “God as the True Self: Plato’s Alcibiades I.” Ancient Philosophy 19: 119.Google Scholar
Johnson, Marguerite, and Tarrant, Harold, eds. 2012. Alcibiades and the Socratic Lover-Educator. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Joyal, Mark. 1990. “Anacreon Fr. 449 (P.M.G.).” Hermes 118. Bd., H. 1: 122124.Google Scholar
Kahn, Charles H. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kahn, Charles H. 2013. Plato and the Post-Socratic Dialogue: The Return to the Philosophy of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, Rachana. 2004. “What’s the Good of Agreeing? Homonoia in Platonic Politics.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 26: 131170.Google Scholar
Kang, Chol-Ung. 2008. “Socratic Eros and Self-Knowledge.” The Journal of Greco-Roman Studies 32: 79102.Google Scholar
Kirk, Gregory. 2016. “Self-knowledge and Ignorance in Plato’s Charmides.” Ancient Philosophy 36: 303320.Google Scholar
Klein, Jacob. 1989. A Commentary on Plato’s Meno. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, 1999. “Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant.” Journal of Ethics 3: 129.Google Scholar
Krämer, H. J. 1990. Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents. Translated by Catan, J. R.. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, Richard. 1991. “Return to the Cave: Republic 519–521.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 7: 4362.Google Scholar
Kraut, Richard. 1992. “The Defense of Justice in the Republic.” In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, edited by Kraut, Richard, 311337. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kurihara, Yuji. 2008. “Plato on the Ideal of Justice and Human Happiness: Return to the Cave (Rep. 519e–521b).” Philosophical Inquiry 30 (3–4): 7786.Google Scholar
Kurihara, Yuji. 2012. “Socratic Ignorance, or the Place of the Alcibiades I in Plato’s Early Works.” In Alcibiades and the Socratic Lover-Educator, edited by Johnson, Marguerite and Tarrant, Harold, 7789. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Landazuri, Ortiz De. 2015. “The Development of Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Philosophy.” Logos (Madrid) 48: 123140.Google Scholar
Larivée, Annie. 2012. “Choice of Life and Self-Transformation in the Myth of Er.” In Plato and Myth: Studies on the Use and Status of Platonic Myths, edited by Collobert, Catherine, Destrée, Pierre, and Gonzalez, Francisco J., 235257. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Larivée, Annie. 2016. “Le pouvoir protreptique de l’amour. Éros, soin de soi et identité personnelle dans le Banquet.” In Plato in Symposium: Selected Papers from the Tenth Symposium Platonicum, edited by Tulli, Mauro and Erler, Michael, 380385. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Lavecchia, Salvatore. 2012. “Selbsterkenntnis und Schöpfung eines Kosmos. Dimensionen der Sophia in Platons Denken.” Perspektiven der Filosofie 35: 115145.Google Scholar
Layne, Danielle A. 2009a. “In Praise of the Mere Presence of Ignorance from Plato to Erasmus.” The Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 83: 253267.Google Scholar
Layne, Danielle A. 2009b. “Refutation and Double Ignorance in Proclus.” Epoché 13 (2): 347362.Google Scholar
Layne, Danielle A. 2015. “Involuntary Evil and the Socratic Problem of Double Ignorance in Proclus.” The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 9: 2715.Google Scholar
Layne, Danielle A. 2018. “Proclus on Socratic Ignorance, Knowledge, and Irony.” In Socrates and the Socratic Dialogue, edited by Stavru, Alessandro and Moore, Christopher, 816834. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Lear, Jonathan. 1992. “Inside and Outside the Republic.” Phronesis 37 (2): 184215.Google Scholar
Lee, Edward N. 1973. “‘Hoist with His Own Petard’: Ironic and Comic Elements in Plato’s Critique of Protagoras (Tht. 161–171).” In Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos, edited by Lee, E. N., Mourelatos, A. P. D., and Rorty, R. M.. Assen: Van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Lee, Edward N. 1976. “Reason and Rotation: Circular Movement as the Model of Mind (Nous) in Later Plato.” In Facets of Plato’s Philosophy, edited by Werkmeister, William H., Phronesis Supplement 2: 70–102.Google Scholar
Lee, Mi-Kyoung. 2005. Epistemology after Protagoras. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, James. 2009. “Bios, Praxis and the Unity of Life.” In Was ist ‘Leben’? Aristoteles’ Anschauungen zur Entstehungsweise und Funktion von Leben, edited by Foellinger, Sabine. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner.Google Scholar
Lennox, James. 2010. “Bios and Explanatory Unity in Aristotle’s Biology.” In Definition in Greek Philosophy, edited by Charles, David, 329355. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, David. 2018. “Socrates’ Self-Knowledge.” In Socrates in the Cave: On the Philosopher’s Motive in Plato, edited by Diduch, Paul J. and Harding, Michael P., 77106. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Liddell, Henry George, Scott, Robert, and Jones, Henry Stuart. 1996. Greek English Lexicon. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lisi, Francisco. 2016. “Sophistischer und Philosophischer Sprachgebrauch bei Platon.” In Platon und die Sprache, edited by Koch, Dietmar, Männlein-Robert, Irmgard, and Weidtmann, Niels, 6281. Tübingen: Narr Francke Attempto Verlag.Google Scholar
Long, Anthony 2001. “Ancient Philosophy’s Hardest Question: What to Make of Oneself?Representations 74: 1936.Google Scholar
Long, Anthony 2014. Greek Models of Mind and Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lott, Micah. 2012. “Ignorance, Shame and Love of Truth: Diagnosing the Sophist’s Error in Plato’s Sophist.” Phoenix 66 (1–2): 3656.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, Mary Margaret. 1988. “The Virtues of Socratic Ignorance.” The Classical Quartley, New Series 38 (2): 331350.Google Scholar
Marrin, Brian. 2017. “What’s Next in Plato’s Clitophon? Self-Knowledge, Instrumentality, and Means without End.” Epoché 21 (2): 307320.Google Scholar
Marrou, H. I. 1965. Histoire de l’Éducation dans l’Antiquité, 6th edition. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.Google Scholar
Matthews, Gareth. 2003. Socratic Perplexity and the Nature of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
May, Hope E. 1997. “Socratic Ignorance and the Theraputic Aim of the Elenchos.” In Wisdom, Ignorance and Virtue: New Essays in Socratic Studies, edited by McPherran, Mark, 3750. Edmonton: Academic.Google Scholar
McCabe, Mary M. 1994. Plato’s Individuals. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
McCabe, Mary M. 2007. “Looking Inside Charmides’ Cloak: Seeing Others and Oneself in Plato’s Charmides.” In Maieusis: Essays on Ancient Philosophy in Honor of Myles Burnyeat, edited by Scott, Dominic, 119. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McCabe, Mary M. 2010. “Banana Skins and Custard Pies: Plato on Comedy and Self-Knowledge.” In Plato’s Philebus: Selected Papers from the Eighth Symposium Platonicum, edited by Dillon, John M. and Brisson, Luc, 194203. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
McCabe, Mary M. 2011. “‘It Goes Deep with Me’: Plato’s Charmides on Knowledge, Self-Knowledge and Integrity.” In Philosophy, Ethics and a Common Humanity: Essays in Honour of Raimond Gaita, edited by Cordner, Christopher, 161180. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McCabe, Mary M. 2013. “Waving or Drowning? Socrates and the Sophists on Self-Knowledge in the Euthydemus.” In The Platonic Art of Philosophy: Festschrift for Christopher Rowe, edited by Boys-Stones, George, El Murr, Dimitri, and Gill, Christopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McCoy, Marina. 2008. Plato on the Rhetoric of Philosophers and Sophists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McCoy, W. James. 1975. “The Identity of Leon.” The American Journal of Philology 96 (2): 187199.Google Scholar
McKim, Richard. 1985. “Socratic Self-Knowledge and ‘Knowledge of Knowledge’ in Plato’s Charmides.” Transactions of the American Philological Association 115: 5977.Google Scholar
McPherran, Mark. 1996. The Religion of Socrates. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Migliori, M., Napolitano, L. M., Fermani, A., eds. 2011. Inner Life and Soul: Psychē in Plato. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Miller, Mitchell. 1986. Plato’s Parmenides: The Conversion of the Soul. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Mitchell. 1999. “Figure, Ratio, Form: Plato’s Five Mathematical Studies.” Apeiron 32: 7388.Google Scholar
Miller, Mitchell. 2015. “Making New Gods? A Reflection on the Gift of the Symposium.” In Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato, edited by Nails, Debra and Tarrant, Harold, 285306. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica.Google Scholar
Moore, Christopher. 2014. “How to ‘Know Thyself’ in Plato’s Phaedrus.” Apeiron 47 (3): 390418.Google Scholar
Moore, Christopher. 2015a. Socrates and Self-Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, Christopher. 2015b. “Socrates and Self-Knowledge in Aristophanes’ Clouds.” Classical Quarterly 65: 2.Google Scholar
Moore, Christopher. 2015c. “Self-Knowledge in Xenophon’s Memorabilia 4.2.” Classical Journal 110 (4): 397417.Google Scholar
Morris, T. F. 1989. “Knowledge of Knowledge and Lack of Knowledge in the Charmides.” International Studies in Philosophy 21: 4961.Google Scholar
Morrison, J. S. 1977. “Two Unresolved Difficulties in the Line and Cave.” Phronesis 22: 212231.Google Scholar
Moss, Jessica. 2012. “Soul-Leading: The Unity of the Phaedrus, Again.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43: 123.Google Scholar
Murdoch, Iris. 1977. The Fire and the Sun. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Naas, Michael. 2015. “American Gadfly: Plato and the Problem of Metaphor.” In Plato’s Animals: Gadflies, Horses, Swans and Other Philosophical Beasts, edited by Bell, Jeremy and Naas, Michael, 4359. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Nails, Deborah. 2002. The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander. 1992. “What Did Socrates Teach and to Whom Did He Teach It?The Review of Metaphysics 46 (2): 279306.Google Scholar
Nicholson, Graeme. 1999. Plato’s Phaedrus: The Philosophy of Love. West Lafayette, IN: Purdue University Press.Google Scholar
Nightingale, Andrea. 2010. “Plato on Aporia and Self-Knowledge.” In Ancient Models of Mind: Studies in Human and Divine Rationality, edited by Nightingale, Andrea and Sedley, David, 826. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nikulin, Dmitri. 2012. The Other Plato: The Tübingen Interpretation of Plato’s Inner Academic Teachings. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
North, Helen. 1966. Sōphrosunē: Self-Knowledge and Self-Restraint in Greek Literature. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Notomi, Noburu. 1999. The Unity of Plato’s Sophist. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1979. “The Speech of Alcibiades: A Reading of Plato’s Symposium.” Philosophy and Literature 3: 131172.Google Scholar
Opsomer, Jan. 1997. “Plutarch’s Defence of the Theages: In Defence of Socratic Philosophy?Philologus 141 (1): 114136.Google Scholar
Pangle, Thomas. 1987. “On the Theages.” In The Roots of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten Socratic Dialogues, edited by Pangle, Thomas, 147174. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Politis, Vasilis. 2007. “The Aporia in the Charmides about Reflexive Knowledge and the Contribution to Its Solution in the sun Analogy of the Republic.” In Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, edited by Cairns, Douglas, Herrmann, Fritz-Gregor, and Penner, Terry, 231250. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Principe, Jade. 2006. “The Ascent as a Return to the Cave.” Rhizai 2: 219239.Google Scholar
Radke, Gyburg. 2003. Die Theorie der Zahl im Platonismus: Ein systematisches Lehrbuch. Tübingen/Basel: Francke.Google Scholar
Rappe, Sara. 1995. “Socrates and Self-Knowledge.” Apeiron 28: 124.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2006. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato’s Republic. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Remes, Pauliina. 2013. “Reason to Care: The Object and Structure of Self-Knowledge in the Alcibiades I.” Apeiron 46: 270301.Google Scholar
Renaud, François, and Tarrant, Harold. 2015. The Platonic Alcibiades I: The Dialogue and Its Ancient Reception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Renz, Ursala, ed. 2016. Self-Knowledge: A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rider, Benjamin. 2011. “Self-Care, Self-Knowledge, and Politics in the Alcibiades I,” Epoché 15: 395413.Google Scholar
Robinson, Richard. 1953. Plato’s Earlier Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Roochnik, David. 2002. “Self-Recognition in Plato’s Theaetetus.” Ancient Philosophy 22 (1): 3751.Google Scholar
Rossellini, Ingrid. 2018. Know Thyself: Western Identity from Classical Greece to the Renaissance. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Rowe, Christopher. 2011. “Self-Examination.” In The Cambridge Companion to Socrates, edited by Morrison, Donald, 201214. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, Christopher. 2015. “Plato, Socrates, and the genei gennaiai sophistikê of Sophist 231b.” In Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato, edited by Nails, Debra and Tarrant, Harold, 149168. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica.Google Scholar
Ryan, Paul. 2012. Plato’s Phaedrus: A Commentary for Greek Readers. Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Sayre, Kenneth M. 1969. Plato’s Analytic Method. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Schmid, W. Thomas. 1998. Plato’s Charmides and the Socratic Ideal of Rationality. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Arbogast. 2008. Die Moderne und Platon: Zwei Grundformen europäischer Rationalität. Stuttgart: Poeschel.Google Scholar
Schultz, Anne-Marie. 2013. Plato’s Socrates as Narrator: A Philosophical Muse. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Schultz, Anne-Marie. 2015. “Socrates on Socrates: Looking Back to Bring Philosophy Forward,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 30: 123141.Google Scholar
Scott, Gary Alan. 2000. Plato’s Socrates as Educator. Albany, NY: State University of NY Press.Google Scholar
Scully, Stephen. 2003. Plato’s Phaedrus. Newburyport, MA: Focus Publishing.Google Scholar
Seaford, Richard, Wilins, John, and Wright, Matthew, eds. 2017. Selfhood and Soul: Essays on Ancient Thought and Literature in Honor of Christopher Gill. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, David. 1997. “‘Becoming like God’ in the Timeaus and Aristotle.” In Interpreting the Timaeus-Critias: Proceeding of the IV Symposium Platonicum, edited by Brisson, Luc and Calvo, Tomás, 327339. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Sedley, David. 1999. “The Ideal of Godlikeness.” In Oxford Readings in Philosophy: Plato (2 vols.), edited by Fine, Gail, 359383. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, David. 2004. The Midwife of Platonism: Text and Subtext in Plato’s Theaetetus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Seeskin, Kenneth. 1986. Dialogue and Discovery: A Study in Socratic Method. Albany, NY: State University Press of New York.Google Scholar
Sichel, Betty. 1985. “Self Knowledge and Education in Plato’s Allegory of the Cave.” Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Philosophy of Education Society 41: 429439.Google Scholar
Smith, Nicholas D. 1997. “How the Prisoners in Plato’s Cave Are ‘like Us.’Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 13: 187204.Google Scholar
Smyth, Herbert W. 1963. Greek Grammar. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Stalley, R. F. 1983. An Introduction to Plato’s Laws. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Stern, Paul. 1999. “Tyranny and Self-Knowledge: Critias and Socrates in Plato’s Charmides.” American Political Science Review 9 (2): 399412.Google Scholar
Stern, Paul. 2008. Knowledge and Politics in Plato’s Theaetetus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1959. “What Is Political Philosophy?” and Other Studies. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Tarrant, Dorothy. 1958. “The Touch of Socrates.” The Classical Quarterly 8 (1–2): 9598.Google Scholar
Tarrant, Harold. 2003. “Review of Joyal, The Platonic Theages.” Phoenix 57 (1–2): 154156.Google Scholar
Tarrant, Harold. 2005. “Socratic Synousia: A Post-Platonic Myth?Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (2): 131155.Google Scholar
Tarrant, Harold. 2007. “Olympiodorus and Proclus on the Climax of the Alcibiades.” The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 1 (1): 329.Google Scholar
Tarrant, Harold. 2012. “Improvement by Love: From Aeschines to the Old Academy.” In Alcibiades and the Socratic Lover-Educator, edited by Johnson, Marguerite and Tarrant, Harold, 147163. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Tarrant, Harold. 2015. “Where Did the Mirror Go? Plato [?] Alcibiades I 133c1–6.” Elenchos 36: 361372.Google Scholar
Tarrant, Harold. 2018. “The Socratic Dubia.” In Socrates and the Socratic Dialogue, edited by Stavru, Alessandro and Moore, Christopher, 386411.Google Scholar
Taylor, A. E. 1932. Socrates. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Thein, Karel. 2011. “L’âme, l’homme et la connaisance de soi dans le Premier Alcibiade.” Chôra 9–10: 171202.Google Scholar
Thein, Karel. 2012. “Imagination, Self-Awareness, and Modal Thought at Philebus 39–40.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 42: 109149.Google Scholar
Thesleff, Holger. 1982. Studies in Platonic Chronology. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica.Google Scholar
Tschemplik, Andrea. 2008. Knowledge and Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Theaetetus. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Tsouna, Voula. 2001. “Socrate et la connaissance de soi: quelques interpretations.” In Figures de Socrate, edited by Laks, André and Narcy, Michel, 3764. Villeneuve d’Ascq: Presses Universitaires de Septentrion.Google Scholar
Tuozzo, Thomas M. 2001. “What’s Wrong with These Cities? The Social Dimension of Sophrosyne in Plato’s Charmides.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (3): 321350.Google Scholar
Tuozzo, Thomas M. 2011. Plato’s Charmides: Positive Elenchus in a “Socratic” Dialogue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vegetti, Mario. 2013. “Dialectics: Configurations and Functions.” In The Painter of Constitutions: Selected Essays on Plato’s Republic, edited by Vegetti, Mario, Ferrari, Franco, and Lynch, Tosca. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Vernant, Jean-Pierre. 1990. “The Myth of Prometheus in Hesiod.” In Myth and Society in Ancient Greece. Translated by Lloyd, Janet. New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory. 1989, December 15. “Divining the Reason.” Times Literary Supplement Historical Archive 1393. Accessed September 9, 2016.Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory. 1991. Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Von Fritz, Kurt. 1963. Philosophie und Sprachlicher Ausdruck bei Demokrit, Platon und Aristoteles. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory. [1932] 1969. Platon, Theaetet und die Antike Mathematik. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.Google Scholar
Warnek, Peter. 2005. Descent of Socrates: Self-Knowledge and Cryptic Nature in the Platonic Dialogues. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Werner, Daniel. 2012. Myth and Philosophy in Plato’s Phaedrus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Werner, Daniel. 2013. “The Self-Seeing Soul in the Alcibiades I.” Ancient Philosophy 33: 307331.Google Scholar
Westra, Laura. 1992. “Knowing the Self in Plato, Plotinus, and Avicenna.” In Neoplatonism and Islamic Thought, edited by Morewedge, Parvis, 89110. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
White, David A. 1993. Rhetoric and Reality in Plato’s Phaedrus. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Zuckert, Catherine. 2009. Plato’s Philosophers: The Coherence of the Dialogues. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by James M. Ambury, Andy German, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel
  • Book: Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy
  • Online publication: 30 November 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316877081.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by James M. Ambury, Andy German, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel
  • Book: Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy
  • Online publication: 30 November 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316877081.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by James M. Ambury, Andy German, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel
  • Book: Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy
  • Online publication: 30 November 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316877081.015
Available formats
×