Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-mnl9s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-06T14:13:28.083Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part II - Protecting Rights and Preparing for the Future

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 May 2025

Anne L. Alstott
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Abbe R. Gluck
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Eugene Rusyn
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut

Summary

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Law and the 100-Year Life
Transforming Our Institutions for a Longer Lifespan
, pp. 75 - 170
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

Part II Protecting Rights and Preparing for the Future

6 The New Old Civil Rights

As the authors of The 100-Year LifeFootnote 1 inform us, a child born today in the West has a 50 percent likelihood of living to be a centenarian. This longevity revolution has been described as “the most important phenomenon of our time in the world, more than the bomb, the Pill, or the Internet.”Footnote 2 The groundswell of individuals in older-age cohorts – whom I will call the “new old” – could activate a world-historical social movement. To fulfill its potential, however, that movement must resist the temptation to advance age-based civil rights solely within shopworn frameworks established by race or sex. The “new old” should seek instead to fashion an innovative antidiscrimination paradigm that honors distinctive age-related concerns.

In Section 6.1, I describe how legislation and doctrine create the temptation to build “like race” or “like sex” paradigms for age. In Section 6.2, I argue that advocates should resist this temptation for both empirical and strategic reasons. In Section 6.3, I show how unmooring the age discrimination paradigm from traditional civil rights models allows us to apprehend it better by considering the distinctive fears older individuals conjure about our own mortality. In Section 6.4, I consider how such insights might be incorporated into antidiscrimination law and politics.

6.1 Understanding the Analogy

Courts interpreting the Age Discrimination in Employment Act (ADEA) and the Equal Protection Clause have traditionally parsed age discrimination through analogy to race or sex discrimination. When courts or legislatures accept this analogy, they afford age discrimination plaintiffs more relief. When such bodies reject that analogy, they look less kindly on those plaintiffs. This pattern presses advocates of older individuals to cast age as analogous to race and sex.

6.1.1 ADEA’s Genesis in Analogy and Disanalogy

Congress fashioned the Age Discrimination in Employment Act of 1967Footnote 3 on the premise that age discrimination differed from other forms of discrimination. Congress considered and rejected the proposal to add ageFootnote 4 to the other classifications protected under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 – race, color, religion, sex, and national origin.Footnote 5 Instead, the 1964 Act commissioned the secretary of labor “to make a full and complete study of the factors which might tend to result in discrimination in employment because of age.”Footnote 6

In 1965, Secretary W. Willard Wirtz submitted The Older American Worker: Age Discrimination in Employment.Footnote 7 Because the Wirtz Report spurred the enactment of the ADEA, courts rely on it as legislative history.Footnote 8 The report began by describing the consensus “that people’s ability and usefulness is unrelated to the facts of their race, or color, or religion, or sex, or the geography of their birth.”Footnote 9 “Having accepted this truth,” the report continued, “the easy thing to do would be simply to extend the conclusions derived from it to the problem of discrimination in employment based on aging.”Footnote 10 The report then dropped the hammer: “This would be easy – and wrong.”Footnote 11

Adopting a more nuanced approach, the Wirtz Report sketched how age discrimination converged with and diverged from the discrimination addressed by Title VII. On the one hand, the report observed that age, like other classifications, sometimes triggered “arbitrary discrimination” based on “assumptions about the effect of age … when there is in fact no basis for these assumptions.”Footnote 12 The report argued that such discrimination “can and should be stopped.”Footnote 13

On the other hand, the report underscored some critical differences between age and other classifications. It noted that while no legitimate discrimination existed where “race or religious discrimination are concerned,” such justified discrimination “clearly does exist so far as the age question.”Footnote 14 Specifically, the Wirtz Report alluded to two distinctive features of age. First, it noted what I call the “universality” argument that “the process of aging is inescapable, affecting everyone who lives long enough.”Footnote 15 Second, it credited what I call the “real difference” argument that “there is in fact a relationship between [an individual’s age] and his ability to perform the job.”Footnote 16

In rehearsing these themes, the report strongly implied that the more age was like race or sex, the more protection it deserved. That implication has cast a long shadow over subsequent legislation and doctrine.

6.1.2 Age Discrimination Plaintiffs Win When Courts Accept the Analogy

Courts interpreting the ADEA favor age discrimination plaintiffs when they deem their claims analogous to race or sex discrimination. In the 1985 case of Western Air Lines v. Criswell,Footnote 17 the Court considered an airline policy that required flight engineers to retire at age sixty. The ADEA generally prohibits mandatory retirement, but allows for a bona fide occupational qualification (BFOQ) defense.Footnote 18 This defense permits the employer to take “any action otherwise prohibited” where age is a “bona fide occupational qualification reasonably necessary to the normal operation of the particular business.”Footnote 19 The airline asserted that it had a BFOQ defense because of the increased safety risk posed by older flight engineers.Footnote 20

The BFOQ defense originated in Title VII, which permits the defense in cases alleging discrimination on the basis of religion, sex, and national origin.Footnote 21 Title VII affords no BFOQ defense against race discrimination.Footnote 22 Even where Title VII permits the defense, courts have construed it narrowly.Footnote 23 Seeking to escape that narrow construction, the employer in Criswell argued that the ADEA only required employers to show their policy was “reasonable.”Footnote 24 In rejecting that claim, the Court observed that the ADEA had taken “a concept and statutory language from Title VII.”Footnote 25 It further pointed out that the BFOQ standard in the ADEA “is one of ‘reasonable necessity,’ not reasonableness.”Footnote 26 Applying the “reasonable necessity” standard, the Court unanimously ruled against the employer.Footnote 27

Two decades later, the Court again relied on an analogy to Title VII to establish disparate impact liability in Smith v. City of Jackson.Footnote 28 Since 1971, Title VII has allowed for a “disparate impact” cause of action.Footnote 29 Under this theory, a plaintiff can prevail against an employer even in the absence of discriminatory intent so long as the employer’s policies have a disparate impact on a protected class.Footnote 30 Because discriminatory intent is often difficult to prove, this cause of action is a vital weapon in a plaintiff’s arsenal.

In City of Jackson, a group of police and public safety officers brought suit against Jackson, Mississippi. Their disparate impact claim alleged that when the City of Jackson gave raises to all such officials, it gave less generous ones to officers over forty.Footnote 31 The Fifth Circuit ruled against the plaintiffs, stating that the ADEA never contemplated disparate impact claims.Footnote 32 In an opinion by Justice Stevens, a majority of the Court reversed, holding that the ADEA cognized such claims.Footnote 33 While the majority splintered on the rationale, five justices underscored the importance of textual similarities between Title VII and the ADEA.Footnote 34

In an opinion disagreeing on this point, Justice O’Connor emphasized how age differed from race and gender. She noted that the Wirtz Report – “the blueprint for the ADEA” – stressed “that age discrimination is qualitatively different from the types of discrimination prohibited by Title VII.”Footnote 35 Specifically, Justice O’Connor invoked the report’s assertion that “there is in fact a relationship between [an individual’s] age and his ability to perform his job.”Footnote 36

6.1.3 Age Discrimination Plaintiffs Often Lose When Courts Reject the Analogy

As Justice O’Connor’s opinion intimated, courts can be less sympathetic to ADEA plaintiffs when they distinguish age from race and gender. The Court reinforced that point in a different portion of City of Jackson. After recognizing disparate impact causes of action under the ADEA, the Court nevertheless held that differences between the ADEA and Title VII conscribed the city’s liability.Footnote 37

In this part of its analysis, the City of Jackson majority focused on the so-called reasonable factor other than age (RFOA) defense. The ADEA permits an employer to engage in “otherwise prohibited” action “where the differentiation is based on reasonable factors other than age.”Footnote 38 The RFOA defense is generally applicable to disparate impact claims, while the BFOQ defense is generally applicable to disparate treatment claims. Unlike the BFOQ defense, the RFOA defense has no counterpart in Title VII.Footnote 39 The Court deemed the RFOA to be a more lenient version of the “business necessity” defense employers can mount against disparate impact claims under Title VII.Footnote 40

The city asserted an RFOA defense by noting that it had to “raise the salaries of junior officers to make them competitive with comparable positions in the market.”Footnote 41 The Court acknowledged that the city could have achieved those goals in other ways, suggesting that the rationale was not a “business necessity.”Footnote 42 Yet because the RFOA only required “reasonableness,” the Court ruled for the city. In pinpointing this difference between the ADEA and Title VII, the Court relied on the Wirtz Report to claim that “certain circumstances … unquestionably affect older workers more strongly, as a group, than they do younger workers.”Footnote 43 It observed that “Congress’s decision to limit the coverage of the ADEA by including the RFOA provision is consistent with the fact that age, unlike race or other classifications protected by Title VII, not uncommonly has relevance to an individual’s capacity to engage in certain types of employment.”Footnote 44

More recently, the Court in 2009 determined that different standards of proof applied under the two statutes. In Gross v. FBL Financial Services,Footnote 45 the Court grappled with whether the ADEA required the plaintiff to show that age was a “but for” factor or merely a “motivating factor” to prove liability.Footnote 46 Under Title VII, the plaintiff only needed to show that age was a motivating factor, at which point the burden of production shifted to the employer to show that it would have made the same decision regardless of race.Footnote 47 Even though Title VII permitted either cause of action, the Court held that the ADEA required age to be a “but for” factor.Footnote 48 It observed that Congress amended Title VII in 1991 to permit the more easily proved “motivating factor” liability. Congress did not, however, amend the ADEA.Footnote 49 Justice Stevens, writing for a four-member dissent, noted that the ADEA should require the same burden of proof as Title VII because the operative provisions were the same.Footnote 50 The 1991 Amendment was not to the contrary as it simply codified the judicial understanding of Title VII at the time.Footnote 51

To this point, I have only discussed the ADEA, leaving the Equal Protection Clause to one side. This choice may seem quixotic, as the clause is the home of the equality principle in the US Constitution. Yet the Equal Protection Clause is much less relevant because the Court has rendered it close to toothless with regard to age discrimination. It has done so by rejecting the analogy between age, on the one hand, and race and sex, on the other.

The constitutional analysis differs from the statutory one insofar as the clause enumerates no classifications. Instead, it broadly bars states from denying “any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.”Footnote 52 Over the past eight decades, however, the Court has established a framework that affords greater judicial protection to five “suspect” classifications. Three of these – race,Footnote 53 national origin,Footnote 54 and alienageFootnote 55 – receive strict scrutiny. Two others – sexFootnote 56 and nonmarital parentageFootnote 57 – receive intermediate scrutiny. The Court accords all other classifications so-called rational-basis review. To complicate matters slightly, rational-basis review can take a relatively stringent form – known as “rational basis with bite”Footnote 58 – or a highly deferential form – known as “ordinary rational basis.”Footnote 59 If state action draws anything other than ordinary rational basis, courts will almost invariably invalidate it.Footnote 60 If state action draws only ordinary rational basis, courts will almost invariably uphold it.Footnote 61

How does a classification acquire heightened scrutiny? The Court has not relied on a single theory. It has, however, repeatedly stated that the judiciary should intervene to correct failures in the political process. Drawing on a famous footnote in the case of United States v. Carolene Products,Footnote 62 the Court has expressed its solicitude for “discrete and insular minorities” in need of protection from the prejudices of the majority.

In the 1976 case of Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia,Footnote 63 the Court confronted an equal protection challenge to a state statute requiring police officers to retire at fifty. Applying only ordinary rational-basis review to age-based classifications, the Court upheld the statute.Footnote 64 The Court acknowledged that “the treatment of the aged in this Nation has not been wholly free of discrimination.”Footnote 65 Nevertheless, it found that older individuals had not faced a history of discrimination or stereotyping like “those who have been discriminated against because of race or national origin.”Footnote 66 It elaborated that “old age does not define a ‘discrete and insular’ group, in need of ‘extraordinary protection from the majoritarian political process.’”Footnote 67 To the contrary, the Court remarked, “[I]t marks a stage that each of us will reach if we live out our normal span.”Footnote 68 This passage is the most prominent example of the “universality” argument in the case law.

The Court later expanded on these themes. In the 1979 case of Vance v. Bradley,Footnote 69 the Court considered an equal protection challenge to a mandatory retirement age of sixty for foreign service officers. It upheld the policy based on the universality and real-difference rationales. In a succinct – if world-weary – encapsulation of both ideas, the Vance Court referred to “the common-sense proposition that aging – almost by definition – inevitably wears us all down.”Footnote 70 Similarly, in 1991, the Court in Gregory v. AshcroftFootnote 71 sustained a mandatory retirement age of seventy for state judges against an equal protection challenge. The Court observed that the provision was reasonable given that “[i]t is an unfortunate fact of life that physical and mental capacity sometimes diminish with age.”Footnote 72

In both the ADEA and equal protection jurisprudence, courts appear to protect age when it is like race or sex, and not to protect it when it is unlike race or sex. Looking only at such cases, advocates would rightly perceive a massive incentive to force age discrimination onto the Procrustean bed of race or sex discrimination. To borrow from the Wirtz Report, succumbing to that impulse would be “easy – and wrong.”Footnote 73

6.2 Rejecting the Analogy

The problem here is a specific form of a general pathology in antidiscrimination discourse. Two decades ago, Janet Halley wrote an essay on how LGBT rights advocates felt impelled to make analogies between sexual orientation, on the one hand, and race and gender, on the other.Footnote 74 “Particularly when they argue to judges, who are formally if not actually constrained by precedent, and even when they make more general political appeals, advocates are opportunists looking for a simile,” she observed. She mimed the advocate addressing the Court: “Your honor, this is just like a race discrimination case; this is just like a sex discrimination case.”Footnote 75

Halley advanced an urbane critique of this strategy. She entertained no illusions that this strategy would disappear. She acknowledged that “analogies are probably an inescapable mode of human inquiry and are certainly so deeply ingrained in the logics of American adjudication that any proposal to do without them altogether would be boldly utopian.”Footnote 76 Nevertheless, she alerted advocates for LGBT rights to the costs of conformity to the regnant paradigms of civil rights – costs that centrally included the misrepresentation of the minority itself. She argued that the analogy faltered on empirical groundsFootnote 77 and, less intuitively, on strategic grounds.Footnote 78

Halley’s analysis illuminates age discrimination jurisprudence. Courts insist that age is different because it is (1) universal and (2) creates a real difference. Because of the incentives described earlier, advocates for older individuals seek to elide these differences. Their arguments, however, can be challenged on both empirical and strategic grounds.

6.2.1 Empirical Argument against the Analogy

Consider a 2018 report by EEOC Acting Head Commissioner Victoria Lipnic titled The State of Age Discrimination and Older Workers in the U.S.: 50 Years after the Age Discrimination in Employment Act of 1967.Footnote 79 Written on the fiftieth anniversary of the ADEA’s date of enforcement, it reviewed changes and continuity since the promulgation of the ADEA. The Lipnic report decried “a central premise of the Wirtz Report … that age discrimination is different than other forms of discrimination,” a notion that “continues to seep into ADEA jurisprudence today.”Footnote 80 “When examined through today’s understanding of how discrimination operates,” the Lipnic report declared, “age discrimination is more like, than different from, other forms of discrimination.”Footnote 81

In making that case, the report addressed both the universality argument and the real-difference argument. With regard to universality, the Lipnic report cited a judge questioning a plaintiff in an age discrimination case: “No, age is different because we are all going to get old … but when you’re talking about gender or race or ethnicity those are immutable characteristics as the Supreme Court has said.”Footnote 82 The report responded that “[a]lthough the notion of immutability is irrelevant to protections under Title VII of the ADEA, age is ‘immutable’ in the sense that it is a characteristic the person has not chosen and cannot change.”Footnote 83

The Lipnic report’s rejoinder sidestepped the true force of the universality argument by focusing on immutability. The judge’s point – like the Murgia Court’s point – was not really about immutability but about the universality of aging. The argument was that age – unlike race or gender – was not as likely to result in empathy failure because everyone would move from the in-group to the out-group. This peculiarity of age distinguishes it from any other classification, whether immutable or not. The immutability of race means that individuals will not shift from being white to being racial minorities. Yet even mutable characteristics like religion do not inevitably entail movement from, say, being Christian to being Muslim. The Murgia argument can be rebutted, as we will see below, but not on the ground that age is indistinguishable from race or gender.

With regard to the real-difference argument, the Lipnic report pointed out that “race discrimination also derives from negative views and stereotypes about the abilities of workers of a particular race, like age discrimination does.”Footnote 84 It also saw “important similarities” between age and sex discrimination, citing “substantial evidence that in the 1960s, people believed that one’s gender determined one’s abilities, interests and qualifications, just like age.”Footnote 85

The Lipnic report’s point that race discrimination involved stereotypes may reflect “today’s understanding,” but it reflected yesterday’s understanding as well. The Wirtz report squarely compared race discrimination to “arbitrary discrimination” on the basis of age.Footnote 86 The Wirtz report deviated from this commonplace only in noting that race discrimination, unlike age discrimination, was never justified.Footnote 87

This notion – that there are justified and unjustified forms of age discrimination – renders the analogy between age and gender the better one. The Lipnic report is certainly correct to state that gender was unfairly used to limit women’s opportunities. Yet the report fails to acknowledge that the courts have allowed discrimination on the basis of gender so long as the distinction is based on a “real difference” between the sexes.Footnote 88 In Nguyen v. Immigration and Naturalization Services,Footnote 89 the Court upheld a facially discriminatory statute that allowed a mother, but not a father, to pass their citizenship automatically to a nonmarital child born in a foreign nation.Footnote 90 The Court defended the statute on the ground that mothers were present at the birth of their children, and therefore would be more likely to establish a relationship between the child and the US.Footnote 91 “The difference between men and women in relation to the birth process is a real one,” it stated, “and the principle of equal protection does not forbid Congress to address the problem at hand in a manner specific to each gender.”Footnote 92 In the Court’s view, the differential treatment was based on biology, not bigotry.

Like sex discrimination, age discrimination involves some stereotypical thinking about older individuals, but also some justifiable distinctions based on the “real difference” between individuals of different ages. Indeed, the argument for “real differences” in the age context seems vastly stronger than the analogous argument in the gender context. The Court has only upheld legislation under a real-difference rationale with a majority opinion once in the equal protection context. In stark contrast, it has repeatedly upheld age-based legislation under that rationale.Footnote 93 And even Justice Marshall, the greatest champion of age discrimination plaintiffs to sit on the Court, acknowledged that “age, unlike sex, is at some point likely to bear a relationship to ability.”Footnote 94

As the genesis of the ADEA suggests, age can easily be distinguished from race. While age may be closer to sex, the similarity disfavors age discrimination plaintiffs. Moreover, the similarity is not that great, as age presents much more of a “real difference” in the workplace than sex does. In the end, the attempts to efface these differences seem so implausible that they suggest some other agenda.

6.2.2 Strategic Argument against the Analogy

That agenda is, of course, a strategic one. Halley archly described the advocate’s posture: “‘It doesn’t matter that the simile is a little inaccurate,’ they would say; ‘judges fall for it, and once we secure some legal rights no one will remember the rhetoric we used to obtain them.’”Footnote 95 In fairness, advocates for age discrimination plaintiffs do sometimes prevail by papering over the distinctions between age and other classifications. Nonetheless, they also fail, as we see in Gross, City of Jackson, Murgia, Vance, and Gregory.

Just as importantly – and much more hopefully – the Court has at times engaged in progressive interpretations of age discrimination precisely because it deems age to be different. In General Dynamics Land Systems, Inc. v. Cline,Footnote 96 the Court confronted the question of whether the ADEA, which clearly “forbids discriminatory preference for the young over the old,” also “prohibits favoring the old over the young.”Footnote 97 The Court held that it did not. To arrive at that conclusion, it had to join a classic debate within antidiscrimination law between classes and classifications. In this debate, scholars have questioned whether equality principles forbid government use of a classification (such as race or age) or forbid the subordination of a particular class (such as Blacks or older individuals) within the classification.Footnote 98 Generally speaking, progressives tend to favor the class-based antisubordination view.Footnote 99 In contrast to the Court’s analysis in other domains,Footnote 100 the Cline Court embraced that view.

Importantly, the Cline Court arrived at this conclusion by emphasizing the ways in which age was not like race or sex. The Court acknowledged that “age” could be interpreted either to mean “any number of years lived, or as a common shorthand for the longer span and concurrent aches that make youth look good.”Footnote 101 In adopting the latter view, it noted that “the term ‘age’ employed by the ADEA is not … comparable to the terms ‘race’ or ‘sex’ employed by Title VII.”Footnote 102 The Court said that while race was not commonly understood “to refer only to the black race,” nor sex “to refer only to the female,” age was generally understood to mean only “old age.”Footnote 103

Cline does not stand alone. In the 1996 case of O’Connor v. Consolidated Coin,Footnote 104 the Court considered the age discrimination claim of a fifty-six-year-old plaintiff, James O’Connor, who had been replaced by a forty-year-old employee.Footnote 105 The Fourth Circuit rejected the plaintiff’s claim by applying a framework developed in the Title VII context. In the lower court’s view, the plaintiff had to show that he “was replaced by someone of comparable qualifications outside the protected class.”Footnote 106 Given that the ADEA protects individuals forty and over, O’Connor failed that requirement.Footnote 107

The Supreme Court unanimously reversed the lower court. In an opinion by Justice Scalia, the Court found that “there can be no greater inference of age discrimination … when a 40-year-old is replaced by a 39-year-old than when a 56-year-old is replaced by a 40-year-old.”Footnote 108 Again, the plaintiff prevailed through disanalogy.

6.3 Transcending the Analogy

I have argued that distinguishing age from other classifications opens space for alternative progressive interpretations of age discrimination. Thus far, I have relied on doctrinal examples. I now cut deeper by turning to a distinctive feature of age that has not yet surfaced directly in the age discrimination jurisprudence. Social scientists have analyzed age discrimination under a “terror management theory” that suggests that age discrimination arises in part out of a fear of our own mortality – a fear without direct analogues in other realms of antidiscrimination law.

6.3.1 The Nature of Terror Management Theory

Terror management theory dates back to the work of cultural anthropologist Ernest Becker, who published his Pulitzer Prize-winning book The Denial of Death in 1973.Footnote 109 In that work, Becker argued that human beings are distinctive in their capacity to apprehend their own mortality.Footnote 110 Given this awareness, much of human activity occurs to manage the panic induced by that threat.Footnote 111 As developed by subsequent scholars, terror management theory posits that human beings respond to their consciousness of death by investing in beliefs in literal or symbolic immortalityFootnote 112 or, perhaps less intuitively, by fortifying their self-esteem.Footnote 113

The point about self-esteem is important for our purposes because it leads to particular views about in-groups and out-groups. As psychologists Jeff Greenberg, Sheldon Solomon, and Tom Pyszczynski demonstrated through a series of experiments, individuals who were primed with their own mortality more strongly favored in-group members and more strongly disfavored out-group members.Footnote 114 For instance, one experiment with judges had some of them take a survey about what they believed would happen after their own deaths.Footnote 115 All the judges were then asked to sentence a hypothetical sex worker. The judges in the control group imposed, on average, a bond of $50.Footnote 116 The judges who had been primed with their own mortality imposed “a far more punitive bond – on average $455, more than nine times the typical tab.”Footnote 117

Multiple studies have corroborated that priming individuals with their mortality leads to harsher assessments of out-groups. In a 2005 article, psychologists Andy Martens, Jamie L. Goldenberg, and Jeff Greenberg focused on how terror management theory affected ageism.Footnote 118 Their analysis illuminates both the universality argument and the real-difference argument.

6.3.2 Terror Management Theory and the Universality Argument

Terror management theory shows us why the universality argument is flawed. As we observed, the courts repeatedly adduced the universality of aging as a reason for why we should not be particularly concerned about age discrimination. Recall that the Murgia Court opined that discrimination against older individuals was less likely, because old age “marks a stage that each of us will reach if we live out our normal span.”Footnote 119

The rejoinders to the universality argument tend to paper over the difference that universality makes. As we have seen, the Lipnic report deflected the discussion from universality to immutability. Justice Marshall similarly tried to minimize the impact of “universality.” He acknowledged that the class of older individuals “is not ‘discrete and insular’ because all of us may someday belong to it, and voters may be reluctant to impose deprivations that they themselves could eventually have to bear.”Footnote 120 Nevertheless, he pointed out that “the time lag between when the deprivations are imposed and when their effects are felt may diminish the efficacy of this political safeguard.”Footnote 121

Such rebuttals are too anemic. Applying terror management theory to ageism, the Martens article began with the Murgia-like question: “[W]hy should individuals exhibit prejudice toward elderly people, if indeed they represent the best-case scenario for the future?”Footnote 122 The authors answered that “ageism exists precisely because elderly people represent our future in which death is certain.”Footnote 123 They asserted “that negative attitudes and behaviors directed toward elderly people can be explained in large part by people’s own fears about aging and death.”Footnote 124

The issue of universality should not be addressed by sidestepping or minimizing it. Rather we should cheerfully concur that universality distinguishes age from all other classifications. We should then note that this distinction is not a reason why the courts should care less about ageism. It is the reason they should care more.

6.3.3 Terror Management Theory and the Real-Difference Argument

Terror management theory also casts the “real-differences” argument in a new light. Let us take for granted that some age-based generalizations are “real differences” and that some are “unreal differences” – that is, stereotypes. These “real differences” make age discrimination more like sex discrimination than race discrimination.

The existence of real age-related differences helps explain some features of ageism. As Becca Levy and Mahzarin Banaji have noted,Footnote 125 several aspects of age discrimination are distinctive. First, “[t]here are no hate groups that target the elderly as there are hate groups that target members of religious and racial and ethnic groups.”Footnote 126 This is presumably what the Wirtz report meant when it noted “no significant evidence” of discrimination based on “dislike or intolerance that sometimes exists in the case of race, color, religion, or national origin.”Footnote 127 Yet, on the other hand, the authors stressed the “widespread occurrence of socially acceptable expressions of negativity toward the elderly.”Footnote 128 Finally, older individuals are distinctive in internalizing that negative view of themselves – “members of all groups tested to date – other than the aged – invariably show more positive implicit attitudes toward their own group compared to non-group members.”Footnote 129 Older individuals were the only stigmatized group that felt as negatively about themselves as nongroup members did.

While they might seem to be in tension, all these features can be explained through “real differences.” As the Wirtz report noted, there are some forms of age discrimination that are entirely justified – indeed, the report agonized over whether to even call this “discrimination.”Footnote 130 And if age distinctions track real differences, it makes sense that there would be little hatred of older individuals, that we could rationally treat them more poorly, and that they would internalize society’s negative views of old age.

Unlike the gender context, however, the “real difference” between older and younger individuals is a source of terror. If we have “death panic” in the context of age, we are less likely to be able to sort through what is a fair and what is an unfair distinction. We are much more likely to overascribe traits and behaviors to biology than to bigotry.

6.3.4 An Exact Inversion

I close this portion of the analysis with a deliberately provocative point. The civil rights paradigm in the US has been built on the foundation of race discrimination, to which age discrimination is a belated addition. Yet if we regard civil rights through a terror management perspective, we could invert that analysis.

Take philosopher Martha Nussbaum’s analysis of age discrimination in her 2017 work Aging Thoughtfully.Footnote 131 While Nussbaum spoke in terms of disgust rather than terror management, her thinking can be easily assimilated into the terror management framework. She observed that the prejudice toward aging bodies was largely fueled by a particular form of disgust. “With aging the truth is front and center: it really is for oneself that one fears,”Footnote 132 she contended. “Stigma learned early and toward others gradually becomes self-stigma and self-exclusion, as one’s own aging body is seen as a site of decay and future death – by oneself as well as by others.”Footnote 133

Nussbaum maintained that other forms of discrimination could be driven by this fear of mortality. She contended that “[p]eople seek to create a buffer zone between themselves and their own animality, by identifying a group (usually a powerless minority) who can be targeted as the quasi-animals and projecting onto that group various animal characteristics.”Footnote 134 She elaborated that “[t]he so-called thinking seems to be: if those quasi-animal humans stand between us and our own animal stench and decay, we are that much further from being animal and mortal ourselves.”Footnote 135

Under this view, we see an exact inversion of age discrimination and race discrimination. Age discrimination is no mere adjunct to the paradigm case of race discrimination. Rather, age discrimination is the central category, as it most directly engages this fear of death. Other forms of discrimination displace that terror – or disgust – onto other groups.

In saying this, I do not contest the primacy of race-based civil rights – it is this country’s original sin. Rather, I am attempting to dislodge the view that age-based discrimination is the peripheral category we often view it to be.

6.4 Doctrinal and Political Reforms

My primary goal here is not to advance legislative or doctrinal reform. Yet because it is easier to dispose than propose, I make some reconstructive gestures as a token of good faith. To respect the difference that age makes is to transform the law and culture of aging.

6.4.1 Legal Reforms

As a matter of constitutional law, my analysis means that MurgiaFootnote 136 must be revisited. Luckily the change required here is doctrinally modest. In its equal protection jurisprudence, the Court has moved away from anointing new classifications as suspect.Footnote 137 Instead, it has expanded the “rational basis with bite” category to engage in more searching review under that standard. For this reason, a subsequent Court need not overrule Murgia with regard to its adoption of rational-basis review. It need only clarify that the rationality standard there has bite, in the same way it had bite in the contexts of sexual orientation,Footnote 138 disability,Footnote 139 or marital status.Footnote 140

This analysis would also have implications in the legislative domain. Some advocates for older individuals have argued that Congress should amend Title VII to include age.Footnote 141 By doing so, one advocate maintains, Congress could obliterate “some of the U.S. Supreme Court’s ill-conceived, pro-business opinions that deny equal protection to older workers.”Footnote 142 I disagree. Given the cogency of the “real-difference” argument, age is sufficiently distinct that it should remain under its own statutory rubric.

At the same time, the existence of real differences will often blind courts to stereotypical thinking.Footnote 143 It seems unlikely that the Court will whittle away at the “real-differences” rationale here as they have done in the gender context. Unlike the gender context, the age context deals with more plausible and salient real differences among cohorts. Moreover, “death panic” means that the line between reality and stereotype may be even more blurred. This point suggests that the real wrong turn in the ADEA occurred in Gross,Footnote 144 where the Court declined to embrace a “mixed motive” analysis that would require an employer to justify its decision if age was seen as a “motivating” factor. Any time a court recognizes that the employer has used age as a factor, it should adopt a hermeneutics of skepticism.

6.4.2 Social Reforms

All of these legal reforms will be for naught unless we change broader social views about older individuals. Again, this is a vast topic, so I will here do no more than identifying one worrisome and one promising solution in Gratton and Scott’s 100-Year Life.

I am pessimistic about Gratton and Scott’s endorsement of greater contact as a solution. Gratton and Scott noted their belief that “age segregation is closely connected to ageism, since it sets up sharp distinctions between ‘us’ and ‘them,’ and leads to stereotyping and associated prejudices.”Footnote 145 They noted that as the three stages of life (education, work, and retirement) perforce become “multiple stages,” “people from different ages have a chance to engage in similar experiences.”Footnote 146 Gratton and Scott believed this engagement would have salutary effects on intergroup attitudes. To support that view, they cited Gordon Allport’s “classic study” outlining contact hypothesis – the view that stereotypes decrease as contact between groups increases.Footnote 147

Allport’s work itself, however, suggests that contact alone will not be enough. Allport underscored that certain conditions need to be met for intergroup contact to diminish prejudice. The groups, for instance, must meet on the terms of relative equality.Footnote 148 If that condition does not obtain, contact is not likely to make much of a difference. We see this in the case of gender, where contact between men and women did not, per se, lead to a diminution of stereotyping of women. Indeed, because women were assigned particular roles, this close contact arguably kept those stereotypes in place. So contact alone does not seem to be a sufficient answer.

Gratton and Scott offered a more promising avenue when they discussed a study about how individuals invested differently when they saw their digitally aged avatars.Footnote 149 The point of this study was to show that when individuals were shown their projected older selves, they tended to save more for their retirement.Footnote 150 Yet this project might not just incentivize greater savings by younger individuals but also push to overcome their denial about the aging process. Confronting one’s older self could be the first step in having empathy for that self.

The terror management theory might appear to cast ageism as practically ineradicable. After all, it casts ageism as rooted in a fear of death, which cannot be staved off forever. Yet we do know that some cultures view both death and older individuals with less terror.Footnote 151 Thus it is not utopian to posit that we could have a different attitude toward death and, therefore, a different attitude toward old age. Comparative study may be particularly useful here.

6.5 Conclusion

Ageism is a problem that cries out for an urgent solution in a period of radically lengthened lifespans. It is all very well to say that individuals should begin their second careers at age sixty-five, but this will be impossible if employers will not hire them at that age. As the problem grows ever more urgent, and the constituency affected becomes ever more numerous, we seem due for a tipping point. I predict that the movement for older individuals will soon have a major mobilizing “moment,” much as other groups did with Black Lives Matter or #MeToo.

I have attempted to suggest some ways for older individuals to use their power when the revolution comes. The traditional way of recognizing a new social movement is to bring discrimination against the group within the pale of the traditional antidiscrimination canon. I argue that this is a mistake (indeed a particular iteration of a more general mistake). If age is truly to be protected, we should not force the “new old” into old paradigms. The opposite of “old” is not only “young”; it is also “new.”

7 Age, Inequality, and Political Representation

We live in an age of widening inequality.Footnote 1 In the mid twentieth century, income and wealth inequality was declining, leading to an era of comparative economic equality and a large middle class. But since the early 1980s, income and wealth inequality has been on the rise. The 100-Year Life describes how increasing life expectancy could transform the course of individual lives in detail – but how does this trend intersect with our age of inequality? And what does it mean for law and policymaking more generally?

The dark side of rising life expectancy is that it is unequally shared. In Section 7.1, I briefly discuss how age and inequality are connected – that is, that not everyone shares in rising life expectancy equally and that those who are living longer share many common attributes. Section 7.2 considers the possible impact of the skew in rising life expectancy on representative government. A wide literature in political science shows how inequality skews politics to favor the wealthy; inequality by age will likely do the same, but with some additional twists. The fundamental problem is that power is held unequally in most societies. Addressing this issue has been one of the central questions of political theory, constitutional law, and institutional design – particularly for those interested in representative democracy. Section 7.3, on age and institutional design, outlines some ways in which political structures might be crafted to account for age-related differences.Footnote 2

7.1 Inequality and Rising Life Expectancy

Rising life expectancy often comes with optimism and celebrations of progress.Footnote 3 But rising life expectancy isn’t experienced by everyone equally in society. In fact, the data show a wide range of disparities in life expectancy. Women live longer than men on average, and that disparity is projected to continue into the future.Footnote 4 White people live longer than Black people, on average, but Hispanic and Latino Americans live longer than either.Footnote 5

Life expectancy is also tied to a range of social factors like wealth, education, and geography. Perhaps unsurprisingly, the wealthy live longer than the poor.Footnote 6 But the difference is striking. The top 1 percent of men in America by income have a life expectancy that is fifteen years longer than the bottom 1 percent.Footnote 7 Those with college degrees live longer than those without,Footnote 8 and studies show that life expectancy has been declining for those without – even as it increases among those with – college degrees.Footnote 9 Where Americans live is also tied to life expectancy. People living in metropolitan areas and on the coasts live longer than those in the middle of the country,Footnote 10 and people living outside metro areas in the south or in Appalachia have lower life expectancies than much of the rest of the country.Footnote 11 Deaths often come from suicide and drug overdoses,Footnote 12 and life expectancy is tied to the prevalence of smoking.Footnote 13 In some cases, geography matters even more than poverty. The life expectancy of the poorest 5 percent in Detroit, for example, is more than ten years lower than their counterparts in New York.Footnote 14

It is worth noting that economic inequality persists even within age cohorts as well.Footnote 15 The Black–white wealth gap, for example, is significant within older age cohorts.Footnote 16 White Americans in their thirties, on average, have three times as much wealth as Blacks (about $147,000). By their sixties, the gap has expanded to seven times as much (or about $1.1 million).Footnote 17 This is partly a function of the cumulative effects of compounding economic inequality over a lifetime.Footnote 18

There may also be significant period effects in inequality by age.Footnote 19 That is, the period of time in which one grew up might shape an entire cohort’s economic opportunities. The generation that grew up in the comparative equality of the mid to late twentieth century will have different economic outcomes than a generation that grew up in the more recent age of wide inequality. Studies show, for example, that the ratio of wealth for older and younger cohorts has changed over time. A Deloitte analysis notes that in 1992 the ratio of median family net worth for households older than seventy-five compared to those less than thirty-five years was 9.4. That ratio had jumped to 24.1 by 2016.Footnote 20 The median family net worth for those under thirty-five actually declined during this period.Footnote 21 Pew’s research has led to similar data. In 2009, the median net worth of households headed by adults over sixty-five was 42 percent higher than their counterparts in 1984. But households headed by adults under thirty-five saw a 68 percent decrease in their median net worth compared to their counterparts a generation earlier.Footnote 22 Over the past few decades, incomes have increased at a greater rate for older people; poverty is declining for those above sixty-five, but rising for those under thirty-five; and younger people suffered more from the Great Recession than older people.Footnote 23

In sum, what the data show is that rising life expectancy is not experienced equally – and will not be experienced equally in the future. Rather, those who live longer – successive cohorts of older Americans – are more likely to be wealthier, white or Hispanic, better educated, and live in metro areas, particularly on the coasts. Within the cohorts of older Americans, inequalities will persist based on race, geography, period effects, and other factors as well.

7.2 Gerontocracy and Its Discontents

Systematic, persistent disparities in age are a problem for representative democracies. The American constitutional system, for example, was designed on a theory that interests – what James Madison calls factions – would be so fragmented that no single faction would be able to dominate politics.Footnote 24 Instead, the clashes between groups would lead to the election of leaders who would advance the public good, rather than the preferences of any one group.Footnote 25 At the same time, the separation of powers was meant to divide institutions, not factions, unlike earlier mixed-government regimes that explicitly saw the primary divides in society as rich versus poor and built those divisions into the constitutional structure.Footnote 26 In recent years, many constitutional scholars have shown the limitations of Madison’s theory. Some have argued that in an ideologically polarized system, political parties and party identity are the central divide in society, and so a system of checks and balances should focus on the “separation of parties, not powers.”Footnote 27 Others have noted that policy preferences overlap with wealth and class, and that the political system is dominated by the wealthy and interest groups; those cleavages, not institutional separations, are primary drivers in politics.Footnote 28 In both cases, the worry is that the Madisonian system will not function as intended because of acute social cleavages.

Age may offer another example of this problem. According to the Interparliamentary Union, only 2.6 percent of legislators around the world are under the age of thirty, despite that age group comprising nearly 50 percent of the world’s population.Footnote 29 Only about 17.5 percent are under forty, and 30 percent are under forty-five.Footnote 30 Outside of elected officeholding, there are age disparities in voter registration, voting, and political acts from writing letters to making campaign donations.Footnote 31 Political scientists have also shown that there are clear life-cycle effects in terms of political participation. Activity in politics is low in youth, increases in middle age, and has a short trail-off at extreme age.Footnote 32 As life expectancy grows, we should expect life-cycle effects on the older end to stretch – with older people remaining active for longer. The result of this data is that there is a massive imbalance in representation of the young and an imbalance that will likely expand with rising life expectancy. If, as political scientists have argued, representative democracy is not a system that aggregates the views of individual voters or responds to deliberation, but rather a process by which groups wield power, then the young have and will continue to have comparatively less power and influence than their elders.Footnote 33

The overlap of age and economic inequality only magnifies this problem. Older people (and those with rising life expectancies) are wealthier than younger people. Political scientists have demonstrated that the poor and middle class are not well represented in government, either through elected officials who come from a blue-collar backgroundFootnote 34 or through participation in contacting representatives, volunteering, donating, voting, or lobbying (personally or through representatives in Washington).Footnote 35 It is perhaps no surprise, therefore, that study after study has concluded that policy outcomes reflect the preferences of the wealthy.Footnote 36 Indeed, when the vast majority of Americans’ views diverge with those of the wealthy, the wealthy’s views tend to control policy outcomes.Footnote 37

The data on age and wealth inequality, and on rising life expectancy, raises the prospect of gerontocracy – a regime defined by the rule of the elderly. If the elderly participate more in politics, serve more in government, and are systematically wealthier than younger people, the elderly will have disproportionately more political power and influence than younger people. Moreover, political influence, like wealth, can compound over time. Decades of donating to political leaders can build close relationships; decades in office can build political power – in the form of favors done, former staff spread throughout the system, and skills and relationships. It may be, as we approach the unequal 100-year life, that we will have an increasingly unequal system in which wealthy, older people have more and more political power – a gerontocracy.

The specter of gerontocracy might not matter if the elderly’s views are similar to those of younger people. But surveys show that different generations have different attitudes toward policy. According to Pew Research, millennials are the most supportive of same-sex marriage, with older generations – Gen X, Boomers, and Silent – exhibiting descending levels of support (the study omitted Gen Z).Footnote 38 Views on whether racial discrimination is the primary barrier for why Black people in America “can’t get ahead” also diverge by generation, and over time the gap has widened even as attitudes changed. Indeed, younger people’s attitudes have shifted further than other generations on whether racial discrimination is a major problem.Footnote 39 This gap in age cohorts persists even if comparing only white millennials to white members of older generations.Footnote 40 On other questions too, there are serious divides based on age: Do immigrants strengthen the country? Younger generations say yes.Footnote 41 Should the US rely more on diplomacy or the military to ensure peace? Younger generations focus on diplomacy.Footnote 42 Should the US government be bigger and offer more services? Younger generations say yes.Footnote 43 Is it the government’s responsibility to provide healthcare coverage to everyone? Younger generations say yes.Footnote 44

Age differences in policy preferences and political participation create a variety of problems. We might call the first the entrenchment problem. Longer life expectancy may mean that people remain in positions of power longer. Commentators regularly note that Presidents Trump and Biden are older than their predecessors, that some congressional leaders are older than is conventional, and that Supreme Court justices regularly serve into their eighties. If older generations remain entrenched firmly in power for longer, that keeps younger generations from gaining power until they too are far older. The result could be a systematic phase shift in the age of political leadership – and continued lack of representation among those who are younger and less wealthy.

A second problem is what we might think of as the increasing imbalance between the wisdom of the ancients and the wisdom of the young. One of the primary arguments for a political system that operates slowly, with many veto-gates, checks, and balances, is that it recognizes the wisdom of past generations. Those who came before were not fools, and their considered decisions should be given great weight before they are displaced by new ideas and new policies. Similarly, societies revere the elderly for their accumulated wisdom and knowledge. A lifetime of successes, failures, and lessons learned may lead to a just and wise gerontocracy. But the problem is that an equal and opposite principle is at play too: the wisdom of the young. As technologies, innovations, and society change, the elderly may not update their technical knowledge or social views as swiftly as they should, particularly in comparison to younger generations who grow up natively familiar with a new context. The wisdom of youth welcomes the future, is more willing to experiment, and charts new frontiers. The young may also think with a longer time horizon, because they must live with policy decisions for many decades to come.Footnote 45 As life expectancy rises and if older people remain in positions of power longer, we should expect a political system that is already designed to move slowly to move even more slowly, to adapt less well to social and technological changes, and to be less innovative. The balance between the conservativism of age and the experimentalism of youth will likely lean further toward the former.

A third problem is in the design of public policies. Political scientist Paul Peterson has observed that federal government policies that help children are systematically different from those helping the elderly across a range of dimensions. Programs for children tend to have state-determined eligibility requirements, rather than federal; they tend to have intergovernmental administration, rather than national; they tend to be complex, rather than simple; and they tend to offer substitutable benefits, rather than supplemental benefits.Footnote 46 Peterson argues that the dynamics of program design are a function of the political power that the elderly have, compared to the young. Their power enables them to push for programs that bring more benefits, with greater consistency and simplicity.Footnote 47

These three problems may lead to a fourth – an increasing gap between the rulers and the radicalized. If policies systematically lag behind changing trends, if programs are better for those who are older and richer than the overall population, and if political leadership is increasingly entrenched in power, we might expect increasing frustration with politics and increasing radicalization among younger cohorts. Younger cohorts may see themselves shut out of direct political representation and their policy preferences advancing far more slowly than they would like. Overlap with economic inequality means that these dynamics could become acute for many with respect to their basic livelihoods.

Looking globally, some commentators have suggested that a “youth bulge” in a country – a large population of young people without sufficient economic opportunities – can contribute to political radicalization and even destabilize governments.Footnote 48 It is possible that rising life expectancy, and the political dynamics it unleashes, might be similar. While some young people may choose to remain in the political system and wait their turn, many others may not. Rising hopelessness and distrust in government’s ability to address their concerns might push them to exit the political process and exercise their voice through protest.Footnote 49 It is possible that such frustrations could lead, over time, to a greater radicalization of politics, particularly among younger cohorts. In a gerontocracy, the slow pace of reform may lead to calls for revolution.Footnote 50

7.3 Age and Political Representation

What can be done about the possibility of gerontocracy? The first option is simply to do nothing. Many social and identity cleavages are not specifically accounted for in political representation – tall people, blondes, fans of crime novels, runners. None of those groups get representation in politics, and few would think they need representation. That intuition likely stems from the view that nothing about their group identity is essential to public affairs or linked to systematic differences in policy preferences. But as noted earlier, this is not true of age. There are significant divergences in policy preferences by age – even among copartisans. Younger conservatives have significantly different views than their elderly counterparts on a variety of policy issues.

Another possibility is that the young are represented, virtually, through their elders. While there is a long tradition of political thinkers who believed representatives should “be in miniature an exact portrait of the people at large,”Footnote 51 there is also a long tradition of those who believed representatives would carry the views of their constituents to politics, even if they did not “mirror” the population precisely.Footnote 52 For example, older members of legislatures have children and grandchildren and may consider those younger generations’ interests when making political decisions. They may also listen to their constituents and represent those views faithfully, for fear of losing an election. Still, political scientists have shown that actual representation matters. Women in office act differently than men; people of color act differently than whites, and people from blue-collar backgrounds act differently than those from white-collar backgrounds.Footnote 53

A second option, which accounts for policy or other changes, is for the political system to informally consider age as a factor in representation. To some extent, this is currently what happens. Some candidates for office run explicitly on generational change, promising fresh ideas and a new approach compared to the tired politics of the past. Their opponents emphasize their experience and entrenched power after decades in office. For appointed roles, leaders may choose to pick people from different age brackets, in part to ensure age diversity. It is not as obvious that leaders take age diversity into account, especially when compared to gender and racial diversity, but they certainly could. Still, with rising life expectancy in the political class, it is possible that the “younger generation” in politics may not actually be so young.

A third option is to grant specific representation by age. This should not be as outlandish as it might first seem. It is worth noting that constitutional theorists have long considered some groups worthy of specific representation. The mixed-government tradition that persisted from ancient times until the American Revolution divided society into classes, giving specific representation to the wealthy and the ordinary people. In comparative politics, the field of consociationalism outlines strategies to give representation to divided societies – decentralization and regional control; power-sharing agreements; and quotas for ethnic group representation at the cabinet or senior level. In societies deeply divided by religion, language, and ethnicity, many have thought to build representation for each faction directly into the political system.

The question, of course, is whether age fits into the same category. People may come to different conclusions on this point, but as noted earlier, there are not only direct correlations between age and wealth but also systematically different policy preferences by age cohort. As life expectancy increases, it is likely that generational divides will increase as well because older generations will be represented for longer. If age is likely to be a more and more significant cleavage over time, it may be worth considering as a factor in institutional design. Let us, therefore, consider a few thought experiments in how age might be incorporated into institutional design.Footnote 54

7.3.1 Age Minimums – and Maximums

The US Constitution considers age in representation, through provisions that set age minimums for federal elected office. Members of the House of Representatives must be twenty-five years of age. Members of the Senate, thirty years of age. And the president must be at least thirty-five years old. Age minimums are a proxy for maturity and experience, and each office was designed with that in mind.

But if age minimums are conventional and uncontroversial, why not also age maximums? Age maximums for service in office would ensure that different generations are represented in the political process. They would proxy new ideas, energy, and changing social norms. They would also prevent entrenchment in office by long-serving political leaders and preemptively ensure the retirement of leaders whose mental acuity may have begun to decline.

How could age maximums be designed? At the legislative level, one could imagine building overlapping age categories, with minimums and maximums, into the qualifications for officeholding. Service in the House of Representatives, for example, could require a person to be between the ages of twenty-five and fifty-five, and in the Senate might require an age between thirty and seventy. It is possible that all members of both branches would still be on the older side of those ranges, but the House would likely always be younger, given the dramatically younger age maximum.

Alternatively, one could imagine designing a legislature without overlap between the two houses – a House with members age twenty-five to forty, and a Senate with members age forty to seventy. Guaranteeing stark differences in age as a qualification for service would ensure generational representation, akin to classical mixed-government strategies that reserved one House for the wealthy and another for commoners.

One challenge, of course, is what happens to the young who are aged out of their position. The answer is that many will likely seek another role – a spot as governor – or might challenge an incumbent in their older-age body. A legislature designed along these lines could therefore potentially increase electoral competition among credible candidates. It might, however, also lead young members to become interest-group lobbyists, drawing on their experience to pressure their former members (and perhaps even mentees) to serve private interests instead of the public good. Post-employment restrictions would therefore probably be necessary for such a system to work.

One could also imagine prescribing an age range on the presidency. A presidential age range would functionally preclude any person from running for that office who would be unable to serve a full four-year term prior to hitting the age maximum and, because party members might want someone who will not be a lame duck from day one, might even prevent most people from winning a nomination to that office if they cannot serve a full two terms. Such a rule would serve as a proxy that presidents have the energy and stamina to handle perhaps the most stressful and consequential job in the world – just as the age minimum proxies a level of life experience needed for the position.

It is also worth noting that there may be value to reducing the age minimums for service in elected office, even without maximums. In response to the disparities in policy designs for children versus the elderly, Paul Peterson has proposed, mostly in jest, allowing children to vote.Footnote 55 Whatever one thinks of his provocation, age qualifications for legislative roles could be reduced from current levels. Some countries have dropped age qualifications to eighteen, and at least one study finds this is an effective tactic for increasing youth representation.Footnote 56

7.3.2 Term Limits

Another possibility is term limits. Term limits do not directly ensure age-based representation, but they may indirectly help. Legal rules for lifetime service (as with federal judges) and incumbency advantages (even without lifetime service rules) mean that officials can often serve in their same position for decades – perhaps even for life. Term limits would mandate departure from office, ending formal or informal incumbency entrenchment. But it is worth noting that this is an indirect way to get at age: There is no reason why newly elected or selected persons, after a term expires, will not be from the same age cohort – or even an older one – than the previous occupant of the office.

But it is also worth recognizing the severe downsides of term limits. First, for legislative positions, term limits bring a risk of heightened interest-group capture. The reason is that most newly elected members of Congress know very little about the subject areas of law and policy they are legislating or overseeing.Footnote 57 Over time, they develop expertise as they see more issues, focus on particular topics, and go into greater depth through committee assignments. In contrast, lobbyists and interest groups have considerable information and expertise – albeit conflicted, and usually deployed to serve their parochial interests. This mismatch in expertise means that overworked, busy members who are constantly running for reelection and do not have much expertise will be more likely to rely on interest-group experts than those who have over many years developed some expertise of their own.Footnote 58

Second, passing significant legislation is often a multi-year and sometimes multi-decade effort. Members sometimes spend years pushing for a particular bill or policy, or at least amassing general expertise on a topic. When the opportunity arises or when a crisis occurs and major legislation is demanded, they have amassed significant expertise to navigate the complex process of passing legislation.Footnote 59 If term limits are too short – say, along the lines of eight years – they may simply ensure that no members of Congress have sufficient expertise and longevity to pass major legislation. Longer term limits, such as twenty years, might not have this downside.

A third problem is that term limits might lead to greater capture in the form of the revolving door. Members of Congress, for example, may depart their positions and make many times more in salary by decamping to lobbying firms. There they can use their contacts and relationships with former colleagues to push forward the interests of whatever group for whom they lobby. Shorter term limits would exacerbate this problem, creating more and more former members and likely, therefore, more well-connected lobbyists.

All of these problems are less of an issue when considering term limits for leadership offices, such as committee chairs or House and Senate leadership. For these positions, term limits will increase turnover among persons in those positions, without significantly decreasing the experience and expertise of the body itself. Members can still spend years pushing causes and will bring expertise to a crisis. But leaders will rotate, preventing the accumulation of power, and possibly ensuring that younger members have an opportunity to exercise their leadership and pursue their agenda – at least for a time.

7.3.3 Intergenerational Judiciary

In recent years, there has been increased interest in reforming the Supreme Court. Proposals have included expanding the size of the Court, rotating judges from lower courts onto the Court, creating partisan balance requirements for the Court, and also establishing term limits for justices. Some who support term limits for Supreme Court justices have done so explicitly as a way to prevent gerontocracy.Footnote 60 They worry that a Court of seventy- and eighty-year-olds is ill-equipped to address many of the innovative issues of the time. Others support the proposal because they worry about too many young people being appointed to the federal courts.Footnote 61 In recent years, Republicans have nominated and confirmed many judges in their thirties for lifetime appointments, seemingly in order to retain their hold on those judgeships for the extra decade before middle age. Term limits might reduce the pressure to do so.

From the perspective of age-based representation, the judiciary is an interesting case. Both parties appoint federal judges between the ages of forty and sixty-five with great frequency, but Republicans tend to appoint more judges than Democrats at the lower end of the age spectrum (including some in their thirties) and Democrats more than Republicans at the highest end of the age spectrum.Footnote 62 One consequence is that there is some intergenerational diversity on the courts – judges in their forties, fifties, sixties, and seventies, and a smaller number in their thirties and eighties. While the balance skews conservative at the younger end, there is some age cohort representation even into the thirties. But over time, the thirty-something and forty-something judges will get older. And when others retire or pass away, creating new openings on the bench, there is no guarantee they will be replaced by new judges in their thirties or forties. Indeed, if Democrats continue their pattern of largely nominating comparatively older judges, it is likely that there will be a systematic skew over time – youth representation will exist during Republican presidencies from newly minted conservative judges, but not during Democratic presidencies.

With respect to the courts, term limits could create revolving-door problems, with judges departing to become lobbyists, appellate lawyers, or even using the bench as a springboard for a run for office. This dynamic is troubling as it might corrupt their decision-making process as judges. Some might also think that judges should have considerable experience in law and life prior to becoming a judge, as both expertise in the law and the exercise of judgment take time to develop. This might suggest a substantive reason for age representation to skew older for judges than for legislators. Age minimums could potentially be useful to address that issue, though they would not enhance intergenerational representation.

7.3.4 Parliamentary Systems, Party Lists, Proportional Representation, and Age Quotas

Some countries’ electoral systems ensure age diversity in legislative representation through quotas for young people. After the Arab Spring protests, Egypt, Morocco, and Tunisia adopted youth quotas for parliamentary service, and after years of domestic conflict, Uganda, Kenya, and Rwanda did as well.Footnote 63 These reforms appear to have been a response to a large, disaffected population of young people.Footnote 64 Bringing young people into politics might give them a voice, rather than leaving them outside the process to protest.

Research on the efficacy of youth quotas is limited, but one study suggests that proportional representation and dropping age qualifications for officeholding to eighteen may be superior tactics.Footnote 65 Youth quotas have thus far tended to be “too low and too selectively applied.”Footnote 66 In addition, proportional representation systems require party elites to develop a slate of candidates, creating an incentive to appeal to different groups of people, and this may push them to have youth representation.Footnote 67 When one party acts in a proportional representation system, there may be a contagion effect pushing others to follow.Footnote 68 The advantages of incumbency are also less significant in proportional representation systems than in first-past-the-post systems.Footnote 69 In parliamentary systems, and particularly for those with proportional representation, adopting slates with young people may therefore be a promising tactic.

7.4 Conclusion

In representative democracies, public policy depends on who has political power and who uses it. Political power turns not simply on the institutional structures of government but on background social conditions such as wealth, ideology, geography, and race. With rising life expectancy pointing toward a 100-year life, age may become an increasingly important feature in determining political power. Older political leaders may become entrenched in office, and older people tend to be wealthier – another important aspect of political power. The consequence of gerontocracy could over time be radicalization of the young who feel poorly represented. Addressing this problem will be important to ensuring representative government, and there are a number of formal strategies governments can take, from age qualifications for office to term limits to youth quotas, in addition to informal strategies like candidate recruitment. But whatever the approach, as people live longer – and do so unequally – the policy consequences will be significant.

8 Age-Based Classifications in an Age of Centenarians

With the number of older adults increasing worldwideFootnote 1 – and the ranks of the very old rising especially sharplyFootnote 2 – countries are confronted with the question of how to respond to their expanding elderly populations. Historically, countries have responded to the “problem” of old age by creating special policies for older adults, such as pension programs for those of “retirement age.”

This chapter considers the role of such age-based law and legal entitlements in a world in which people routinely live to be 100 years old. It asks: In such a world, what should be the legal significance of advanced chronological age? Should an adult’s chronological age affect his or her legal status or entitlements? It posits that the rise of the 100-year life should prompt a shift away from age-based policy. Specifically, it shows why, as life expectancy increases, chronological age will become an increasingly poor proxy for other characteristics, and that, therefore, using chronological age to establish eligibility for legal entitlements will result in increasingly poorly targeted policy interventions. It also explains how the use of age-based classifications will become increasingly inequitable and regressive.

The chapter calls for a wholesale reconsideration of the use of age-based criteria. It argues that social welfare policies should increasingly reject age-based classifications in favor of approaches that target interventions to populations based on their actual vulnerability to the particular problems the policies aim to address. It explains that although this alternative approach may be more challenging to administer, it is increasingly necessary to ensure efficient and equitable distributions of resources.

8.1 The Role of Age-Based Classifications

Age-based legal classifications are ubiquitous. Across time and across cultures, jurisdictions have used chronological age as a mechanism for establishing rights and responsibilities.

Today, chronological age classifications occur in a variety of legal contexts. Chronological age is used to establish legal duties. In both criminal and civil cases, minors are typically held to a lower standard of care than are adults.Footnote 3 Similarly, certain behaviors may be required of individuals at one age, and not at another. For example, states may require education for minors, or special tests for older adults seeking drivers’ licenses.Footnote 4 Chronological age can also determine eligibility for benefits. Although states have generally abandoned age as a basis for imposing guardianship or conservatorship, eligibility for public health insurance in the US largely depends on chronological age. Not only is Medicare coverage largely limited to those over sixty-five years of age, but older adults and children can more readily qualify for Medicaid than can younger adults. In addition, chronological age can determine the level of protection the law provides against actions by others. For example, the US Age Discrimination in Employment Act (ADEA) provides protection against age discrimination in employment to those aged forty and over, but no protection to those under the age of forty.Footnote 5

The ubiquity of age-based legal classifications, in part, reflects their utility. In some contexts, chronological age is a meaningful predictor of individuals’ needs or abilities, and, therefore, using age-based classifications can help efficiently target policy interventions and resources. Compulsory education requirements for minors, for example, largely reflect the distinct needs and abilities of youngsters, whose cognitive abilities generally develop in predictable ways corresponding with their chronological age.

The ubiquity of such classifications also, however, reflects their substantial administrative appeal. Chronological age classifications are easy to administer because chronological age can be readily determined without any need for discretionary judgment. Thus, policymakers are understandably likely to use age as a proxy for a wide range of other less-readily-ascertained characteristics. Indeed, age-based legal classifications are frequently used as proxies for more-difficult-to-measure attributes such as maturity, disability, or financial insecurity.

Consistent with these advantages, chronological age-based classifications are particularly prevalent in policies designed to respond to the risks associated with aging. Indeed, age-based classifications are a core feature of US laws and policies designed to address the needs of older adults. The major entitlement programs in the US – Social Security, Medicare, and Medicaid – have rules that preference individuals for benefits based on advanced chronological age. Most Americans will only become eligible for government-provided health insurance because they become older.

Age-based classifications are also common in policies designed to address concerns about the safety of older adults. Indeed, the use of age-based classifications has increased in recent decades as the US has sought to respond to the problem of elder abuse and neglect. States are embracing elder-specific social service interventions. Almost all states have adopted mandatory elder abuse reporting.Footnote 6 Many of these require third parties to report otherwise confidential information if the suspected victim is above a certain age. For example, Rhode Island requires “any person who has reasonable cause to believe that any person sixty years of age or older has been abused, neglected, or exploited or is self-neglecting” to “immediately” report it to the state.Footnote 7 Others require reporting of suspected abuse when the victim is above a certain age and has a requisite level of disability.Footnote 8

States have also created new crimes that exclusively apply to behavior directed at older adults.Footnote 9 Some states have criminalized certain types of otherwise consensual sexual relationships where the “victim” is an older adult. For example, Washington prohibits sexual relations between disabled persons aged sixty and over and those who provide them with paid transportation.Footnote 10 Similarly, some states have adopted statutes that create criminal liability for certain types of financial transactions if those transactions involve a person of advanced age.Footnote 11 And Maine allows for certain transactions to be voided if they were the result of undue influence exerted on a person aged sixty or older.Footnote 12

8.2 Impact of Expanded Life Expectancy: Recalibration

Expanded life expectancy, and the growing ranks of the extremely old, should trigger recalibration – or, at least, a consideration of whether recalibration is in order – of age-based legal classifications that differentiate among adults.

Recalibration could help to better allocate scarce resources. As the population ages, entitlement programs for older adults will become substantially more costly without recalibration. This has been well recognized in the context of the Social Security system. Scholars and policymakers have long been in conversation about increasing the Social Security retirement age (either the early retirement age, normal retirement age, or both) to maintain the program’s financial solvency. Anne Alstott, for example, has suggested that raising the retirement age for higher-income workers is appropriate both to address the program’s solvency and to further fairness across the life cycle.Footnote 13 Similar suggestions have been made, although with less political support, about raising the Medicare eligibility age in response to changing demographics.Footnote 14

Recalibration could also improve the fit between age-based criteria and the underlying characteristics being targeted. Age-based criteria are often used in policy as a proxy for disability and frailty, but old age is actually a poor predictor of either, especially when it is defined broadly (such as sixty or sixty-five and older, as is common in US policy). At higher age thresholds, by contrast, there is a stronger correlation between chronological age and disability and frailty. For example, although dementia is often thought of as a common ailment in old age, less than 5 percent of those in their seventies have dementia, but over a third of those age ninety and older do.Footnote 15

Thus, ratcheting up age-based eligibility criteria is likely to result in more tailored policy interventions because chronological age is a more accurate predictor of incidence of physical and cognitive disabilities for the very oldest of the old than for older adults who are younger (i.e., the “old-old” and “young-old”). The older the age classification used, the more likely the individuals covered by that classification will have predictable physical and cognitive vulnerabilities and thus the more likely the classification will be a reasonable proxy for such traits.

Recalibration may also impact the experience of growing older, potentially in positive ways for some. Age-based legal classifications help shape the social meaning of chronological age. For example, turning sixty-five is perceived as an entrance into old age and a major milestone for Americans because it has been deemed “retirement age” for Medicare (and previously was “normal retirement age” for Social Security benefits). As one blogger wrote: “Turning 65 years old is one of those life passages – like college hazing and infantry basic training – many men would rather avoid contemplating until it’s upon us … Nobody wants to think about becoming an elder.”Footnote 16 Thus, increasing the minimum age criteria for policies designed to address the needs of older adults may prolong the perceived experience of middle age.

On the other hand, recalibration in the form of simply raising the eligibility age for benefits (e.g., Social Security, Medicare, access to retirement accounts without penalty) will come with substantial costs and often inequitable results. As eligibility ages are raised, we can expect people to remain in the workforce longer, potentially crowding out younger workers and workers with lower wages.

Increased inequities can be expected because although people’s chronological age increases at parallel rates, their biological ages do not. Biological age, which may be estimated based on biomarkers and other indicia of health, occurs at different rates in different people. In addition to genetic contributors, socioeconomic status, lifestyle, and environmental factors, including exposure to pollution, may impact the rate of biological aging.Footnote 17 Thus, responding to increases in longevity by increasing eligibility thresholds – without accompanying those changes with new supports that meet the needs of those of advanced biological age – will tend to be increasingly regressive: disproportionately disadvantaging already disadvantaged and marginalized groups.

In short, the rise of the 100-year life should not simply cause recalibration of age-based classifications; it should trigger reconsideration of their use in the first place.

8.3 The Impact of Expanded Life Expectancy: Reconsideration

The rise of the 100-year life should revive and reenergize the classic debateFootnote 18 over what role (if any) chronological age should play in determining rights or establishing eligibility for benefits. That is, it should seriously call into question not only what age-based classifications are used but also whether such classifications should be used at all.

One reason that expanding life expectancy should also prompt reexamination of the use of age-based legal classifications is that chronological age is likely to be an increasingly poor proxy for underlying characteristics that policymakers wish to target (e.g., functional abilities or needs).

As life expectancy increases, we can expect increased heterogeneity in the experiences and life trajectories of people born in the same year. This is because aging fosters heterogeneity. As a generational cohort grows older, its members become more diverse in their functional abilities and health status. Heterogeneity in health-related characteristics is particularly pronounced in early older age.Footnote 19 Consistent with this general pattern, a recent study of older adults in Canada, which considered thirty-four health-related characteristics, found that, overall, health heterogeneity peaks around seventy years of ageFootnote 20 but continues to increase for certain characteristics – including functional performance – into at least the eighties.Footnote 21

The increased heterogeneity among age peers reflects, at least in part, the effect of cumulative advantage and disadvantage over the life course. In particular, those with lower socioeconomic status and lower levels of education, on average, experience poor health and more functional limitations than those with higher socioeconomic status and levels of education.Footnote 22

A second more fundamental reason why expanding life expectancy should prompt reexamination of the use of age-based classifications is equity. The expansion of the ranks of centenarians, and the oldest-of-the-old more broadly, is not evenly distributed in society. Although it is often said that everyone grows old, this is simply untrue. Old age is not an inevitable experience. Not everyone will reach older age. Illness, accidents, and violence mean that many will die in their youth or younger adulthood. As of 2021, life expectancy at birth for non-Hispanic Black Americans was six years less than for non-Hispanic white Americans, and more than seven years less than that for Hispanic Americans.Footnote 23

Very old age is even less certain. As of 2018, less than 10 percent of Americans born alive lived to the age of ninety, and under 2 percent lived to be 100. Incidence of very old age varies by race and ethnicity. For example, as of 2018, Hispanic Americans were nearly twice as likely to live to age 100 as non-Hispanic Black Americans, and nearly 2.5 times as likely to live to age 100 than non-Hispanic white Americans.Footnote 24 The likelihood of reaching very old age also varies substantially by socioeconomic status. In fact, in the US, educational attainment level is one of the strongest predictors of adults’ health and mortality. Notably, the gap in life expectancy by socioeconomic status is widening in many parts of the country. A recent study of disparities in mortality found that the gap between those with higher levels of education and those with lower levels of education has widened in many states (especially those in the South and Midwest) since the mid 1980s.Footnote 25

Even if all Americans had an equal chance of surviving to very old age, however, the rise of the 100-year life would create new equity concerns about policies that disproportionately allocate resources to the very old. This is because such policies may create an inequity from a lifespan perspective. When compared with younger adults, older adults appear vulnerable. However, when compared to others of their own birth cohort, older adults are resilient – they are the survivors and privileged relative to others born at the same time who did not live to old age. Thus, policies that target older adults for special assistance may further entrench inequities by reducing the overall share of resources spent on groups that disproportionately die at younger ages (a group disproportionately composed of those with lower educational attainment, the poor, individuals with disabilities, and Black Americans).

In short, the effect of differences in life expectancy means that the use of age-based classifications is likely to increasingly result in an inequitable distribution of resources. As gaps in longevity increasingly accrue to some socioeconomic groups and not others, policies that differentiate among adults based on chronological age will increasingly serve to compound disadvantage or advantage.

Radical reconsideration of age-based criteria may have some advantages for older adults. Age-based classifications are typically thought of as benign with regard to older adults. Yet, this is increasingly untrue as states adopt legislation that – in the name of protecting older adults from abuse and exploitation – selectively burdens the rights of older adults.Footnote 26

Moreover, reconsideration may benefit older adults even when it involves reconsidering policies that in fact provide for a preferential treatment of older adults. Chronological age criteria that are used to establish eligibility for benefits or to set legal duties, but which are not highly correlated with need or do not reflect meaningful differences in capabilities, may perpetuate stereotypes about age. This in turn can fuel ageism (i.e., stereotyping and discrimination based on age). Policies that provide special benefits to older adults or try to limit or punish certain types of arrangements if they involve older adults (e.g., certain types of sexual relationships or financial transactions) may promote stereotypes about older adults as helpless, frail, or unable to make decisions. Such ageist stereotypes are not merely distasteful; they may increase risk of elder abuse. Although the empirical evidence of the link between ageism and elder abuse is still emerging and more is needed to show that ageism in fact causes elder abuse, there is some suggestive evidence that points to a likely causal connection.Footnote 27 As Edman Palmore has argued, “stereotypes of the old as helpless, worthless, and repulsive” may promote elder abuse by encouraging “people to vent their frustrations on elders or to see them as vulnerable targets for exploitation.”Footnote 28

A move away from age-based criteria has precedent. It would be, for example, consistent with a shift in the law’s approach to court-appointed guardians and conservators. Historically US states have authorized the appointment of a guardian or conservator to make decisions for people whom a court determined had a particular status, such as old age and a disability associated with old age, or a particular medical diagnosis. Influenced by the Uniform Probate Code’s alternative approach, states have largely moved away from such status and age-based criteria. Today most states only permit the appointment of a guardian or conservator – and the corresponding removal of rights from the person for whom one is appointed – if a court finds that individual has functional limitations that result in a need for such an arrangement.

8.4 An Alternative Framework

A reconsideration of age-based classifications should lead to a move away from using chronological age as a proxy for other ascertainable characteristics – such as disability, health status, or financial insecurity – in favor of more direct approaches. In a world where chronological age is likely to be an increasingly poor indicator of functional ability or need, and where socioeconomic gaps in life expectancy are substantial, it will be increasingly indefensible to use chronological age to differentiate among adults.

Chronological age should not be seen as a reasonable criterion for targeting public policy interventions simply because it is convenient or perceived to be a proxy for need, health status, or vulnerability. Instead, polities should seek to find alternative targeting mechanisms. To do so, polities should consider the growing literature on how “vulnerability” can be a basis for the allocation of resources. This school of thought builds on Martha Fineman’s “vulnerability theory,” which proposes that vulnerability is inherent to the human condition, and that governments therefore have a duty to respond by ensuring that all people have equal access to societal institutions that distribute resources.Footnote 29 The approach has captured the imagination of some elder law scholars already.Footnote 30 For example, in the context of old-age policy, Swedish scholars Titti Mattsson and Lottie Giertz look to Fineman to argue that states should move away from allocating social services based on group-based identities like age or diagnosis; instead, they propose, the state should focus on vulnerability – which they describe as allowing for more individualistic interventions.Footnote 31

The vulnerability approach is a promising alternative to group identity (e.g., race, gender, poverty) as a basis for targeting social welfare policy. However, as I have discussed at length elsewhere,Footnote 32 policies cannot respond to vulnerability merely as a universal characteristic of human beings. Thus, using a vulnerability approach to target policy interventions requires a contextual approach that defines vulnerability relative to the threat being addressed and targets people based on their vulnerability to a specific problem. This would be consistent with a conceptualization of vulnerability being a product of the relationship between individuals and their environment.

By way of example, imagine a state wished to address the problem of financial exploitation. Adopting a vulnerability approach would suggest that states should resist the urge to create age-specific crimes (like “elder abuse” or “exploitation of an elderly adult”). Instead, the state should identify factors that make people susceptible to such exploitation or its impacts and allocate resources with a view to supporting conditions that increase resilience to financial exploitation. Thus, states might support interventions that target conditions associated with the risk of exploitation, such as social isolation, lack of long-term care supports, limited financial literacy, and lack of access to civil legal services for those who experience exploitation.

While vulnerability will increasingly be a superior basis for distributing resources, it would be a mistake to demand an end to all age-based classifications. Even with demographic shifts, polities could reasonably use age-based criteria where their underlying policy goal is specifically related to chronological age. A polity could decide – as a matter of public policy – that it considers age to be an appropriate and ethical basis for allocating resources (e.g., health care, basic income) or assigning duties (e.g., participation in compulsory education). Similarly, a polity might reasonably choose to allocate resources in a way that explicitly favors older adults to express appreciation for older adults or reward them for the contributions they made during their lifetimes. There are times where policymakers may wish to use age-based legal classifications not as a proxy for other characteristics but because policymakers think chronological age itself matters. For example, schemes that provide pension payments to older adults (such as the US Old Age Survivor’s and Disability Insurance program – commonly referred to as Social Security) may also function as a way for society to express appreciation for older adults or reward them for the contributions they made during their lifetimes. Favoring older adults for public benefits may compensate for disadvantages associated with older age. And the prospect of future benefits may help all people by reducing the fear of aging.

Likewise, increased longevity does not call into question distinctions between minors and adults. It remains reasonable for polities to continue to distinguish between adults and minors in a host of situations. Among children, chronological age remains a reasonably robust proxy for the stage of development. Moreover, a polity will frequently have compelling justifications for treating children differently from adults. For example, it might reasonably decide to provide public education to children but not adults on the grounds that children can make best use of that resource because of their development stage or because they will (on average) have more years of life to benefit from that public investment.

In addition, whether abandoning age-based criteria will actually further efficiency and equity depends on politics. Efforts to replace age-based eligibility criteria in critical social safety net programs, such as Social Security and Medicare, risk unleashing political forces that would dismantle the programs.

Thus, those seeking to replace age-based classifications with targeting based on vulnerability will need to be mindful of the potential political consequences of their actions, as well as the additional administrative costs associated with the use of what are likely to be more complex classification systems. But in a world where age-based classifications are becoming more inefficient and inequitable, the benefits of abandoning age-based classifications will likely increasingly outweigh the costs.

8.5 Conclusion

This chapter has examined how the law should respond to the challenge posed by old age when old age itself is changing. It has suggested that, as life expectancy increases, the use of age-based classifications will become less efficient and more regressive. Accordingly, not only will age-based criteria need to be recalibrated to ensure that scarce resources can be allocated efficiently, but the use of such criteria should be reconsidered altogether. A promising alternative to reliance on age-based criteria is to use a vulnerability-based approach: targeting social welfare interventions to populations based on the population’s vulnerability to the particular concern the intervention aims to address. While this approach may lack the alluring convenience of age-based criteria, it has the potential to more equitably and efficiently allocate resources in an aging world.

9 Working to Death Labor Law and Collective Voice in the 100-Year Life

The premise of this volume – that human beings will soon regularly live to be well over 100 years old – seemed quite plausible just a few years ago. But in the time since Linda Gratton and Andrew J. Scott published The 100-Year Life in 2016, the unprecedented COVID-19 pandemic ravaged the globe, increased morbidity, and, for a period of time, significantly reduced human lifespans. Even assuming we have emerged from this public health debacle with the 100-year life once again a possibility, the pandemic has exposed the extent to which any promise of extended life is likely to be defined by deep inequities. Working-class people, and workers of color in particular, are the least likely to enjoy extended lifespans. And if they do live longer, they are unlikely to enjoy a leisurely retirement in which they decide how they spend their extra years. Instead, they are likely to face more toil and precarity.

This chapter imagines a different future. It asks: What would the 100-year life look like if working people had a greater hand in shaping it? What would a legal regime look like that gave working people power to affect decisions about how work is structured and how resources are distributed in the era of the 100-year life? How might we reimagine labor law for a more just and equitable 100-year life?

9.1 Working to Death

For many Americans, work is characterized by low wages, long hours, little autonomy, and deep precarity. The pandemic also made work life-threatening. While highly paid professionals retreated to computer screens and home offices, low-wage service workers risked their lives, with few rewards. Those who were in unions were able to negotiate greater protective equipment, safety precautions, hazard pay, and leaves of absence for individuals most at risk. Yet the vast majority of US workers lacked such collective representation. And the vast majority were employed at will, subject to dismissal for any reason or no reason at all (save legally proscribed reasons like discrimination). Against this background, most workers were fearful of reporting violations of workplace safety and health standards that put them, their coworkers, and their communities at risk of infection.Footnote 1 Indeed, when workers requested protective equipment like masks and gloves, some employers retaliated, even barring workers from speaking out about weak COVID-19 workplace safety standards.Footnote 2 For older workers, for whom the risks of COVID-19 were vastly increased, the lack of a collective organization and resulting lack of power to negotiate were particularly consequential. Some quit their jobs; others risked their lives. Racial inequities intertwined with these class and age inequities: Working-class Black and Latino males faced the largest decrease in life expectancy as a result of the pandemic, while workers of color were hit the hardest by rising unemployment. These dynamics meant that millions of workers, already on the brink, faced eviction, food shortages, and mental health crises.Footnote 3

Even after the pandemic began to subside, age, gender, and racial inequalities in the labor market persisted. As the job market recovered, older workers had more difficulty reentering the labor market than their younger counterparts; women, too, failed to reenter the job market at the same rate as similarly educated men.Footnote 4 The pandemic highlighted and increased the amount of care work that people, particularly women, performed without compensation or acknowledgment. And although the unemployment rate for people of color bounced back to prepandemic levels, the racial unemployment and wage gaps remained “high and widespread.”Footnote 5

In short, the pandemic and its aftermath left little doubt that, if our political economy remains unchanged, the 100-year life, if not elusive, will bring only more years of arduous work for the vast majority of workers, particularly low-income workers, workers of color, and women workers.

9.2 The Need for Worker Power

How, then, to think about reforming workplace law in the event of the 100-year life? Two other chapters in this volume focus on employment law. Professor Kenji Yoshino considers the pressing problem of how the law can effectively protect against age discrimination in an era in which workers live longer. He argues for unmooring the age discrimination paradigm from the traditional civil rights model, and for the law to take into account the distinctive fears that older individuals conjure about their own mortality. Professor Cynthia Estlund’s chapter tackles a related problem: ensuring workers’ retirement security over the course of longer lifespans – a problem made more challenging by the fact that most workers already lack adequate pensions and retirement savings. Estlund concludes that it will be necessary to extend work in order to approach a sustainable ratio of workers to retirees, and of work years to retirement years. She also considers how to address the problems of intergenerational competition and integration at work in a world with transformative new technologies and longer lifespans. Noting that a longer life could increase employers’ tendency to dismiss or refuse to hire aging workers, she renews calls not only to strengthen antidiscrimination protections but also to limit American law’s adherence to employment at will. In an earlier work, Professor Anne Alstott argued for enhancing and revising the Social Security program and delinking benefits from paid work to increase portability and part-time feasibility.Footnote 6

Alstott, Estlund, and Yoshino are all correct that finding new ways to fund retirement, delinking social benefits from employment, rethinking age discrimination law, and protecting workers from unjust termination are all critical policy reforms in an era of extended lifespans. But those reforms are unlikely to be achieved or sustained in ways that address the fundamental inequities that will characterize work in the 100-year life without also addressing the problem of collective voice among workers. That is, if workers are to enjoy longer lifespans and a more dignified and remunerated work life during their expanding lifespans, the law must also include a framework that gives them greater power over decisions about the shape of work and the political economy.

9.3 The Decline of Unions – and the Failure of US Labor Law

In the aftermath of the New Deal and World War II, more than a third of US employees belonged to unions. With workers able to exercise collective power in the workplace, the economy, and the halls of government, inequality was at an all-time low. Labor unions not only fought for higher wages and better working conditions but also backed early state efforts to establish social insurance programs, lobbied for a comprehensive federal retirement bill, and supported the eventual Social Security Act of 1935.Footnote 7 Social Security, in particular, proved to be a crucially important program, lifting millions of seniors out of poverty.

But the goal of an enduring collective voice for working-class people in the US was not achieved. From the outset, at the insistence of southern legislators, millions of workers, primarily African Americans, were explicitly excluded from labor law – as domestic workers and agricultural workers – or worked in sectors and regions of the country that were, in practice, largely unorganized. And unions soon came under significant attack. The 1947 Taft-Hartley Act curtailed numerous labor rights and excluded yet more workers from coverage. Moreover, although the left-leaning industrial unions in the 1930s and 1940s pushed for a social democratic system of universal health care and other social benefits delinked from employment, by the 1950s they had lost this fight. Retirement benefits, as well as health insurance, became closely tied to employment, and unions themselves became more bureaucratic and inward-facing.Footnote 8

By the 1970s, US companies had adopted a position of intense resistance to unions: They globalized and fissured their employment relationships, eliminating union jobs while ramping up their antiunion practices against new organizing efforts. Meanwhile, the Supreme Court interpreted the National Labor Relations Act (NLRA) in ways that limited the ability of workers to bargain and strike in the changing economy.Footnote 9 Union membership declined precipitously. Today, while the rate of unionization is on the rise, it stands at about 6 percent among workers in the private sector and only about 10 percent among workers overall.Footnote 10

Economic inequality is now at its highest point since the Gilded Age, when unionization rates were similarly low.Footnote 11 And as workers have lost economic power, they have also lost political power. Wealthy individuals and corporations spend vast sums to influence elections and legislative and administrative processes, while workers have largely lost their collective organizations that enable them to engage effectively in politics. Not surprisingly, studies suggest that elected officials are almost entirely unresponsive to the concerns of the poor and working class – at least when their preferences diverge from those of the wealthy.Footnote 12

Meanwhile, although state and federal employment laws, which proliferated in the 1960s, provide a host of protections to workers as individuals, many rights go unenforced or underenforced. Wage theft, health and safety violations, and sexual harassment are rampant in many workplaces.Footnote 13 Individual workers, lacking bargaining power, are frequently forced to sign away their rights to go to court and even to proceed collectively in arbitration.Footnote 14 Unlike most advanced industrial democracies, the U.S. does not guarantee workers health insurance; nor do most workers receive compensation for the important labor they perform caring for their children or their elderly relatives. Retirement security is, for many, elusive: Just 15 percent of private sector workers had access to a defined benefit plan in 2020,Footnote 15 while Social Security benefit cuts are still being implemented from reforms in 1983.Footnote 16

Meanwhile, millions of the most vulnerable workers, predominantly people of color, remain excluded altogether from both collective labor law and individual employment law as independent contractors, domestic workers, or agricultural laborers. These exclusions are particularly relevant for seniors who are more likely to work as independent contractors than younger workers.Footnote 17 And one in five workers in their fifties and early sixties work in jobs that lack health or retirement benefits, making it much harder to prepare for retirement.Footnote 18 In fact, seniors often take on these jobs specifically to supplement inadequate retirement savings.Footnote 19 And while workers in nontraditional jobs are vulnerable due to these statutory exclusions, the ability to work longer to finance a comfortable retirement is already stratified by income: Higher-income workers tend to retire later than lower-income workers, who are more likely to exit the labor market at a younger age due to health issues, caregiving responsibilities, or job loss.Footnote 20

On the positive side, a host of recent organizing efforts among workers, from Amazon warehouse workers to healthcare workers, from Uber and Lyft drivers to journalists, have drawn attention to these problems. These workers seek tangible improvements in their jobs; they also seek basic dignity at work. As one Amazon worker involved in a unionization campaign observed, “You’re running at a consistent, fast pace … You ain’t got time to look around. You get treated like a number. You don’t get treated like a person. They work you like a robot.”Footnote 21

Meanwhile, seniors have remained organized and politically engaged on issues related to retirement. Notwithstanding the national decline in membership in unions and other civic organizations, the AARP – an organization devoted to organizing and advocating for retirees – maintains a membership of nearly 40 million. The AARP has played a key role in opposing various efforts to erode retirement benefits. For example, in 2021, the AARP lobbied against the TRUST Act, which would empower congressional “rescue committees” to make changes to Social Security and Medicare. While Republican legislators have recently floated both the idea of “sunsetting” the Social Security Act and a federal budget plan that would cut benefits, AARP’s political power suggests that these efforts will not go very far.

Though the problems that workers will confront in any future 100-year life are palpable and the interest in organizing to solve such problems is significant, the existing legal frameworks are of little utility. About 70 percent of Americans approve of unions, yet obstacles to achieving unionization among workers even in the traditional labor force are substantial.Footnote 22 The law permits employers to engage in a wide range of efforts to persuade workers not to organize while excluding union organizers from the workplace. Moreover, when employers resort to illegal tactics such as threatening or firing workers for organizing, they incur virtually no penalties. Meanwhile, the law does not only exclude independent contractors, agricultural, and domestic workers, but it altogether lacks a framework for retirees and unemployed workers to organize into unions or for unions to bargain to address many problems facing retirees. That is, the law mandates only that employers negotiate with unionized employees about wages, benefits, and working conditions at a single workplace. It does not set up a system for sectorwide bargaining in order to raise wages and benefits throughout the industry, nor does it create a system for bargaining about broader social programs.

One proposed legislative reform – the Protecting the Right to Organize (PRO) Act – would better protect traditional workers in the process of organizing, bargaining, and striking, including by increasing penalties when employers attempt to coerce or retaliate against employees for unionizing.Footnote 23 The PRO Act would also extend employee status to many workers now classified as independent contractors, like gig workers, FedEx drivers, and many more. These reforms could prove extremely helpful in enabling workers to exercise more voice at work.

However, even with these important reforms, US labor and employment law would not be well designed to give workers a voice in how to structure work and the broader political economy during the 100-year life. This is because even the improved law would lack a framework for retirees and unemployed workers to organize (while still excluding domestic and agricultural workers), and it would lack a system for sectoral or social bargaining. That is, even if the PRO Act passed, US labor law would continue to channel organizing and bargaining to individual worksites, between traditional employees and single firms, without giving worker organizations power to negotiate sectoral standards or broader social benefits. Yet, in a world in which employees, over the course of a lifetime, work for many different firms, move in and out of the workforce over a longer lifespan, spend more years working a reduced load as they age, or spend more years in retirement or caregiving, a labor law system organized solely around worksite-by-worksite bargaining for private benefits makes little sense.

9.4 Alternative Approaches to Worker Voice and Power

The US approach sharply differs from many European systems that are better positioned to enable worker voice over the course of an extended lifespan, though their systems too face significant limitations. For example, in Germany, the union federations participate in basic decisions concerning national wage policy and policies relating to employment, economic growth, and social insurance.Footnote 24 Meanwhile, collective bargaining occurs on a regional basis to set wage scales that cover all workers, at least in manufacturing sectors; those agreements then provide a floor above which local bargaining may occur.Footnote 25 Many German workers also have a voice at their worksite through statutorily guaranteed works councils.Footnote 26 Such works councils are granted codetermination rights on topics such as health and safety and working hours.Footnote 27 They also are entitled to information and consultation rights on topics such as the introduction of new work methods and technologies – an especially important right in a time of rapid technological change. Additionally, workers at large companies have an automatic voice through representation on corporate boards.Footnote 28

In Denmark, unions have played an even more active role in negotiating social policy. Unions and employers have, for example, collectively negotiated national policies on worker training and parental leave. Moreover, union bargaining in Denmark often builds on statutory entitlements. For example, while older workers and workers with disabilities had statutory protections against age discrimination, social partners expanded these protections through collective bargaining such that workers now have the right to be placed in “light jobs” if they are unable to perform their positions.Footnote 29

And in Norway, unions, employers, and the state have joined together to bargain for policies that improve working conditions so that older workers can remain in the workplace.Footnote 30 This bargaining produced the Inclusive Workplace Agreement, which aims to reduce the use of sick and disability leave, extend workers’ working lives, and recruit more workers with disabilities and other vulnerable groups.Footnote 31 The social partners also serve on the board of the government-funded Centre for Senior Policy, which performs research regarding senior workers and works with companies to improve their policies.Footnote 32

In France, the political organization of unions enables them to mobilize on issues regarding retirement. For example, in 2023, in response to President Emmanuel Macron’s proposal to reform the pension system by raising the legal age of retirement from sixty-two to sixty-four, France’s eight largest labor unions coordinated nationwide strikes across multiple sectors, including transportation, education, and energy.

These systems are by no means perfect. Workers’ power in these countries has also declined in the face of globalization and neoliberalism.Footnote 33 However, a viable framework exists to set fair standards for all workers and to enable senior workers and retirees to exercise their collective voice.

The US lacks any comparable framework. To be sure, the law does facilitate workers’ political voice in important ways. Section 7 of the NLRA has been interpreted to protect workers’ concerted activity that occurs through political channels – even for nonunion workers, as long as such activity relates to employment issues.Footnote 34 In addition, unions, like other organizations, may engage in electoral politics and lobby government officials. Many unions spend a great deal of energy and money on political activity, with significant effect. They have helped enact legislation that protects all workers, from the Fair Labor Standards Act and the Occupational Safety and Health Act to the Family and Medical Leave Act and the Affordable Care Act. But US law does little to facilitate a voice for working people in the various decisions that affect senior workers or that will be posed by the putative 100-year life.

9.5 A New Labor Law for the 100-Year Life

What might a different system look like, one that builds on the current regime but gives workers – who may soon enjoy longer lifespans and many different stages of work – greater power over decisions about the shape of work and the political economy?

First, as in the industrial democracies discussed earlier, the law should provide for sectoral bargaining so that collective bargaining agreements apply to workers throughout a region or sector, effectively forming the basis for employment policy in those sectors, while at the same time providing for worker voice at the worksite and firm level through works councils, local unions, and corporate board representation.Footnote 35 Such a model would enable workers to move between firms more easily over time and limit risks of leaving and entering the workforce. More generally, research suggests that where sectoral bargaining is combined with worksite organization, racial and gender wage gaps decrease and unions can exercise more economic and political power.Footnote 36

Second, the law should also give organizations of workers a formal role in developing social benefits and policies that will be critical for expanding lifespans, for example, through administrative processes at the local, state, and/or federal levels of government.Footnote 37 Beyond simply permitting group participation, as notice-and-comment rule-making currently does, the law could give worker organizations a formal seat at the table in negotiating retirement, disability, family leave, and childcare benefits, and, perhaps, eventually job guarantees, basic income, and more.

Third, to make such social bargaining effective for workers at every stage in the 100-year life, the law should encourage or facilitate new forms of worker organizations that encompass a broader range of working-class people, including those unemployed, engaged in paid and unpaid caregiving, and retired.Footnote 38 Examples of such nontraditional worker organizations exist within our own system, past and present. For example, following the Great Depression, unemployed workers organized in large numbers.Footnote 39 The movement of the unemployed originated in local communities, with protests and marches demanding – and sometimes winning – public relief funding from local and state governments. Members of unemployed worker groups also banded together and entered relief offices demanding immediate relief for individuals denied aid. A national federation called the Workers Alliance was later formed, consisting of most of the large organizations of unemployed workers. This federation prioritized lobbying for national relief programs over direct action in localities; ultimately, it was unable to win passage of its prioritized legislation for expanded direct relief, higher pay on federal Works Progress Administration projects, and a permanent public works program, and its local organizing diminished as well. Still it provided an important voice for unemployed workers through a critical period.

Welfare organizing of the 1960s provides another example of a nontraditional working-class organizing effort. During this period, welfare recipients, the majority of them Black women, began to organize to change local welfare policies, overturn benefit denials for members, and win special grants for welfare recipients to cover household furnishings and clothing.Footnote 40

Numerous examples of organizations engaging workers in nontraditional employment exist in the contemporary landscape. For example, home-care organizing has engaged hundreds of thousands of low-wage, formerly isolated workers in collective organization, even without the existence of a central worksite or single employer, helping raise wages and improve funding for caregiving.Footnote 41 The Freelancers Union represents independent workers, offering insurance benefits and other resources to various types of freelancers and advocating for legislative protections on their behalf. The Domestic Workers Alliance has succeeded in winning domestic workers’ bills of rights in numerous states; the bills provide employment protections such as paid time off and overtime rights. Many Hollywood writers work independently, but through their membership in the Writers Guild of America, they are guaranteed minimum pay levels, residuals, and retirement and health coverage. And community-based worker centers across the nation have organized to combat wage theft, co-enforce workplace protections with state and local governments, and advocate for increased pay and protections.

In a different vein, several organizations already organize retirees. AARP provides individual benefits to members and advocates on behalf of older and retired Americans. The Alliance for Retired Americans is sponsored by unions and aims to mobilize retired union members, seniors, and community activists to advocate for various political causes such as Social Security expansion and reducing prescription drug prices. Several unions also have their own retiree chapters and organizations.

More examples exist abroad. As Professor Katherine Stone has detailed, Japan has seen an explosion of nontraditional forms of labor organizations: City unions have pressured employers in an entire metropolitan area around work-related concerns; women’s unions have organized to further the interests of women workers; and ethnically specific unions have asserted pressure on behalf of ethnic groups.Footnote 42 In Europe’s most progressive social democracies, not only are traditional unions engaged in defining social programs that benefit all workers, but nontraditional worker and retiree organizations exist as well, working to advance policy concerning issues such as social security, pensions, and health treatment among retirees.Footnote 43

These kinds of nontraditional but democratic organizations can be nurtured and expanded with supportive legal frameworks.Footnote 44 For example, law can facilitate the growth of organizations by enabling the aggregation of resources, by allowing access to workers, information, and free spaces to organize, and by effectively protecting workers from retaliation for organizing and engaging in concerted action. In addition, by granting organizations a role in negotiating social benefits in administrative processes, as discussed earlier, the law can give the organizations greater legitimacy, aiding their organizing efforts. Government programs can also partner with democratic membership organizations that represent underrepresented constituencies, giving them grants to provide and administer benefits. For example, under the Ghent system, unions operate unemployment insurance funds and provide benefits to unemployed workers.Footnote 45 US policymakers could extend this model to provide portable benefits, training, and increased workplace enforcement to workers across the span of the 100-year life.Footnote 46

9.6 Conclusion

As Anne Alstott has written, the predicted “leap in longevity is likely to challenge many of our expectations about work” and could “revolutionize” many of our relationships.Footnote 47 But without a fundamental change in the way work is organized, the leap in longevity will also augment and extend existing power dynamics that define the lives of many workers in America, making inequalities and indignities even more acute. To avoid that result, workers – of all kinds and backgrounds – must have a voice in the decisions about what work looks like over the course of the 100-year life.

Of course, one might worry that the reforms suggested above are fanciful or impossible to achieve. Indeed, past experience highlights the difficulty of labor law reform, even in times of unified democratic control of government.Footnote 48 Yet the obstacles have been overcome in the past and can be overcome again.Footnote 49 COVID-19 made the economic plight of poor and working-class Americans politically salient, as illustrated by the massive, redistributive economic stimulus enacted in March of 2021 and subsequent legislation like the Infrastructure Investment and Jobs Act of 2021 and the Inflation Reduction Act of 2022. The resurgence of organizing among workers, tenants, and debtors that has occurred in the wake of the pandemic has only increased this salience. Meanwhile, the federal structure of our government creates openings for legislative change at the state and local levels, even when federal change is impossible. Ultimately, even if the more ambitious reforms discussed earlier are not possible in the near term, incremental, achievable reforms can get us closer to a world in which workers are not working to death but rather have a collective voice in the 100-year life.

10 The Savings Mirage

Walk into any bookstore’s self-help section and you will find a wall of books that were written with one goal: to help Americans figure out how to save money. Saving money is widely considered the cornerstone of how to have a successful life and, perhaps most of all, a relaxing and successful retirement. The titles say it all: “Saving for Retirement Made Easy,”Footnote 1 “Winning at Retirement,”Footnote 2 “How to Retire Debt-Free & Wealthy,”Footnote 3 and so on. The message is clear: It is possible to retire with abundant savings – you just have to learn more and be strategic.

The reality, however, is that retirement savings are an insurmountable aspiration for many Americans, particularly low-wage workers. Indeed, almost one in four Americans has less than $400 in savings.Footnote 4 One-third of Black households have zero or negative net worth.Footnote 5 But much like the self-help books in the corner of the bookstore, the government’s response to this overall lack of savings has been to emphasize the need for individuals to save.Footnote 6 Policy initiatives have focused primarily on consumer financial education and nudging people in the “right” direction.

Yet, despite the emphasis on saving for retirement, as Anne Alstott and others have discussed in depth, elderly Americans whose incomes are at the low end of the income distribution are increasingly worse off than their higher-income counterparts.Footnote 7 They enter old age with little or no savings, medical problems without adequate coverage, a necessity to work in order to eat and have a place to live, and, unsurprisingly, increasing rates of bankruptcy filings.Footnote 8

In the past, retirement years were limited in duration for most Americans, as a brief jaunt of post-work life was soon met with death.Footnote 9 Indeed, between 1650 and 1850, elderly Americans were less than 2 percent of the population.Footnote 10 Yet, as life expectancies have increased,Footnote 11 we are faced with the prospect of elderly Americans living in poverty for decades on end. In other words, in the past the problem of no savings, and thus elderly poverty, was simply less of a problem since Americans, on average, spent fewer years in retirement. This, in turn, meant the financial struggle of the retirement years would also be relatively short. But with the 100-year life becoming a reality for more Americans, an elderly poverty crisis looms.Footnote 12

In this chapter, I unpack the contradiction in the message embedded in our cultural narrative about the moral worth of self-sufficiency and savings against the backdrop of the realities of our existing poverty laws. I show how this is a central and unresolved incongruity in US policy toward the poor and near poor. The government does not provide a solid financial foundation for older Americans who were making poverty- and near-poverty-level wages during their preretirement years, yet the government also does not allow those making low wages (low enough to not even provide for basic necessities such as housing, food, and clothing despite full-time work) to build a nest-egg for retirement. This antisavings policy – enforced through asset limitations for basic safety net programs such as the Supplement Nutrition Assistance Program (SNAP, commonly referred to as “food stamps”), Temporary Assistance for Needy Families (TANF, commonly referred to as “cash welfare”), and Social Security Disability Insurance (SSDI, commonly referred to as “disability”) – essentially guarantees that those who are poor will continue to be poor and without savings throughout their extended old age.Footnote 13 Therein lies the savings mirage.

I argue that as a society we have to get our story straight. Are we committed to a country in which we require people to save for themselves in order to avoid an old age of hunger and financial instability? If so, we need to implement policies that make it easier to save, not only for those who are middle or upper class but also for those who are low-income throughout their working years. On the other hand, if we are committed to restricting the savings of low-income workers because of our devotion to the notion that public benefits should only go to those who have otherwise stripped themselves of savings, then we need to develop a plan to provide in retirement for those who struggled through their working years, unable to save in part because of strict government policy. But we can’t have it both ways. If we continue with the crash course we are on, an elderly poverty epidemic is bound to emerge. New safety net policies show some promise, but this central contradiction in message and policy needs to be recognized in order to promote substantial policy change.

10.1 A Savings Society

The history of responsibility for the elderly in the US is an evolving one. Life was short in the mid 1800s, with the life expectancy of most white Americans only thirty-nine years.Footnote 14 But those who did live into old age and were poor were usually out of luck. The elderly were generally considered a “burden on the local taxes,” and many were either sent to poorhouses, which were “dreary, vermin-infested, and laden with human waste,” or auctioned off as farm labor.Footnote 15 By the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, “the status of seniors had reached its nadir,” a time when old age was thought of as a disease in and of itself.Footnote 16

After the Great Depression, life expectancies were increasing as were the percentage of elderly Americans living in poverty – by 1935, 50 percent of elderly Americans were poor, and by 1940, almost two-thirds were poor.Footnote 17 These staggering numbers, along with the realities of the Great Depression, led to President Franklin D. Roosevelt signing the Social Security Act of 1935 into law.Footnote 18 This was the beginning of a significant shift, where American values transformed and the government began investing in elderly economic security.Footnote 19 Indeed, in 1965, Lyndon B. Johnson’s administration furthered the goals of Roosevelt by enacting Medicare and Medicaid. At the same time, following World War II, employers began to expand retirement benefits for their full-time employees, providing them with defined benefit pensions and other important benefits for old age. Taking all of these changes together, Americans could in general depend on economic security in their old age.Footnote 20

In the late 1970s and early 1980s, however, the concepts of individualism and self-sufficiency began to pervade US culture and politics.Footnote 21 A weakening of the safety net for Americans, including older Americans, followed. Employers began to replace mandatory pension plans with optional higher-risk 401(k) plans that do not guarantee a certain income during retirement, social security payments were reduced, and many more jobs did not provide any avenue at all for retirement savings.Footnote 22 Jacob Hacker refers to this as the “Great Risk Shift,” one where “a myriad of risks that were once managed and pooled by government and private corporations shifted onto individuals and families.”Footnote 23

But people are still getting old, and life expectancies are continuing to increase, with the 100-year life in sight for many Americans. In response to increased longevity, there has been a renewed sense of urgency by the government in setting expectations – expectations that Americans must save for their own retirements. We have transformed into a country that says “take care of yourself” – even when you are old. In 2000, then Treasury Secretary Lawrence Summers gave remarks focusing on the need to encourage Americans to save more.Footnote 24 He said that it was critical not only “to our economic health” but also for families “because it influences their capacity to manage what is new in the New Economy: not least, the fact that people are living much longer than before.”Footnote 25 He went on to discuss the (increased) chances of people living to ninety years old, then concluded that “as people are retiring earlier and living longer, retirement spans for many individuals are approaching half or more of their working lives.”Footnote 26 Summers acknowledged the challenges that come with longer lifespans and then summarized his goals for the speech as follows:

  1. 1. First, discuss why increasing saving is so crucial both for the American economy as a whole and for the economies of individual American families.

  2. 2. Second, discuss our approach to increasing saving based on improving financial literacy and promoting financial access. Recent economic research demonstrates that saving is like any other form of consumer behavior: It is governed by habit, is responsive to social signals, and it can be promoted.

  3. 3. Third, discuss the growing problem of borrowing, or negative saving.

  4. 4. And fourth, discuss specific legislation that goes beyond existing incentives to further promote savings among Americans who have not had the opportunity to avail themselves of existing incentives.Footnote 27

The government’s recent policies and rhetoric indicate that Summers’s vision lives on – we must teach Americans how to save and provide behavioral nudges and incentives for doing so.Footnote 28 Indeed, in 2015, the Treasury Department released a treasury note entitled “Helping More Americans Save” in part to mark “America Saves Week, an annual opportunity to encourage all Americans to save and a chance for individuals and families to take stock of their financial health and preparedness.”Footnote 29 The notice, released by J. Mark Iwry, then Senior Advisor to the Secretary of Treasury for Retirement and Health Policy and the Deputy Assistant Secretary for Tax Policy, noted that “[s]avings for retirement is one of the best ways to prepare for a secure financial future.”Footnote 30 And further, the Treasury Department was “ensuring that more Americans have the knowledge and tools to manage money and credit responsibility because educated and financially capable consumers can better attain their own financial goals and contribute to the strength of our overall county.”Footnote 31

There are moralist and paternalistic overtones to both of these releases. The idea is fairly simple: Some Americans are not financially educated and need help “learning” how to save, so the government will do the work to improve “habits,”Footnote 32 as Secretary Summers put it. The lesson seems to be that if we create opportunities to save, change habits, and increase social pressure, we will see a difference. There was little discussion in either release (or others like them)Footnote 33 of the structural conditions that make it difficult for Americans to save.

The federal government and federal laws certainly incentivize savings and wealth accumulation. But as others have documented in detail, most of these programs primarily benefit middle- to upper-income white citizens. For instance, our tax code has written into it several savings incentives, but low-income people rarely benefit from these incentives.Footnote 34 There are some other programs that are more inclusive, but in general they are small in scale and come and go. For example, Treasury created the “myRA” retirement savings program, which was designed to be a starter retirement savings program. It was supposed to help low-income workers who didn’t have access to retirement savings plans through their jobs, but the take-up rate was low, and it was eventually shut down after Treasury found it not to be cost-effective.Footnote 35 Other Treasury programs sought to work with employers to create simple retirement plans for workers not covered by existing plans.

Ultimately the social construct of savings as moral, trainable, and the right thing to do pervades the culture in the US. And existing research shows that low-income Americans have adopted this ethic and in fact desperately want to save – they even work the existing savings-unfriendly systems to try to force themselves to save.Footnote 36 However, their efforts are often in vain, in part because of the underappreciated aspects of our laws and policies that make it almost impossible for the working poor to save. In the next section, I discuss these restrictions.

10.2 Restrictions on Savings

There are a plethora of reasons why it is difficult for Americans to save. Wage stagnation and rising expenses are significant factors. A 2019 study found that 53 million Americans, accounting for 44 percent of American workers between the ages of eighteen and sixty-four, qualified as “low-wage” earners.Footnote 37 The median hourly wage of those low-wage workers was $10.22, with median annual earnings of about $18,000.Footnote 38 Further, over half of low-wage earners were either the only workers in their family or lived in families where all workers were low-wage.Footnote 39 While wages went up a bit in the midst of the pandemic, a recent study found that in 2022 more than 51.9 million workers, or almost 32 percent of the labor force, made less than $15 per hour.Footnote 40

Such low wages leave families vulnerable to economic insecurity – just one small shock, such as missing work due to an illness, a funeral of a family member, or a needed repair for a car used for transportation to work, can send these workers into financial turmoil and create a need to depend on the scant public safety net that is available.Footnote 41 In fact, many low-wage workers even working full time and without experiencing economic shocks must depend on Medicaid and food stamps to get by. Numerous studies and reports confirm that large companies pay their workers such low wages that these workers need public assistance, even when working full time.Footnote 42

Even at times when low-wage workers have the opportunity to save – when perhaps they receive an unexpectedly large tax return, they are given extra hours at work, they receive a stimulus payment/credit, or they sell a prized possession for cash – our poverty laws often prevent these workers from accumulating any meaningful savings. How is this possible in a society that so values saving? It happens through asset limitation laws that affect every major public assistance/antipoverty program (outside of the tax system) that provides money or money-like relief to low-income Americans. These limitations impose rigid restrictions on the amount of cash and assets aid recipients can accumulate. Thus, recipients are in a bind. If they attempt to put away meaningful savings when they receive a lump sum in the form of, for instance, a stimulus check or tax credit, they cannot continue to access the programs they need to survive month to month.

Before Ronald Reagan was elected, states set welfare programs’ eligibility requirements. President Reagan, however, campaigned in the early 1980s on a promise to reform welfare by cracking down on “welfare queens” (a term he popularized) who, he claimed, abused the public welfare system. During a 1976 stump speech, Reagan described the welfare queen as follows: “She has eighty names, thirty addresses, twelve Social Security cards and is collecting veterans’ benefits on four non-existing deceased husbands. And she’s collecting Social Security on her cards. She’s got Medicaid, getting food stamps and she is collecting welfare under each of her names. Her tax-free cash income is over $150,000.”Footnote 43 Welfare recipients were portrayed as primarily Black, and the media and other politicians perpetuated this (inaccurate) image.Footnote 44

While Reagan did not succeed in the massive welfare reform he promised, he was able to push through asset restrictions on major welfare programs, which largely remain in place today (though states have regained some control). Reagan did this via the Omnibus Reconciliation Act of 1981, which set asset limits at $1,000 for most welfare programs, a large decrease compared to then-existing state limits. And the federal limits had teeth. A study conducted ten years after Reagan left office showed that low-income single mothers reduced their personal savings by an average of $1,250.Footnote 45

Following Reagan’s presidency, the poverty laws in our country moved even further in the direction of building expectations for families to develop and sustain their own safety nets, both during their working years and into their old age. In the mid 1990s, Bill Clinton ran for president on a campaign promise to reform cash welfare (then Aid to Families with Dependent Children – AFDC) into a program that would promote “personal responsibility” and “economic self-sufficiency.”Footnote 46 When Clinton was elected, welfare reform was indeed passed, transforming AFDC into TANF, stripping away the existing safety net for families, and turning welfare into a bare-bones program with much state control.Footnote 47 Further restrictions for eligibility were put on cash welfare, such as more work requirements and a five-year lifetime limit.Footnote 48 As part of the changes, states regained control to set asset limits, but only some states made changes.Footnote 49

Asset limitations may seem like small potatoes, but a large percentage of the population is potentially subject to them. Indeed, roughly 20 percent of the US population participates in means-tested government aid programs each month.Footnote 50 Generally people move in and out of public assistance programs. Of those who participated in public assistance programs between January 2009 and December 2012, the largest share, 43 percent, stayed in the programs between thirty-seven and forty-eight months. Another 31.2 percent of participants stayed in programs between one and twelve months.Footnote 51

Asset limits vary significantly program by program and even state by state. For instance, the Supplemental Security Income (SSI) asset limit, which is controlled at the federal level, is $2,000 for an individual and $3,000 for a couple.Footnote 52 Asset limits for SNAP are set by the federal government at $2,750, and $4,250 for households containing a member who is disabled or over sixty.Footnote 53 However, states can modify or even eliminate SNAP asset limits through categorical eligibility. TANF limits, now set by states, vary from $1,000 to $10,000 or even no limit, with the average around $1,000–3,000.Footnote 54 And Medicaid asset limits again are set by states and most have not increased the dollar limit since 1989.Footnote 55 State limitations vary significantly – there are usually none for children, but in about half the states, there are limits for families, usually between $1,000 and $6,000.Footnote 56

For some of these programs, one vehicle (or a certain amount of vehicle value) is excluded from the asset limits, but no more than that. And treatment of retirement savings is “confusing and seemingly arbitrary.”Footnote 57 When asset tests were first enacted in the 1970s, defined benefit plans such as traditional pensions were common, and asset limitations for some programs (SNAP, for example) did not count such accounts in the asset calculation. But today, most employees, particularly low-income ones, do not have access to traditional pension plans. Instead, if they are part of any plan at all, they tend to be part of defined contribution plans, such as 401(k)s.Footnote 58 And if a worker is laid off from a job that includes a 401(k), that 401(k) will likely be rolled into an IRA, which then is counted. Those accounts are not exempt from most asset limitation tests for public benefits.Footnote 59

Asset limitations help ensure that the poor remain poor. Indeed, studies have shown that asset limits create disincentives for low-income families to save. Multiple studies have confirmed that families save more when asset limitations are lower or nonexistent, and save less when asset limits are instituted.Footnote 60 Further, to the extent that low-income families may find a work-around by saving money “under their mattress” at home, such practices are counter to the fairly well-accepted goal of trying to move more low-income people to be banked rather than unbanked.Footnote 61 But if there is a sense among low-income families that their bank accounts will be surveilled and used against them via asset limit investigations, then they are acting rationally by remaining unbanked and outside mainstream financial institutions.

It is important to understand asset limitations for what they are: a significant, though often overlooked, part of America’s structural racism that perpetuates the racial wealth gap and disproportionately leaves poor, Black, elderly Americans struggling. While in absolute numbers whites far outnumber Blacks in their receipt of public benefits, rates of participation in public assistance programs are higher among Blacks. According to the US Census Bureau, in 2012, 13 percent of white Americans participated in a public assistance program, compared to 42 percent of Black Americans.Footnote 62 Thus, asset limitations perpetuate the racial wealth gap by disproportionately preventing Black Americans from accumulating savings or wealth and, thus, also leave Black Americans particularly vulnerable to experiencing poverty in their old age.

10.3 Where Are We, and Where Can We Go from Here?

So where does this leave us? We are at a crossroads, no doubt. While there is a widespread belief that we do in fact take care of our elderly, that Medicare and Social Security cover people in old age, the data show otherwise. The failure of these programs to fully support the poor in old age has been well detailed by others, particularly Anne Alstott in her important book A New Deal for Old Age.Footnote 63 The data are consistent with Alstott’s findings. Being old and poor is not uncommon.Footnote 64 One study found that roughly one in three elderly Americans is economically insecure, living at or below 200 percent of the Federal Poverty Line.Footnote 65 The data for Black and Latinx elderly Americans are even worse, with half living at or below 200 percent of the Poverty Line.Footnote 66 Another study found that 49 percent of older workers and their spouses will experience downward mobility in retirement.Footnote 67

Ultimately, a key problem is that our savings rhetoric largely does not mesh with our law. We pretend that we live in a society that provides structures that enable retirement savings for all, and thus, a policy of “encouraging more low-income Americans to save,”Footnote 68 as former Treasury Secretary Lawrence Summers suggested, is a way forward. Encouraging the lowest-paid Americans to save will not cut it, in part because we do not provide realistic structural opportunities for them to do so. Yet we use moralistic overtones around savings to shift responsibility from structures to individuals, all while picking up on Reagan-era tropes about race, potential fraud, and exploitation of government programs in order to support the need for these asset limitation laws.

We must pull out of this false narrative that behavioral interventions are the most promising way forward because savings opportunities are available for low-income workers but often squandered. Once we do so there is much that can be done. Fortunately, the good ideas are abundant, but more attention to this issue is needed. During the height of the COVID pandemic, the Child Tax Credit was improved in multiple ways – increasing the amount per child, broadening the credit’s scope, and making it fully refundable. Allocation of the credit was based entirely on income, not assets. The expansion of the Child Tax Credit was not extended, but perhaps as advocates continue to work toward expansion, the ability to save for the long term should be centered in the conversation. The key problem now is that when poor families gain the opportunity to save, through an expanded social safety net, a promotion at work, or something else, this is a positive change that can help secure their future into old age. But when and if they need to access safety net programs such as SNAP or TANF (or continue receiving help from such programs), the savings will become a burden – something they will have to spend down in order to qualify or continue to qualify.

We can attack the problem in one of two broad categories of change, though the best plan is likely one that pursues both of these avenues. If we want to depend on people to create their own nest-eggs for retirement, then we need to repeal asset limitations and provide benefits and structures, early and often, that allow even our lowest-wage workers to save, and save at a rate that would support them in retirement. Given the very low wages of many Americans, the government would likely have to provide, at a minimum, matching funds, and probably even supplemental funds, in order for such a program to work and make a meaningful difference in retirement savings.

Alternatively, or perhaps in conjunction with an aggressive savings program, reforming social security to truly be progressive can eliminate elderly poverty for many Americans. Such a reform would need to take into account the reality that, at least without change, our structures prohibit many seniors from saving for retirement, and the program would need to provide extensive benefits to these seniors in order to keep them from living an old age of poverty. There are several existing comprehensive plans to reform social security, and an extensive discussion of such plans is not warranted here. However, my broader point is that in order for such plans to gain traction, we need to transform the moralistic narratives around savings that pervade our culture and have been circulating for decades. Indeed, we need to align the national conversation about savings with the realities of the structural systems we have in place – including the laws that prohibit low-income Americans from saving while accessing needed support during their working years.

10.4 Conclusion

Ultimately, only when we shift the cultural narrative, peel back the moralistic and judgment-laced rhetoric around poverty, savings, and retirement, and acknowledge existing structural barriers to savings can we then rebuild these structures and circumvent the looming elderly poverty epidemic. If we want the “golden years” to be golden for everyone, it is imperative to attend to this now. As plans and nudges to help Americans save pervade, asset limitations must be addressed in order for these programs to make a meaningful difference in the ability of low-income Americans to save for retirement.

11 Trusts and the 100-Year Life

As human lives grow longer, what will happen to the law that governs death? How will a person’s property be divided at death, and will we see any changes in the way people make wills, trusts, and plans for the distribution of their estates after they pass away? In this chapter, I argue that the answers to these questions are surprising: As lives grow longer, the law of property distribution at death will become less important. People who expect to live into their second centuries will have less property to pass at death and will feel a greater need to hand it over to their descendants and beneficiaries before they die. The law of trusts and estates will remain a bedrock feature of the legal system, but it will look more and more like a backstop and less and less like a preferred mode for dividing up the bulk of accumulated estates.

11.1 Background

The declining importance of the law of decedents’ estates promised by the lengthening of human lives will intensify a trend that has already been growing for decades. As John Langbein explained in a seminal law review article in 1988, the law of estates has been diminishing in importance since at least the middle of the twentieth century, and possibly long before.Footnote 1 The causes are many. One is the transformation in the character of wealth. Whereas the estates of the old aristocracies prototypically consisted of land, today wealth tends to consist primarily of financial assets, such as securities, savings accounts, and insurance contracts. These forms of financial assets are much easier to transfer than land and, therefore, require less attention from lawyers and judges when they are transferred at death. Similarly, much of the wealth that passes from generation to generation in 2024 consists of investments in human capital that tend not even to register as forms of wealth transfer at all. When a professional family devotes hundreds of thousands of dollars to the private education of its children, no intervention by a probate court is needed.

Still another cause of decline in the law of probate is the growth and now dominance of forms of wealth transfer that self-consciously avoid the law of probate. Life insurance proceeds, bank accounts, retirement accounts, and brokerage accounts can all be crafted to name beneficiaries to take assets in the event of an owner’s death. When the day comes, the assets move solely by the actions of these financial institutions, with no need for a will or probate court. Even a family home can be owned jointly with a right of survivorship, so that a spouse’s death automatically transfers their share to the spouse who survives, again with no need for probate.

Estate-planning practitioners have cut further into the domain of the probate courts by mastering the so-called “revocable trust.” A revocable trust is a trust that its creator – known as a “settlor” – can take back at any time. A revocable trust can work as an excellent substitute for a will because, like a will, it does not become permanent until the settlor’s death. The settlor can add and remove assets from it as the settlor pleases during their lifetime, making no final decisions until moments before they pass away. The revocable trust offers many advantages, one of which is to avoid probate. Since, at the time of a settlor’s death, the property in a revocable trust formally belongs to the trustee rather than the settlor, the property is not part of the settlor’s estate for purposes of probate. The dispositive terms of the trust need not be filed with a probate court, and lifetime transfers to the trustee generally cannot be challenged as part of probate proceedings.

The intentional attempt to avoid probate reflects the reality that probate is often expensive and time-consuming, especially for modest estates that have little need of the benefits probate ostensibly offers. If an estate of modest size can be divided up by a series of financial institutions that merely carry out the orders embedded in financial contracts, the estate can often avoid the costly intervention of lawyers, the potential for dispute, and the occasions for taxation and fee extraction that tend to follow entry into probate.

11.2 Less Wealth at Death

The lengthening of human lives will intensify this downward trend in the importance of probate for two reasons. The first is that decedents will have less wealth to pass. For the same reasons that lengthening lives will strain systems of public retirement support, they will also strain private savings. As working years take up a smaller share of human lives, workers will have to spend more years living off of their savings. To support a period of extended retirement and prolonged illness, family homes will have to be liquidated, 401(k) accounts used up, and savings accounts eaten away. All of this will leave fewer assets to be transferred when a person passes away.

Some portion of the burden on private savings might be lightened by lengthening years of work. If people spend some of their extra years working and saving, the financial pressure of those extra years will not be as intense as if people spent all of their extra lifespans on the golf course. But there remains a real possibility that the extra years in income-earning labor will not be enough to compensate for the extra years in retirement and illness. If that happens, the size of probate estates and even nonprobate transfers will decline. A person will have to use their savings to support themselves rather than to provide for the next generation.

11.3 Greater Urgency of LifeTime Transfer

For the fortunate few who have a surplus of wealth even after their extended years of retirement, the lengthening of life will intensify the downward trend in death-time transfers for a second reason: People will feel a greater need to pass their wealth before they die. The trouble is that the age at which people conceive and bear children is not growing as quickly as the age at which people die. Many people can now expect to live past 100, but relatively few will bear children past forty. As a result, the gaps between generations, though growing, are not growing as quickly as human lives, so that as parents die at older and older ages, their children are receiving transfers of wealth at later and later stages in their lives. Think of the difference between Queen Elizabeth II of the United Kingdom, who ascended to the throne at age twenty-five after her father passed away at the age of fifty-six, and Elizabeth’s son Charles, who remained a prince into his seventies as his mother continued to occupy the throne well into her nineties. Few families have thrones to pass on to their children. But what about homes, cars, and 401(k) accounts?

This postponement of wealth transfer presents a problem. Money is often most useful when a person is young. This is partly a result of the cycles of human lives and earnings. Income tends to grow over the first five or six decades of life, so that an educated person in their twenties will tend to earn less than they will in their forties or fifties. Help with a down payment for a house is thus more useful when the person is young and has a lifetime of mortgage payments and future earnings still ahead than when they are middle-aged and have a padded savings account and a mortgage that is already half paid off. A related concern about life cycles is that a person’s propensity to consume tends to drop later in life. Extra money has little appeal for an infirm elderly person who no longer needs fashionable clothes, comfortable vacations, or extra square footage. A parent with extra resources to spare might therefore feel a greater urgency to subsidize children and grandchildren while they are still relatively young than older children who have established incomes.

Money also tends to be useful when a person is young because money has a time value. The foundation of finance is the conviction that money today is worth more than money tomorrow. All else equal, therefore, a child and his family will prefer to start consuming today than wait for another thirty years while the old family home sits underutilized by parents. Like all rational people, Junior might prefer to spend money now than later. Even if we set aside the concerns about Junior’s uneven income over the course of his life, we might still be concerned about the simple time value cost of forcing Junior and his offspring to wait to enjoy the fruits of grandparents’ savings. Some of these concerns about time value might be mitigated by the possibility of investment growth. That is, Junior might be rewarded for his patience with compounding returns on the savings and a larger ultimate inheritance upon the death of his parents. But savings may not grow at a rate commensurate with the discount factors of younger generations, especially if the savings consist of assets that are costly to maintain or that might decline in value, such as homes and cars.

A final reason to hasten the transfer of wealth is that wealth sometimes requires active management or even active consumption. Think of a family business in which a founder must transfer control to their children. A son might take over the family restaurant, or a daughter might assume the corner suite of the family investment office. In an age when retirements were short and death came early, the transfer of control over a family business often coincided with death. Junior would take over the day Father was laid to rest. As retirements and lives lengthen, death-time succession will no longer suffice. Later generations have to be given control well before earlier generations pass on. We cannot expect an elderly founder to effectively manage a business into their eighties and nineties, and we cannot expect their children to wait for them to retire when they are in their fifties and sixties.

The need for active management often mixes with a need for active consumption. Though remaining in the family home may be satisfying and comforting to an elderly person who has spent most of their adult life there, the prolonged decades of occupancy may come at a significant financial cost if the home is large enough to be used by (and sold to) a family with children and if it decays through the neglect of maintenance and renovation that often accompanies aging.

The need to shift transfers from death to life will intensify a problem that estate planners have always known and have always struggled with, which is how to balance the need for income in retirement with the need for timely transfer to the next generation. Mother might recognize that it would be good to pass on assets to Junior sooner rather than later, but at eighty-five years old, Mother might not know how many of these assets she will need to support herself for the rest of her life. If she has a million dollars in savings, she might need all of it if she expects to live another twenty years, or she might need just half of it if she expects to be gone in just another ten years. If she knows that Junior and his children could use the money now, how is she supposed to predict how much to give now and how much to hold on to? This is an old problem, and it long predates the growth of the 100-year life. But the greater strain on personal finances and the larger bands of uncertainty introduced by longer lives and retirements will make this needle even harder to thread.

The risk of passing too much too early makes it clear that what we need is not simply to smooth the making of transfers during life but also to allow such transfers to be made flexibly, so that gifts can be made and then taken back if the life and needs of the donor become unexpectedly long and great.

11.4 Challenges

What, then, stands in the way of such a system? What do we need to do to make it possible for long-lived people to pass their property before they die even as they retain enough control to take some of it back to meet the needs of an unexpectedly long life?

Many of the obstacles involve taxation. The system of unified estate and gift taxation we now have in the United States is a major accomplishment, in that it tries to treat life- and death-time transfers as part of a single pool. The details are complicated, but the basic gist is that if I make a gift during my life, I have to file a gift tax return in the year I make it, but I will owe no tax until the total of my life- and death-time gifts together exceeds the value of my exemption from the estate tax. Any excess over the exemption gets taxed only at the time the threshold of exemption is crossed, whether that happens in life or death. This system largely avoids the need to pay taxes on transfers during lifetime for any but the very wealthiest families.

Some obstacles to lifetime transfers remain, however. One is the so-called step-up in income tax basis at death. If a donor takes a piece of property in life and then holds it as it appreciates in value, the income tax basis for the donor is usually the price at which the donor purchased the property minus any depreciation. Were the donor to sell the property during their lifetime, they would owe income tax on the appreciation. But if the donor waits until their death and then transfers the property by will, the basis of the donees will equal the value of the property at the time of the donor’s death, appreciation and all. Were the donees to sell the property immediately after the donor’s death, they would owe no income tax. Lifetime transfers do not receive the same favor. The donee of a lifetime gift receives the same basis as the donor.

The trouble, of course, is that this system creates profound incentives to hold property until death. If I bought a house in Palo Alto in 1975 and watched it skyrocket in value through 2024, it would be disastrous to sell or donate the house before I passed away. Instead, the tax incentive would be to hang on to the house for all 110 years of my long life and then leave it to my children in my will. A lifetime transfer would be an income tax disaster. A death-time transfer is the only rational strategy.

One can imagine strategies for accelerating the use of the property, but none is fully satisfying. I could rent the house out and make a gift of the income to my children every year. But the income might exceed the annual gift tax exemption. Additionally, I would owe income tax on the rental income, and my children would not have immediate access to the full value of all the capital accumulated in the house.

Another obstacle to flexible and accelerated transferring is the generation-skipping transfer tax. If a 110-year-old donor hesitates to make a gift to their child who is already eighty-five years old, then the donor could achieve greater value for the gift by handing the assets to a grandchild or even great-grandchild who can make better use of the money. If the goal is to support someone who has yet to attend college, a donor can simply select a beneficiary further down the family tree. The donor can wait until death and still see the assets go to a person who is young enough to genuinely need them.

The problem with this strategy is the generation-skipping transfer tax, or GST tax. The tax is designed to ensure that assets subject to the estate tax get taxed at every generation. Congress did not want a person to be able to pass their fortune to their great-grandchildren without making the fortune subject to estate taxation at the deaths of the person’s children and grandchildren. To put it a bit crudely, the GST tax imposes the estate tax multiple times, based on the number of generations the donee sits below the donor on the family tree.

Private estate planners have developed strategies for handling the GST tax. One is the creation of a perpetual trust that is funded with assets up to the full amount of the estate tax exemption and then made perpetual so that it can benefit the donor’s children, grandchildren, great-grandchildren, and other descendants later on. Since the transfer was made only once, the trust can continue to benefit the donor’s descendants across many generations without encountering estate or gift tax.

The perpetual trust has its drawbacks, however, including the obvious governance problems that come with having something exist forever, not to mention the fact that it only works for the estate tax exemption amount, which, though relatively high right now, might easily come down in the future to levels that make life uncomfortable for a greater share of the public.

A further obstacle to lifetime giving is the tax benefits of retirement accounts. A person who contributes to a 401(k), IRA, or similar retirement account owes no income tax on the money contributed at the time of the contribution and continues to owe no income tax as the investments appreciate until the time the person makes a withdrawal. Such accounts can be leveraged to great effect, ensuring that assets appreciate over time without being periodically reduced by capital gains taxation. The effect can be compounded by continuing to hold the account until death and then handing it over to children and letting them continue to enjoy the same benefits until they are forced to make withdrawals of their own. The length of time a child can hold the account was diminished by the tax reforms of 2017, but the possibilities for savings by keeping assets inside the account after a donor’s death remain substantial. The benefits available under these retirement accounts thus encourage death-time transfers, because there is no way to hand these assets to spouses or children during the donor’s lifetime without undoing the tax benefits.

One might argue with respect to all of these tax issues that convenience and efficiency are not the only policies we must consider in taxation. We have to think about the raising of revenue, redistribution, and so on. Retirement savings, for instance, are supposed to be used to fund retirement, not to accumulate dynastic wealth, and so one might not be troubled by the possibility that lengthening lifespans may complicate the accumulation of dynastic wealth. My point, however, is that whatever our other goals for taxation might be, the lengthening of life will put pressure on them to the extent people come to prefer life over death in the timing of wealth transfers. Tax policy has several goals, but one of them is to avoid distorting people’s behavior. And to the extent tax law encourages a person to cling to property they do not need until they pass away at 110 just so their descendants can save money on taxes, it will be shaping people’s actions in ways that are not socially optimal.

In addition to posing problems for taxation, a shift toward lifetime giving will raise other challenges for the system of wealth transfer as well. In particular, one wonders about the future of life insurance as a form of wealth transfer. By its nature, a term life insurance policy does not pay out until the insured person dies. So, what if the great length of a person’s expected lifespan pushes the person to prefer a transfer before their death? Life insurance will not be a good option. People will continue to use life insurance as a protection against the prospect of an untimely death, but it will cease to be an attractive option for transferring wealth when death comes late.

11.5 Conclusion

One might think that as people live longer lives, the system of law that governs the transfer of their property at death would become more important. But the opposite is true. People will have fewer assets to transfer at death and a stronger desire to transfer them during life. People will want flexibility between life and death, and they will want the law to help them achieve it.

12 The Right to Grow Old

Americans have no right to grow old. Or so we are told. In 1985, in a case holding that the rights of people with disabilities were to receive no special constitutional protection, Justice Byron White worried in his majority opinion that people with intellectual impairments constituted so broad a class that there would be no “principled” way to distinguish discrimination against them from burdens on “the aging, the (physically) disabled, the mentally ill, and the infirm.”Footnote 1

The clear implication was that these other burdens were self-evidently permitted. And so, for the Court, the idea that laws burdening the elderly might be worthy of special attention from judges was not just wrong but also so obviously wrong that it could serve as the lead float, as it were, in a parade of horribles. This chapter is about what US courts find so horrifying about a right to grow old, and whether they are right to be afraid.

It is important first to clear some definitional underbrush. There is, to be sure, a right to grow old in a sense. Deriving from the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendment rights not to be deprived of life without due process of law and the Eighth Amendment right against cruel and unusual punishments, Americans enjoy a right against arbitrary killing at the government’s hands.Footnote 2 Should the state choose to end your life before you become elderly, it had better have a good reason for doing so. This is the right to grow old in its negative sense, as a right against certain kinds of state action. This negative form is the one US constitutional rights typically take.

Even this negative right has its limits. If the state is not ending life but is merely burdening the elderly in some other way, courts don’t take much notice. Age discrimination is barely scrutinized under US constitutional law.Footnote 3 The traditional reasons for greater scrutiny, grounded in a group’s relative lack of political power, its historical marginalization, or its vulnerability to overbroad and harmful stereotypes, can apply to the elderly with great force. US courts nonetheless tend to consider discrimination against older people to be obviously rational even when it is sloppy and harmful.Footnote 4

The positive version of the right to grow old, such as it is, is still more limited. In this form, it is not so much the right to life as the right to live. It is the right to the support needed to maintain an adequate quality of life up until death. The elderly face predictable challenges that arise less from choices they have made than simply because they are human, and therefore mortal. Our physical dexterity and mental acuity typically lessen as we age, sometimes to a point where they become debilitating in the way of severe physical or mental disabilities. Providing care for older Americans also imposes burdens on the professional lives of family members, and especially women. These challenges require our care, our attention, and our money. The costs of medical care and supervision needed for the elderly to retain their dignity are overwhelming. And even if the morbidity of old age is reduced in the future,Footnote 5 we can still expect that as Americans live longer on average, the wages they will have earned in their working lives will be insufficient to cover these costs. They – we, inescapably – will need help.

It might seem as though help is not forthcoming, at least not from constitutional law. Judges accustomed to the American way of thinking seem to resist positive rights. The US Supreme Court has been unusually clear that the Constitution protects individuals against certain state-inflicted harms but generally does not require the state to ensure a minimum quality of life or prevent or deflect the predations of private actors.Footnote 6 Of a piece with this narrow rendition of constitutional rights, the Court has also been clear that state actions that reliably burden even protected classes, such as those defined by race, sex, or religion, will be viewed as constitutionally uninteresting unless a victim can show that the state was trying specifically to harm the members of those classes.Footnote 7 The US Supreme Court’s theory of the Constitution’s protections appears to view rights as arising only in those cases in which the government is acting pathologically, not when ordinary governance happens (even knowingly) to spoil some lives along the way. This kind of constitutional austerity sweeps the legs from under any putative right to grow old.

An aging population calls for reconsideration of the constitutional status of the elderly. We can expect rational stereotypes about the capacities of older Americans, already troubling, to become ever more outdated and limiting. We can also expect inequality to rise as Americans get older; basic survival skills tend to atrophy with age, and there is reason to be skeptical that future Americans will muster the political will to redistribute wealth to make up for it.

Constitutional law can only do so much for a miserly nation, but the prospects for some contribution are less bleak than they might appear. Positive rights are more prevalent in American constitutional law than US courts typically admit. Although courts are, for the foreseeable future, unlikely to create new substantive positive rights out of the cloth of the US Constitution, positive rights are best understood not as new rights but as the positive sides of older ones. And there are US constitutional rights whose protection requires the government to take on affirmative obligations. The Supreme Court’s rejection of overt protection for positive rights has been deliberate, reflecting less an inherent feature of the US Constitution than a persistent divide in US politics, particularly around issues of race and class. Carving out some constitutional space for a right to grow old would require less a sledgehammer than a scalpel, less a constitutional invention than an exercise of judgment.

12.1 Positive Rights at the Supreme Court Bar

The Supreme Court has said repeatedly that the constitution protects negative rather than positive rights. Most bracingly, in the 1989 case of DeShaney v. Winnebago County Department of Social Services, the Court denied that a boy who had been beaten into a coma by his father had any constitutional rights against the county welfare workers who had negligently kept the boy in the father’s care.Footnote 8 “Our cases have recognized,” Chief Justice Rehnquist wrote, “that the Due Process Clauses generally confer no affirmative right to governmental aid, even where such aid may be necessary to secure life, liberty, or property interests of which the government itself may not deprive the individual.”Footnote 9

The refusal to understand the Fourteenth Amendment’s rights provisions as conferring a duty on the state to protect citizens from private injuries is consistent with a set of cases that arose in the 1970s, when the constitutional status of the welfare state remained very much in play. Thus, the Court held that a family had no right to have its state welfare benefits increase commensurate with family size,Footnote 10 that a woman had no right to a publicly funded abortion, even one that was medically necessary,Footnote 11 and that kids in poor neighborhoods had no right to have their public schools funded on par with those in rich neighborhoods.Footnote 12

But as hostile as the Burger Court and its sequelae have been to positive rights, the constraint the Court’s body of cases imposes on the recognition of such rights is best understood as one of degree rather than kind. Positive rights are not a question of which rights the Constitution protects but rather about what the government is obligated to do in respect of those rights. Rights to food, shelter, education, health care, and other rights often associated with the positive dimension of rights do exist under US constitutional law. The Constitution does not permit the government to take food off American tables or prevent Americans from educating themselves.Footnote 13 When courts and commentators say that Americans lack positive rights, what they typically mean, rather, is that the federal Constitution does not obligate the government to provide these entitlements or facilitate access to them. In the language of international human rights law, the government has a duty to respect these rights, but it does not have a corresponding duty to protect or promote them.

This limitation is strict and marks the US as a global outlier, but it is not categorical. The Supreme Court has recognized some instances in which the respect the government must afford to rights extends to positive duties to facilitate their exercise. For example, the constitutional right to counsel is understood not simply as a “negative” right of criminal defendants to bring their own counsel to court but has been read to include a positive right to have the government provide counsel to indigent defendants.Footnote 14 The right to vote is not simply a right not to have one’s vote unreasonably denied but also imposes obligations upon states to create an effective infrastructure for receiving and counting ballots. The right to marry is not just a right to hold oneself out as married but includes an obligation on the state to solemnify the marriage and, therefore, make married persons eligible for certain state benefits. Even in the US, then, the fact that a right is recognized does not, ipso facto, tell us the degree to which its positive dimensions are constitutionally resonant.

The text of the US Constitution is unhelpful here. Many courts around the world protect the positive dimensions of rights, but the different approach they take to these questions is not, as many believe, because their written constitutions provide for these rights explicitly. Although most of the world’s constitutions are indeed longer and more explicit than that of the US, including when it comes to rights often characterized in positive terms, the text of the US Constitution determines neither the substance nor the degree of its rights commitments. As David Strauss has observed, the rights the Constitution protects are surprisingly disconnected from its specific language.Footnote 15 The Constitution contains no explicit rights against race or sex discrimination, no right to vote, and no free speech rights against states. The degree to which these or other rights are respected, protected, or fulfilled by US courts depends on acts of construction that could as easily apply to rights to food, health, education, and so forth.

Indeed, US courts nearly accepted this invitation in the 1960s and 1970s. Positive rights relate closely to what American lawyers call the “state action doctrine” and what lawyers in many other parts of the world describe in the language of “horizontal effect:” To what extent does the Constitution require private actors to respect constitutional rights? A constitutional ban on private forms of discrimination is functionally related to a constitutional requirement that the government protect individuals against abuse by private actors. And by the late 1960s, six justices on the Supreme Court were willing to hold that, in at least some senses, the US Constitution could be read to reach such abuse.Footnote 16 This posture was manifest in a series of cases that prevented privatization as a means of evading desegregation measures, shielded “sit-in” protesters from state trespass laws, and affirmed Congress’s power to guard against private discrimination.Footnote 17

During the same period, in cases concerning the state’s obligations toward those it seeks to prosecute criminally, the Court held that the state had to engage in prophylactic acts that lowered the risk of faulty convictions, most famously when it found that the government had to pay for a lawyer for indigent defendants.Footnote 18 In extending this last right to the appeal stage, the Court relied not on the Sixth Amendment right to counsel but on the Equal Protection Clause, reasoning that, in the government’s refusal to fund appellate counsel for indigent defendants, “an unconstitutional line [had] been drawn between rich and poor.”Footnote 19 Later, in striking down Virginia’s $1.50 poll tax, the Court again relied on the presumptive impermissibility of government distinctions on the basis of wealth.Footnote 20 For courts to take seriously the right to be free of the disparate burdens of wealth might, in a practical sense, induce courts to require states to provide certain goods and services to the poor; the only alternative would be to take those goods and services away from the wealthy. An equal protection basis for such holdings could extend them beyond the criminal justice or voting contexts and into other important interests not held to have a specific constitutional basis, such as food, shelter, and health care.

The Court recognized this possibility in later cases placing limits on its incipient wealth discrimination doctrine. Pointedly, in a 1971 decision holding that indigent people can’t be denied marital dissolution based on their inability to pay court fees, the Court relied solely on the Constitution’s due-process provisions rather than equal protection.Footnote 21 Two years later, the Court decided that Texas could tie school funding to local property taxes, plainly disadvantaging students living in poor neighborhoods.Footnote 22 This arrangement did not count as unconstitutional wealth discrimination, Justice Lewis Powell wrote for the 5–4 majority, and the students in poor schools did not suffer so much as to implicate any fundamental right to education.Footnote 23

The San Antonio case was, to be sure, bad news for supporters of positive constitutional rights. Wealth discrimination claims have gotten nowhere since then, and the Court appeared to deny that the Constitution mandated state support for important interests. It is important to linger here, however, because Justice Powell’s rejection of a right to education was not total. Because the state did not absolutely deny poor children’s right to a public education – they got to go to school, after all – the Court did not reach the question of whether a state had an affirmative obligation to provide a minimum level of public education.Footnote 24 And the most significant case to have addressed this question since the San Antonio case, Plyler v. Doe,Footnote 25 suggests that the state might indeed hold such an obligation.

Plyler arose out of a Texas policy that denied free public education to the children of undocumented immigrants. The Court struck it down. While paying lip service to the Rodriguez Court’s suggestion that public education is not a constitutional right, “neither,” wrote Justice Brennan for the majority, “is it merely some governmental ‘benefit’ indistinguishable from other forms of social welfare legislation.”Footnote 26 Justice Brennan singled out “the importance of education in maintaining our basic institutions and the lasting impact of its deprivation on the life of the child.”Footnote 27

Taken in tandem, the Rodriguez and Plyler cases reinforce the idea that judicial recognition of the positive dimensions of rights may be denied at retail, but cannot be denied wholesale. In thinking through how much the crack in the door to positive rights could widen in the case of rights to various forms of support for older Americans, it is necessary to examine the political economy of the right to grow old, especially in relation to rights for which the door has remained closed.

12.2 The Political Economy of Positive Rights

The cases in which US courts stifled the growth of positive rights were not random. They were tied quite directly to race and class and were the products of courts built to produce them. A potential right to grow old involves very different politics.

When Richard Nixon ran for president in 1968 and 1972, his two most significant domestic issue areas were criminal justice and busing.Footnote 28 He used these issues and the racialized frame around them as wedges to try to pry working-class whites away from the Democratic Party. Criticism of the Supreme Court’s decisions on “law and order” and desegregation made regular appearances in Nixon’s stump speeches (as they were, more pointedly, in George Wallace’s).Footnote 29 At the time of the election, President Lyndon Johnson’s nomination of Abe Fortas to replace the retiring Earl Warren was stalled in the Senate, and so the Warren Court was almost literally on the ballot.

The year before, Johnson had made Thurgood Marshall the Court’s first African American justice. Marshall was also, of course, the face of desegregation, and the Nixon and Wallace campaigns and their supporters frequently conflated racial integration in schools with crime. “They are afraid of street disorders and crime,” the New York Times wrote in an article on Wallace’s supporters. “They also hate provocative political demonstrators and they resent incursions of Negroes into predominantly white neighborhoods and schools.”Footnote 30 The militaristic language of infiltration was used to describe violent criminals and Black schoolchildren alike. Nixon was vice president when Brown was decided, and he publicly supported President Eisenhower’s federal interventions in support of integration. Still, especially in light of Wallace’s presence in the race, Nixon suggested that the Warren Court’s desegregation rulings had been too broad and consistently emphasized themes of federalism and local political control.Footnote 31

These law-and-order and desegregation themes permeated Nixon’s judicial selection process. Warren Burger’s selection as chief justice and the choice of Harry Blackmun as Nixon’s second Supreme Court pick owed in part to the perception that they were “law-and-order” judges.Footnote 32 The racial undertones of Nixon’s other two selections were undeniable. Lewis Powell had presided over the Richmond School Board during its resistance to desegregation efforts, vowing that he would never favor compulsory integration.Footnote 33 As a law clerk to Justice Robert Jackson, William Rehnquist had written a memo supporting Plessy v. Ferguson.Footnote 34 (Nixon’s failed nominations of southerners Clement Haynesworth and Harrold Carswell were widely perceived as efforts to appeal to voters who disapproved of civil rights reforms.)

The racial themes of Nixon’s campaign against the Warren Court engulfed his stance on government welfare as well. The common association of “welfare” with irresponsible behavior by racial minorities is well established. Nixon’s 1968 convention speech played on these themes, accusing government welfare programs of “reap[ing] … an ugly harvest of frustration, violence, and failure.”Footnote 35 The case rejecting any constitutional right to welfare, Dandridge v. Williams,Footnote 36 included Chief Justice Warren Burger in its five-justice majority opinion. The cases rejecting the right of Medicaid and state welfare recipients to abortion funding – Maher v. RoeFootnote 37 and Harris v. McRaeFootnote 38 – both included Burger, Powell, and Rehnquist in their narrow majorities. Race was barely below the surface of the abortion issue. As Justice Marshall wrote in dissent in Harris, the abortion rate for nonwhites was about twice what it was for whites, and nonwhites were disproportionately likely to be indigent.Footnote 39

The Court’s opinion in the public school funding case, Rodriguez, decided two months after Roe, had all four of Nixon’s appointees in the 5–4 majority, which Powell authored.Footnote 40 Rodriguez was on its face a case about wealth discrimination, but of course it was also about race, on several levels. Rodriguez was a desegregation case. Demetrio Rodriguez brought the lawsuit on behalf of a group of parents of students in schools in Edgewood, a neighborhood whose public schoolchildren, due in large part to housing discrimination, was more than 90 percent Mexican American.Footnote 41 More broadly, southern states’ massive resistance to the Supreme Court’s injunction in Brown v. Board of Education that they may not racially segregate their public schools was followed by more passive resistance. Minority-to-majority transfer schemes, whereby students could freely transfer out of schools in which they were a racial minority, were struck down by the Supreme Court in 1963.Footnote 42 Closing the public school system to avoid desegregation was ruled invalid in 1964.Footnote 43 Freedom of choice plans, which tended to replicate dual school systems, fell in 1968. Most jurisdictions ultimately settled on geographic zoning as the way to assign students to schools. The problem is that geographic zoning is vulnerable to white flight that can reproduce and reinforce racially identified neighborhoods and schools, such as in Edgewood.

The problem of white flight is stubborn enough on its own – as the busing saga demonstrated – but allowing schools to be financed through local property taxes greatly exacerbates the problem by effectively privatizing public schools. Well-financed schools attract more affluent residents, raising property values. The cycle then repeats. In this way, formally separate but formally equal schools were replaced by informally separate and formally unequal schools. This inequality, though naked, was ostensibly produced through private market ordering and was therefore invulnerable to constitutional attack.

In nearly every case in which the Burger Court conspicuously limited the respect that needed to be shown to the positive dimensions of constitutional rights – in Dandridge, in Rodriguez, in Washington v. Davis,Footnote 44 in Maher – those rights were bound up in race and class politics.

The right to grow old is different in this respect because “[a]ll children, except one, grow up.”Footnote 45 The challenges of aging disproportionately affect the poor and the disadvantaged, of course, but none of us are immune entirely from them. Social Security and Medicare, both of which primarily benefit the elderly, remain two of the most popular government social programs. Research has suggested that media portrayals of these programs tend to be positive and tend to depict white recipients, and indeed that whites with conservative views on race view Social Security more positively than their liberal counterparts.Footnote 46 If the positive dimensions of social rights are ever to find favor with US courts, the rights of an aging population are more likely to be recognized than others.

12.3 Putting Age Discrimination in Context

Viewing social obligations toward older Americans as constitutionally enforceable may require a wholesale shift in cultural attitudes about duties toward others, but adopting a different posture toward rights would get some of the way there. American courts faced with rights disputes tend to load the weight of analysis on threshold legal questions, such as whether the Constitution contains particular rights, who is entitled to hold them, and what the standard of review is when those rights are abridged. Identifying rights with particular categories of deference is thought to discipline the inquiry and subject rights to the forms of analysis – interpretation of written texts, historical understandings, and legal precedents – that judges are competent to perform.

These questions are abstractions, deliberately so, and tend toward a style of slippery-slope reasoning familiar to US lawyers. To those socialized into American rights review, declaring a “right to grow old” seems to entail judges attempting to require the government to fund elder care, to make medical and drug payments, to make its buildings and services more accessible to people with physical and intellectual challenges, to impose certain accommodation requirements in workplaces and public-facing businesses, or even to restructure hiring practices or pension guarantees to enable older Americans to remain gainfully employed. A right to grow old might also seem to require a reassessment of the bounds of the category itself. If there is a right to grow old, why not a right to be sick; to be an addict; to be obese, or short, or tall; or to be less intellectually agile? What accommodations, and at what cost, do people in these conditions require of the government? Where does it end? Not knowing the answer to this question makes a right to grow old seem either unwieldy or lawless. There can be no such right. Right?

Many of the world’s courts approach the positive dimensions of rights differently. They do not refuse to recognize them for fear of slippery slopes, chaotic decision-making, or empowering too many litigants. They also, and relatedly, do not assume that recognizing the need to protect or promote constitutional rights requires them to do so fully or immediately.

In thinking through what particularized, contextual decision-making might look like in the area of age-related burdens, consider two roughly contemporaneous Canadian cases decided under the Charter of Rights and Freedoms. In the first, McKinney v. University of Guelph, private universities in Ontario were sued by professors and a librarian over the schools’ mandatory retirement age of sixty-five.Footnote 47 In the second, Tetreault-Gadoury v. Canada (Employment and Immigration Commission), a woman who lost her job just before turning sixty-five sued over being denied unemployment benefits, which were unavailable to those eligible for retirement benefits.Footnote 48

Either of these cases would be straightforward losses under the US Constitution as interpreted by the Supreme Court. Never mind that the University of Guelph is a private institution and therefore immune to constitutional attack under US state action doctrine (and, it turns out, under Canada’s as well). The key point is that age discrimination receives rational-basis review.Footnote 49 Any conceivable rational reason for age discrimination passes constitutional muster, and there will always be conceivable rational reasons for age discrimination. This is particularly so in the context of social welfare programs designed to address problems that typically arise at particular life stages.

The particular challenged provisions in McKinney and Tetreault-Gadoury had perfectly rational justifications. Mandatory retirement requirements cannot be viewed in isolation from other labor and welfare policies. Often they are the products of delicate collective bargaining or implicit trade-offs that include compensating pension or job security guarantees (including, in the case of a university, a tenure system). These requirements can create job opportunities for younger workers in tacit exchange for requiring those workers to help fund the retirement of their predecessors. In certain settings, moreover, the requirement obviates the need to dismiss older employees for performance reasons, which can be more acrimonious and dignity-effacing than mandatory retirement. The restriction of unemployment benefits considered in Tetreault-Gadoury was designed to prevent people over the age of sixty-five from receiving both pension and unemployment benefits at the same time and to prevent manipulation of the Unemployment Insurance Act by those who were planning to retire.

Unlike in the US, age discrimination is specifically prohibited under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms.Footnote 50 But rather than decide either that age discrimination was so constitutionally offensive that only the most compelling of reasons could permit it, or that age discrimination was easily justified on any conceivable rationale, the Canadian courts carefully examined the justifications themselves. Doing so enabled the Court to come out differently in the two cases based on relevant differences between them.

The McKinney Court acknowledged that the mandatory retirement policies at issue constituted age discrimination but held that the discrimination was justified under section 1 of the Charter, which says that the Charter’s rights guarantees are “subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society.”Footnote 51 Under the proportionality test the Canadian Supreme Court applies in rights cases, this inquiry requires the Court to assess the importance of the state’s objectives, the fit between those objectives and the challenged practice, the necessity of the challenged practice in light of available alternatives, and the burden of the practice in relation to its benefits. Here Justice La Forest, writing for the majority, agreed with the universities’ submission that mandatory retirement enables faculty renewal and bolsters tenure protections, which enhance academic freedom, and that these objectives could not easily be achieved without the policy.Footnote 52 The Court recognized that the important questions were not about whether there was age discrimination, which there obviously was, but whether it was justified in a way that respected both the rights of individual employees and the needs of an important societal institution.

The Court came out differently in Tetreault-Gadoury, which Justice La Forest also wrote. But the contrast with McKinney was not in whether particular rights were recognized or whether a particular standard of review applied. In both cases, the policy before the Court contravened section 15 of the Charter, which prohibits age discrimination. In both cases, the Court reached that view independent of whether the discrimination was intentional or invidious. Under the Charter, discrimination is actionable even if it is indirect or based solely on the adverse impact on a population.Footnote 53 In both cases, moreover, the objectives behind the policy were legitimate and important. The difference was that, in Tetreault-Gadoury, unlike in McKinney, the Court believed those objectives could be achieved without burdening the rights of sixty-five-year-olds. There was no evidence that sixty-five-year-olds were any more likely than others to abuse the system by seeking unemployment benefits for which, by not actively looking for work, they were ineligible.Footnote 54

The Supreme Court of Canada differentiated cases on their facts, on the margins, rather than by putting them into separate legal categories. It was able to both recognize and discipline a right against age discrimination without abstracting away from the context of the cases. The next section generalizes this strategy and discusses others that enable courts around the world to do the same.

12.4 Strategies

There are at least five distinct strategies that courts can deploy to discipline a right to grow old without extinguishing it: (1) proportionality, (2) polycentric constitutionalism, (3) a “minimum core” approach, (4) progressive realization, and (5) remedial flexibility. I briefly discuss each strategy below.

12.4.1 Proportionality

It is sometimes assumed that what makes courts around the world responsive to positive rights is constitutional enumeration. As I show above, this is not necessarily the case, as US constitutional rights are frequently atextual and sometimes have positive dimensions. What does differentiate the US approach to positive rights from that of many other courts is the all-or-nothing frame that US courts often apply. In cases like Rodriguez, courts suggest that positive rights can’t be recognized because they can’t be maximally enforced.

Proportionality – used nearly all the world over, save the US – is an essential tool for avoiding this dilemma. As the Canadian age discrimination cases show, proportionality analysis tends to divert judicial attention away from interpretive questions, such as whether the constitution recognizes particular rights, and towards questions of application, such as the degree of burden to the rights bearer, what justifications the government is relying on, and what alternatives are available to it. Under proportionality analysis, it becomes possible to treat the positive and negative dimensions of rights in just the same way, because the relevant question is not whether the right is a right but rather what the government is obligated to do, or refrain from doing, in virtue of the burdens it is placing on citizens. The answer to that question is neither “nothing” nor “everything.” It is, in every case, “it depends.”

The landmark Canadian case of Eldridge v. British Columbia (Attorney General) provides a striking example.Footnote 55 A nonprofit that had been providing sign-language interpretation for hearing-impaired patients in British Columbia hospitals at no cost to the province ceased operation and the province refused to pay for the service to continue. The Supreme Court of Canada held that the province was liable, not because disability rights are especially absolute or subject to some kind of “strict scrutiny” but rather because the ability to communicate with one’s healthcare provider is vitally important in a hospital setting and the cost to the province to provide interpretation services was trivial.Footnote 56

The province attempted to defend its actions using US-style slippery-slope arguments to the effect that a holding in favor of the patients in this case meant that the hospital would need to fund a host of language translation services, but Justice La Forest made short work of the claim, calling it “purely speculative” and noting the many relevant differences between people who cannot speak English or French and those who are hearing-impaired.Footnote 57 Justice La Forest noted those differences not to say that a different translation case would not arise or would necessarily come out differently but to say that such a claim and its outcome “cannot be predicted in advance.”Footnote 58 A reluctance to decide hypothetical cases in advance of their concrete facts is a common feature of proportionality, which engages intimately with those facts to reach outcomes.

12.4.2 Polycentric Constitutionalism

Rights protection is not solely the province of courts. Indeed, the usual way in which communities protect the rights of their members is by making and enforcing laws in pursuit of public health, safety, and welfare. Whether by providing health care, health insurance, or various forms of assisted living, by promulgating pension or retirement rules, or by crafting other state-provided social insurance programs, legal accommodation of old age should occur primarily through legislation rather than court decisions. It is telling that accommodation and protection for people with disabilities, the closest analogue to a right to grow old, occurs primarily through the Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA),Footnote 59 the Rehabilitation Act,Footnote 60 the Individuals with Disabilities Education Act (IDEA),Footnote 61 and state and local law. What protections federal law offers against age discrimination also occur primarily via statutes: the Age Discrimination in Employment Act (ADEA)Footnote 62 and the Age Discrimination Act.Footnote 63 Both the negative and – especially – the positive dimensions of the rights these laws advance reflect a constitutional vision enacted through laws, not just litigation.

And yet, these laws need a firmer constitutional foundation. According to the Supreme Court, Congress’s power to pass both the ADA and the ADEA stems entirely from its power to regulate interstate commerce rather than from its power to enforce the equality and rights guarantees of the Fourteenth Amendment.Footnote 64 The reason for this limitation is that the Court reviews disability and age discrimination under rational-basis review rather than heightened scrutiny. This means that states that discriminate rationally against older people or people with disabilities have not violated the Constitution, which in turn means that Congress cannot premise legislation-holding states to higher standards on its Fourteenth Amendment enforcement power.

Being forced to defend rights-protective statutes as an exercise of the Commerce Clause has significant costs. In the ADA and ADEA contexts, it means that individuals aggrieved under these laws cannot bring damages actions against states.Footnote 65 And a chillier wind blows. The Court has declared that the Commerce Clause cannot be used to require Americans to engage in activities, which threaten accommodation requirements.Footnote 66

A right to grow old need not necessarily rely on a heightened scrutiny for individual acts of age discrimination. It could be enough for the Court to recognize the power of Congress to legislate in rights-protective ways even for rights that the Court does not view in the same terms.

12.4.3 Minimum Core

International human rights law has grappled with the problem of giving justiciable or administrable content to the positive dimensions of rights. The United Nations Committee on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights has interpreted the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) to protect a “minimum core” of the rights that instrument recognizes, whether to food, health, education, or water.Footnote 67 The idea of minimum core obligations counters the concern that positive rights may induce legal decision-makers to try to maximize the provision of services beyond state capacity or the allocative competence of adjudicators by, instead, defining the government’s obligations in minimalist terms.

The minimum core idea has held an appeal in international human rights law insofar as it enables the Committee to articulate obligations that must be fully and immediately realized regardless of a country’s level of development. Thus, the Committee has offered in its General Comment on the right to health that its minimum core includes the right of nondiscriminatory access to health facilities, goods, and services; basic access to nutritionally adequate and safe food; access to basic shelter, housing, sanitation, and potable water; the provision of “essential drugs;” equitable distribution of health facilities; and adoption and implementation of a national health strategy.Footnote 68 Many countries, of course, fall below this minimum core for many of their citizens, but the conceit is that it is nonetheless coherent to label this failure a human rights violation. To apply the same label, for example, to a poor country’s failure to provide access to higher standards of care would make the human rights regime (even more) vulnerable to charges of ineffectual idealism.

The minimum core concept has had relatively little traction in national constitutions – it was conspicuously rejected in an early South African Constitutional Court decisionFootnote 69 – but it is portable between international and domestic law.Footnote 70 In the Rodriguez case, for example, a minimum core idea would have permitted the court to hold that some but not all discrepancies between rich and poor neighborhood schools were constitutionally tolerable. Perhaps a court could order schools to equalize costs of books and teacher salaries but not necessarily the number of field trips or the food options in the cafeteria. Inequity and injustice would of course remain, but the point of the minimum core in a domestic context is that courts can play a role in mitigating injustice even where institutional constraints prevent them from eradicating it.

In applying this idea to the right to grow old, a court could potentially require, for example, that health insurance for older Americans cover, at least in part, the costs of long-term assisted living, or that the government require, by law, that employers offer employment guarantees for employees who must devote some time to caring for elderly relatives on a long-term basis. At a minimum, a right to grow old could simply mean that the government receives some deference from courts in the choices it makes in structuring programs of this sort.

12.4.4 Progressive Realization

The ICESCR obligates states to aim for “progressive realization” of the rights it identifies,Footnote 71 in recognition of the fact that, as Katharine Young writes, “[i]n international human rights law, waiting is an accepted part of rights realization.”Footnote 72 A progressive realization norm generally assumes that “minimum core” is not an adequate global standard – it would, for example, give a pass to the wealthiest countries – but at the same time it concedes that states often lack the material, political, and institutional capacity to respect, protect, and fulfill rights fully and expeditiously. In addition to a variety of international human rights instruments, several domestic constitutions also include the language of progressive realization, and it has been much discussed in the South African constitutional context.Footnote 73

Admittedly “progressive realization” might be a tough sell in the US. It sounds uncomfortably close to “with all deliberate speed,” the much-maligned standard the Warren Court deployed in its too-deliberate implementation of Brown v. Board of Education.Footnote 74 The discomfort is well founded. Permitting a state to delay its implementation of constitutional rights allows it to smuggle political goals – up to and including outright resistance to the right – into claims of administrative necessity.

Still, the failure of the remedy ordered in Brown to overcome massive resistance to the implementation of that decision does not mean that progressive realization is never appropriate. That position overstates the capacity of judges to disrupt entrenched racial politics, and, in doing so, it denies courts a tool that may be necessary to the availability of positive rights. Judges don’t like to order relief that will reliably be ignored or slow-walked. Without something like a commitment (concession?) to progressive realization, US courts are unlikely to find their way to positive rights.

A right to grow old could benefit from progressive realization through state duties to protect or promote the positive aspects of the right being stated in general terms: for example, a requirement that long-term care be facilitated without specifying exactly how much or through what channels, but by setting benchmarks for evaluation along the experimentalist model identified and championed by scholars such as Charles Sabel and William Simon.Footnote 75 Litigants could return to courts at a later date if progress is not forthcoming.

12.4.5 Remedial Flexibility

A final piece to the puzzle of respecting, protecting, and fulfilling a right to grow old comes, appropriately, at the end: flexible remedies. In part, the need for flexible remedies is but a restatement of the need for progressive realization. But there is a more specific point that bears mention. US courts tend to view dialogic approaches to remedies as exotic, even threatening to their credibility. Many constitutional courts around the world, including in Canada, Germany, Ireland, Israel, and South Africa, resort routinely to a remedial technique sometimes referred to as a “suspension of invalidity.” This is a technique whereby a court issues a ruling on constitutionality but suspends the order for a set period of time to allow the state to structure the remedy as it sees fit. Thus, for example, in a South African case holding that a statute governing the procedure for criminal appeals was unconstitutional, the South African Constitutional Court suspended the validity of its judgment for more than a year to allow Parliament to develop new procedures for the processing of appeals.Footnote 76

This technique is not entirely foreign to US courts. Brown II had something of this structure, as noted. Less high-profile but more to the point, in Northern Pipeline Construction Co. v. Marathon Pipe Line Co., the Supreme Court held that bankruptcy courts had been given too much power, but it delayed its judgment by four months to give Congress time “to reconstitute the bankruptcy courts or to adopt other valid means of adjudication.”Footnote 77 The suspension of invalidity device demonstrates that progressive realization need not involve endless dialogue but is amenable to the adoption of quite specific and coercive benchmarks.

12.5 Conclusion

The right to grow old is a tall order in the US, but it is not an impossible one. The inevitability of aging means that such a right likely faces fewer obstacles than other rights that have significant positive dimensions. It does not require the invention of new substantive rights – indeed, it is already constitutionally protected. It does, however, require a recognition of governmental duties of protection and fulfillment of rights that are not typical (though they do exist) in US constitutional law. The anxiety US courts face about such duties could be soothed by incorporating elements of proportionality analysis, by giving deference to political bodies acting to protect the rights of older Americans, and by availing themselves of some of the tools of incremental or partial rights realization that have become familiar within international human rights law.

Footnotes

6 The New Old Civil Rights

1 Lynda Gratton & Andrew J. Scott, The 100-Year Life: Living and Working in the Age of Longevity 2 (2016).

2 Ashton Applewhite, This Chair Rocks: A Manifesto against Ageism 22 (2016) (quoting unnamed journalist at 2012 Age Boom seminar).

3 29 U.S.C. §§ 621–634.

4 General Dynamics Land Systems, Inc. v. Cline, 540 U.S. 581, 586–587 (2004) (“Congress chose not to include age within discrimination forbidden by Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, being aware that there were legitimate reasons as well as invidious ones for making employment decisions on age.”).

5 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a)(1) (deeming it unlawful for a covered employer “to fail or refuse to hire or to discharge any individual … with respect to his compensation, terms, conditions, or privileges of employment, because of such individual’s race, color, religion, sex, or national origin”).

6 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-14.

7 W. Willard Wirtz, Report of Sec’y of Labor: The Older American Worker – Age Discrimination in Employment (June 30, 1965) [hereinafter “Wirtz Report”].

8 See, e.g., Smith v. City of Jackson, 544 U.S. 228, 232 (2005); Cline, 540 U.S., at 587, 590; Western Air Lines v. Criswell, 472 U.S. 400, 409 (1985).

9 Wirtz Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 4.

10 Footnote Id. at 4–5.

11 Footnote Id. at 5.

12 Footnote Id. (emphasis omitted).

13 Footnote Id. at 31.

15 Footnote Id. at 9.

16 Footnote Id. at 5.

17 472 U.S. 400 (1985).

18 Footnote Id. at 402–403.

19 29 U.S.C. § 623(f)(1).

20 Criswell, 472 U.S., at 403.

21 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(e)(1).

22 Footnote Id.; see also Malhotra v. Cotter & Co. 885 F.2d 1305, 1308 (7th Cir. 1989).

23 See, e.g., Dothard v. Rawlinson, 433 U.S. 321, 334 (1977) (“We are persuaded by the restrictive language of § 703(e), the relevant legislative history, and the consistent interpretation of the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission that the BFOQ exception was in fact meant to be an extremely narrow exception to the general prohibition on the basis of sex.”).

24 Footnote Id. at 419.

25 Footnote Id. at 412.

26 Footnote Id. at 419.

27 Footnote Id. at 423.

28 544 U.S. 228 (2005).

29 Griggs v. Duke Power Co., 401 U.S. 424 (1971).

30 Footnote Id. at 432–433.

31 City of Jackson, 544 U.S. at 230.

32 Footnote Id. at 231.

33 Footnote Id. at 232.

34 A four-justice plurality rested its conclusion in part on the ground that “Griggs, which interpreted the identical text at issue here, thus strongly suggests that a disparate-impact theory should be cognizable under the ADEA.” Footnote Id. at 236. Justice Scalia, writing separately, observed that while he agreed with the Court’s reasoning, he did not find it dispositive. Footnote Id. at 243. Instead, he found the textual similarity to be a basis to defer to the reasonable view of the EEOC, which he found supported the viability of a disparate impact claim.

35 Footnote Id. at 254 (O’Connor, J., concurring). As discussed later, the majority in City of Jackson found that while the plaintiffs could assert a disparate impact claim, they had failed to prove one in this case. Footnote Id. at 243. For this reason, Justice O’Connor’s opinion was a concurrence rather than a dissent.

36 Footnote Id. at 255 (O’Connor, J., concurring) (quoting Wirtz Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 5).

37 Footnote Id. at 240.

38 29 U.S.C. § 623(a)(2).

39 City of Jackson, 544 U.S., at 233.

40 Footnote Id. at 243.

41 Footnote Id. at 242.

42 Footnote Id. at 243.

43 Footnote Id. at 240–241.

44 Footnote Id. at 240.

45 557 U.S. 167 (2009).

46 Footnote Id. at 180.

49 Footnote Id. at 174.

50 Footnote Id. at 180.

51 Footnote Id. at 186–187.

52 U.S. Const. Amend. XIV, section 1.

53 Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.S. 184 (1964).

54 Oyama v. California, 332 U.S. 633 (1948).

55 Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.S. 365 (1971). The heightened scrutiny accorded to alienage has been watered down in ways not relevant for these purposes.

56 Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976).

57 Trimble v. Gordon, 430 U.S. 762 (1977).

58 Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620 (1996); Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, 473 U.S. 432 (1985); Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972). See Katie R. Eyer, The Canon of Rational Basis Review, 93 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1317, 1319 (2018) (“For example, the modern canon also acknowledges that so-called ‘animus’ doctrine, or ‘rational basis with bite,’ can involve a deviation from this exceptionally deferential version of rational basis review.”) (internal citations omitted).

59 United States Railroad Retirement Board v. Fritz, 449 U.S. 166 (1980); Williamson v. Lee Optical, 348 U.S. 483 (1955). See Eyer, supra Footnote note 58, at 1318–1319 (“Rational basis review is a form of review that is ‘almost empty,’ ‘enormously deferential,’ and ‘meaningless.’”) (internal citations omitted).

60 Susannah W. Pollvogt, Beyond Suspect Classifications, 16 u. pa. j. const. l. 739, 744 (2014) (“The term ‘heightened scrutiny’ refers to both strict scrutiny and intermediate scrutiny, with strict scrutiny being the more demanding of the two standards … Minor semantic distinctions aside, the two forms of heightened scrutiny are more alike than different in that a plaintiff’s chances of prevailing are much greater under either of these forms of heightened review, as compared to deferential rational basis review.”) (internal citations omitted).

61 Susannah W. Pollvogt, Unconstitutional Animus, 81 Fordham L. Rev. 887, 889 (2012) (“Under rational basis review, the plaintiff almost invariably loses.”).

62 United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152–153 Footnote n.4 (1938).

63 427 U.S. 307 (1976).

64 Footnote Id. at 312.

65 Footnote Id. at 313.

67 Footnote Id. (quoting Carolene Products, 304 U.S. at 152–153 n.4).

68 Footnote Id. at 313–314.

69 440 U.S. 93 (1979).

70 Footnote Id. at 111–112.

71 501 U.S. 452 (1991).

72 Footnote Id. at 472.

73 Wirtz Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 5.

74 Janet E. Halley, Like Race, in What’s Left of Theory, 40–74 (Judith Butler, Tom Guillory & Kendall Thomas eds., 2000).

75 Footnote Id. at 40.

76 Footnote Id. at 46.

77 Footnote Id. at 52 (noting the rise of the argument that sexual orientation, like race, is a biologically immutable characteristic).

78 Footnote Id. (noting the strategic uses of the analogy between sexual orientation and race, even assuming the analogy is not entirely accurate).

79 Victoria A. Lipnic, The State of Age Discrimination and Older Workers in the U.S. 50 Years after the Age Discrimination in Employment Act (ADEA), US Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (June 2018).

80 Footnote Id. at 13.

82 Footnote Id. at 13 (quoting Waters v. Logistics Management Institute, 2018 U.S. App. Lexis 3122, *11 (4th Cir. 2018), audio of oral argument at http://coop.ca4.uscourts.gov/OAarchive/mp3/16-2353-20180123.mp3).

83 Footnote Id. at 45.

84 Footnote Id. at 14.

86 Wirtz Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 5.

87 Footnote Id. (noting that justifiable discrimination “clearly does exist so far as the age question, but does not exist so far as, for example, racial or religious discrimination are concerned”).

88 While the gender-based real difference doctrine comes up most explicitly in the context of constitutional equal protection doctrine, it has cognates in Title VII as well. The cognized forms of the BFOQ defense, for instance, often turn on “real differences” between the sexes. Arthur Larson & Lex K. Larson, Employment Discrimination (2d ed. 2005), § 43.02, at 43–44 (“The clearest [BFOQ case] is that in which a physical feature unique to one sex is essential to the performance of the job” such as a “wet nurse”), cited in Russell K. Robinson, Casting and Caste-ing: Reconciling Artistic Freedom and Antidiscrimination Norms, 95 Cal. L. Rev. 1, 34 n.164 (2007). Moreover, the absence of a BFOQ defense for race suggests that Congress was unwilling to deem any difference “real” in that domain.

89 533 U.S. 53 (2001).

90 Footnote Id. at 73.

91 Footnote Id. at 65.

92 Footnote Id. at 73.

93 See, e.g., Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452 (1991); Vance v. Bradley, 440 U.S. 93 (1979); Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307 (1976).

94 Vance v. Bradley, 440 U.S. 93, 121 (Marshall, J., dissenting).

95 Halley, supra Footnote note 74, at 52.

96 540 U.S. 581 (2004).

97 Footnote Id. at 584.

98 See Kenji Yoshino, Assimilationist Bias in Equal Protection: The Visibility Presumption and the Case of “Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell,” 108 Yale L.J. 487 (1998) (“A classification-based view of equal protection seeks to treat all classes created by a classification the same, while a class-based view privileges the disadvantaged class(es) created by a classification. [A classification-view] tends to ignore differences between the classes created by a classification.”).

99 See, e.g., Reva B . Siegel, Why Equal Protection No Longer Protects: The Evolving Forms of Status-Enforcing State Action, 49 Stan. L. Rev. 1111, 1142 (1997) (describing essay’s standpoint, “which does not equate discrimination with ‘classification,’ but begins instead from the premise that status-enforcing state action is mutable in form”).

100 As the Cline dissent pointed out, the Court has adopted the anticlassification view for Title VII classifications. See Cline, 540 U.S., at 611 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (noting that the Court has interpreted Title VII to protect whites as well as racial minorities).

101 Footnote Id. at 596.

102 Footnote Id. at 597.

103 Footnote Id. at 598.

104 517 U.S. 308 (1996).

105 Footnote Id. at 309–310.

106 Footnote Id. at 310.

108 Footnote Id. at 312 (emphasis in original).

109 Ernest Becker, The Denial of Death (1973).

110 Footnote Id. at 69.

111 Footnote Id. at 15.

112 Eva Jonas & Peter Fischer, Terror Management and Religion: Evidence that Intrinsic Religiousness Mitigates Worldview Defense Following Mortality Salience, 91 J. of Personality & Soc. Psychol. 553 (2006).

113 Brandon J. Schmeichel et al., Terror Management Theory and Self-Esteem Revisited, 96 J. of Personality & Soc. Psychol. 1077 (2009).

114 Jeff Greenberg, Sheldon Solomon & Tom Pyszczynski, The Worm at the Core: On the Role of Death in Life (2015).

115 Footnote Id. at 12.

118 Andy Martens, Jamie Goldenberg & Jeff Greenberg, A Terror Management Perspective on Ageism, 61 J. of Social Issues 223 (2005).

119 Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307 (1976).

120 Vance v. Bradley, 440 U.S. 93, 113–114 n.1 (1979) (Marshall, J., dissenting).

121 Footnote Id. at 114 n.1.

122 Martens et al., supra Footnote note 118, at 223.

124 Footnote Id. at 223–224.

125 Becca R. Levy & Mahzarin R. Banaji, Implicit Ageism, in Ageism: Stereotyping and Prejudice against Older Persons (T. D. Nelson ed., 2002).

126 Footnote Id. at 50.

127 Wirtz Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 8.

128 Levy & Banaji, supra Footnote note 125, at 50.

129 Footnote Id. at 55.

130 Wirtz Report, supra Footnote note 7, at 5 (noting that this “type of discrimination … should perhaps be called something else entirely”).

131 Martha C. Nussbaum & Saul Levmore, Aging Thoughtfully: Conversations about Retirement, Romance, Wrinkles, & Regret (2017).

132 Footnote Id. at 114.

134 Footnote Id. at 110.

135 Footnote Id. at 111.

136 Murgia, 427 U.S., at 307.

137 Kenji Yoshino, The New Equal Protection, 124 Harv. L. Rev. 747, 757 (2011) (noting that “the last classification accorded heightened scrutiny by the Supreme Court was that based on nonmarital parentage in 1977”).

138 United States v. Windsor, 570 U.S. 744 (2013); Romer, 517 U.S., at 620.

139 Cleburne, 473 U.S., at 432.

140 Eisenstadt, 405 U.S., at 438.

141 See, e.g., Patricia G. Barnes, Betrayed: The Legalization of Age Discrimination in the Workplace 220–221 (2014) (“Congress must do what it should have done in 1964 – make age a protected class under Title VII.”).

142 Footnote Id. at 221.

143 The dissenters in Nguyen v. Immigration and Naturalization Services, 533 U.S. 53 (2001) criticized the majority for confusing biology and bigotry. Justice O’Connor observed that “the idea that a mother’s presence at birth supplies adequate assurance of an opportunity to develop a relationship while a father’s presence at birth does not would appear to rest only on an overbroad sex-based generalization.” Footnote Id. at 86 (O’Connor, J., dissenting).

144 Gross v. FBL Financial Services, 557 U.S. 167 (2009).

145 Gratton & Scott, supra Footnote note 1, at 328.

147 Footnote Id. (citing Gordon Allport, The Nature of Prejudice (1954)).

148 See, e.g., Allport, supra Footnote note 147, at 281 (“Prejudice (unless deeply rooted in the character structure of the individual) may be reduced by equal status contact between majority and minority groups in pursuit of common goals.”).

149 Footnote Id. at 257–258 (citing Hal E. Hirshfield et al., Increasing Saving Behavior through Age-Progressed Renderings of the Future Self, 48 J. of Marketing Research 23 (2019)).

150 Hirshfield et al., supra Footnote note 149.

151 Jill M. Chonody & Barbara Teater, Why Do I Dread Looking Old? A Test of Social Identity Theory, Terror Management Theory, and the Double Standard of Ageing, 28 J. of Women & Ageing 112 (2016) (noting that while the findings are complex, there are transnational differences with regard to ageism and death panic).

7 Age, Inequality, and Political Representation

1 Thomas Piketty, Capital in the Twenty-First Century (Arthur Goldhammer trans., Belknap Press of Harvard University Press 2014) (2013).

2 Throughout this chapter, I do not take on the question of future generations, only differences in generations and age of those currently alive. The former topic is one that is much discussed in law and philosophy. See, e.g., John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 284–293 (1971) (Chapter: “The Problem of Justice between Generations”); Bruce Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State 101–227 (1980) (Chapter: “Justice over Time”); Richard A. Epstein, Justice across the Generations, 67 Tex. L. Rev. 1465 (1989). There are also some proposals for how to design political systems to represent the interests of future generations. See, e.g., Matthew W. Wolfe, The Shadows of Future Generations, 57 Duke L.J. 1897, 1914–1918 (2008) (describing proposals).

3 Lynda Gratton & Andrew Scott, The 100-Year Life (2016).

4 Lauren Medina et al., Living Longer: Historical and Projected Life Expectancy in the United States, 1960 to 2060 (2020), 1, US Dep’t of Com., US Census Bureau, https://www.census.gov/content/dam/Census/library/publications/2020/demo/p25-1145.pdf.

5 Footnote Id. at 7; Elizabeth Arias & Jiaquan Xu, United States Life Tables, 2017, 68 Nat’l Vital Stat. Reps. 3 (June 24, 2019), https://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/nvsr/nvsr68/nvsr68_07-508.pdf.

6 Cong. Rsch. Serv., R44846, The Growing Gap in Life Expectancy by Income: Recent Evidence and Implications for the Social Security Retirement Age (2021), 1, https://fas.org/sgp/crs/misc/R44846.pdf; Sabrina Tavernise, Disparity in Life Spans of the Rich and the Poor Is Growing, N.Y. Times (Feb. 12, 2016), https://www.nytimes.com/2016/02/13/health/disparity-in-life-spans-of-the-rich-and-the-poor-is-growing.html.

7 Raj Chetty et al., The Association between Income and Life Expectancy in the United States, 2001–2014, 315 J. Am. Med. Ass’n 1750 (2016), https://jamanetwork.com/journals/jama/article-abstract/2513561; Neil Irwin & Quoctrung Bui, The Rich Live Longer Everywhere. For the Poor, Geography Matters, N.Y. Times (Apr. 11, 2016), https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2016/04/11/upshot/for-the-poor-geography-is-life-and-death.html.

8 Org. for Econ. Coop. & Dev., Life Expectancy by Sex and Education Level (Nov. 10, 2017), https://www.oecd-ilibrary.org/sites/health_glance-2017-7-en/index.html?itemId=/content/component/health_glance-2017-7-en.

9 Anne Case & Angus Deaton, Deaths of Despair and the Future of Capitalism (2020); Isaac Sasson & Mark D. Hayward, Association between Educational Attainment and Causes of Death among White and Black US Adults, 2010–2017, 322 J. Am. Med. Ass’n 756 (2019), https://jamanetwork.com/journals/jama/fullarticle/2748794.

10 Yana C. Vierboom & Samuel H. Preston, Life beyond 65: Changing Spatial Patterns of Survival at Older Ages in the United States, 2000–2016, 75 J. Gerontology: Soc. Sci. 1093 (2020), https://academic.oup.com/psychsocgerontology/article/75/5/1093/5717464.

11 Yana C. Vierboom et al., Rising Geographic Inequality in Mortality in the United States, 9 SSM–Population Health 1 (2019), https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6804490/pdf/main.pdf.

12 Anne Case & Angus Deaton, Rising Morbidity and Mortality among White Non-Hispanic Americans in the 21st Century, 112 PNAS 15078 (2015), https://www.pnas.org/content/112/49/15078.

13 Vierboom et al., supra Footnote note 11, at 7; Vierboom & Preston, supra Footnote note 10.

14 Irwin & Bui, supra Footnote note 7.

15 Angela M. O’Rand & John C. Henretta, Age and Inequality: Diverse Pathways through Later Life 31 (1999).

16 Kriston McIntosh et al., Examining the Black–White Wealth Gap, Brookings Inst. (Feb. 27, 2020), fig. 2, https://www.brookings.edu/blog/up-front/2020/02/27/examining-the-black-white-wealth-gap/.

17 Urban Inst., Nine Charts about Wealth Inequality in America, https://apps.urban.org/features/wealth-inequality-charts (updated Oct. 5, 2017).

19 O’Rand & Henretta, supra Footnote note 15, at 16.

20 Patricia Buckley & Akrur Barua, Are We Headed for a Poorer United States? Growing Wealth Inequality by Age Puts Younger Households Behind, Deloitte Insights (Mar. 12, 2018), https://www2.deloitte.com/us/en/insights/economy/issues-by-the-numbers/march-2018/us-average-wealth-inequality-by-age.html.

22 Pew Rsch. Ctr., The Rising Age Gap in Economic Well-Being (Nov. 7, 2011), 1, https://www.pewresearch.org/wp-content/uploads/sites/3/2011/11/WealthReportFINAL.pdf.

24 The Federalist No. 10, at 77–78 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961).

25 Book Note, The Relevance and Irrelevance of the Founders, 120 Harv. L. Rev. 619, 624–625 (2006).

26 Ganesh Sitaraman, The Crisis of the Middle-Class Constitution 21–111 (2018).

27 Daryl J. Levinson & Richard H. Pildes, Separation of Parties, Not Powers, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 2312 (2006).

28 Ganesh Sitaraman, The Puzzling Absence of Economic Power in Constitutional Theory, 101 Cornell L. Rev. 1445 (2016); Kate Andrias, Separations of Wealth: Inequality and the Erosion of Checks and Balances, 18 U. Pa. J. Con. L. 419 (2015).

29 Interparliamentary Union, Youth Participation in National Parliaments (2021), 7, 9.

31 Kay L. Schlozman et al., The Unheavenly Chorus 216–218 (2012).

32 Footnote Id. at 200, 230.

33 Christopher H. Achen & Larry M. Bartels, Democracy for Realists (2016).

34 Nicholas Carnes, White-Collar Government: The Hidden Role of Class in Economic Policy Making (2013).

35 Schlozman et al., supra Footnote note 31.

36 See, e.g., Larry M. Bartels, Unequal Democracy (2d ed. 2016); Martin Gilens & Benjamin I. Page, Testing Theories of American Politics: Elites, Interest Groups, and Average Citizens, 12 Persps. on Pol. 564 (2014).

37 Gilens & Page, supra Footnote note 36.

38 Pew Rsch. Ctr., The Generation Gap in American Politics (Mar. 1, 2018), 30, https://www.pewresearch.org/politics/wp-content/uploads/sites/4/2018/03/03-01-18-Generations-release2.pdf.

39 Footnote Id. at 26–27.

41 Footnote Id. at 28.

42 Footnote Id. at 19–20.

43 Footnote Id. at 13–14.

44 Footnote Id. at 15.

45 Juliana Bidadanure, Six Reasons Why the UK Parliament Should Have Youth Quotas, openDemocracy (June 15, 2015), https://www.opendemocracy.net/en/opendemocracyuk/six-reasons-why-uk-parliament-should-have-youth-quotas/.

46 Paul E. Peterson, An Immodest Proposal, 121 Daedalus 151, 161–165 (Fall 1992).

48 Lionel Beehner, The Effects of “Youth Bulge” on Civil Conflicts, Council on Foreign Rels. (Apr. 13, 2007), https://www.cfr.org/backgrounder/effects-youth-bulge-civil-conflicts.

49 See Albert O. Hirschman, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty (1972).

50 Cf. Sitaraman, supra Footnote note 26, at 21–55 (describing fears that inequality could lead to revolution); see also Daniel Ziblatt, Conservative Parties and the Birth of Democracy (2017) (arguing that conservatives enabled reform in part due to fears of revolution).

51 John Adams, Thoughts on Government (1776), Nat’l Const. Ctr., https://constitutioncenter.org/the-constitution/historic-document-library/detail/john-adams-thoughts-on-government-1776 (accessed May 25, 2023).

52 For a discussion of this and other theories of representation, see generally Hanna Pitkin, The Concept of Representation (1967).

53 Clair C. Miller, Women Actually Do Govern Differently, N.Y. Times (Nov. 10, 2016), https://www.nytimes.com/2016/11/10/upshot/women-actually-do-govern-differently.html; Robert R. Preuhs & Rodney E. Hero, A Different Kind of Representation: Black and Latino Descriptive Representation and the Role of Ideological Cuing, Pol. Rsch. Q. 157 (2011); Carnes, supra Footnote note 34.

54 I exclude technocratic policy options, such as setting the discount rate within cost–benefit analysis, to value the interests of future generations more highly. This topic not only has been discussed extensively in the literature but also has a more limited scope than the structural questions of political representation I consider here. For a discussion, see David A. Weisbach & Cass R. Sunstein, Introduction to Symposium on Intergenerational Equity and Discounting, 74 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1 (2007); Cass R. Sunstein & Arden Rowell, On Discounting Regulatory Benefits: Risk, Money, and Intergenerational Equity, 74 U. Chi. L. Rev. 171 (2007).

55 Peterson, supra Footnote note 46, at 170.

56 Daniel Stockemer & Aksel Sundstrom, Age Representation in Parliaments: Can Institutions Pave the Way for the Young? 10 Eur. Pol. Sci. Rev. 467, 486 (2018).

57 See, e.g., Nelson W. Polsby, Some Arguments against Congressional Term Limitations, 16 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol’y 101, 105 (1993) (observing that experience leads to policy knowledge and that term limits would reduce knowledge of members of Congress, thereby indirectly empowering lobbyists and others in the political system with more knowledge).

59 See, e.g., Robert G. Kaiser, Act of Congress (2014) (describing the expertise of Barney Frank after decades in Congress, passing the Dodd-Frank Act after the 2008 financial crisis).

60 Stephen Calebresi & James Lindgren, Term Limits for the Supreme Court: Life Tenure Reconsidered, 29 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 769 (2006); Stephen Calebresi & James Lindgren, Supreme Gerontocracy, Wall St. J. (Apr. 8, 2005), https://www.wsj.com/articles/SB111292087188301557.

61 Kermit Roosevelt III & Ruth-Helen Vassilas, Coming to Terms with Term Limits: Fixing the Downward Spiral of Supreme Court Appointments, Am. Const. Soc’y (June 2017), https://www.acslaw.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/06/Coming_to_Terms.pdf; Rosalind Dixon, Why the Supreme Court Needs (Short) Term Limits, N.Y. Times (Dec. 31, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2021/12/31/opinion/supreme-court-term-limits.html.

62 Moiz Syed, Charting the Long-Term Impact of Trump’s Judicial Appointments, ProPublica (Oct. 30, 2020), https://projects.propublica.org/trump-young-judges/.

63 Jana Belschner, The Adoption of Youth Quotas after the Arab Uprisings, 9 Pol., Grps., & Identities 151, 153 (2018).

65 Stockemer & Sundstrom, supra Footnote note 56.

66 Footnote Id. at 468.

67 Footnote Id. at 473.

69 Footnote Id. at 473–474.

8 Age-Based Classifications in an Age of Centenarians

1 U.N. Dep’t of Econ. & Soc. Aff., World Population Aging: Highlights (2017), 8, https://www.un.org/en/development/desa/population/publications/pdf/ageing/WPA2017_Highlights.pdf.

2 Footnote Id.; Jean-Marie Robine & Sarah Cubaynes, Worldwide Demography of Centenarians, 165 Mechanisms Ageing & Dev. 59 (2017).

3 See Dan B. Dobbs et al., The Law of Torts, §§ 134–137 (2d ed. 2019) (discussing the standard of care for minors in US tort law); Am. L. Inst., Model Penal Code § 4.10 (2018) (describing a general policy against convicting persons who were under the age of sixteen at the time an offense was committed).

4 See, e.g., Fla. Stat. Ann. § 322.18(5) (2021).

5 29 U.S.C. § 631(a) (2021).

6 Nina A. Kohn, Outliving Civil Rights, 86 Wash. U. L. Rev. 1053 (2009).

7 R.I. Gen. Laws § 42-66-8 (2021).

8 See, e.g., Mo. Rev. Stat. §§ 192.2400, 192.2405 (2000).

9 See Nina A. Kohn, Elder (In)Justice: A Critique of the Criminalization of Elder Abuse, 49 Amer. Crim. L. Rev. 1, 8–13 (2012).

10 See Wash. Rev. Code § 9A.44.100(1)(f), § 9A.44.010(16) (2020) (criminalizing sexual conduct with a “frail elder or vulnerable adult” defined as “a person sixty years of age or older who has the functional, mental, or physical inability to care for himself or herself”); Wash. Rev. Code § 9A.44.100 (2020) (making it a felony for a paid transportation provider to knowingly cause a disabled person age sixty or older, other than his or her spouse, “to have sexual contact with him or her or another” even if the contact is consensual).

11 See, e.g., 720 Ill. Comp. Stat. Ann. 5/17-56(a), (c) (2020).

12 33 Maine Rev. Stat. Ann. § 1021 et seq. (2020).

13 Anne L. Alstott, New Deal for Old Age: Toward a Progressive Retirement (2017); Anne L. Alstott, A New Deal for Old Age, 97 B.U. L. Rev. 1933 (2017).

14 See Kaiser Family Found., Raising the Age of Medicare Eligibility (2013), https://www.kff.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/01/8169.pdf.

15 B. L. Plassman et al., Prevalence of Dementia in the United States: The Aging, Demographics, and Memory Study, 29 Neuroepidemiology 128 (2007), http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2705925/.

16 Suddenly Senior, Turning 65 Years Old: Scream about It (Mar. 26, 2018), https://www.suddenlysenior.com/turn-65-and-scream-about-getting-old/.

17 Tze Pin Ng et al., Socio-environmental, Lifestyle, Behavioural, and Psychological Determinants of Biological Ageing: The Singapore Longitudinal Ageing Study, 66 Gerontology 603 (2020).

18 See Age or Need? Public Policies for Older People (Bernice Neugarten ed., 1982) (discussing the modern debate over age-based classification – considered the seminal book on the topic).

19 Quoc Dinh Nguyen, Health Heterogeneity in Older Adults: Exploration in the Canadian Longitudinal Study on Aging, 69 J. Amer. Geriatric Soc. 678 (2021).

22 David J. Lowsky et al., Heterogeneity in Healthy Aging, 69 J. Gerontology Series A. Bio. Sci. & Med. Sci. 607 (2014).

23 Ctrs. for Disease Control, Vital Statistics Rapid Release, Provisional Life Expectancy Estimate for January through June 2020 (2021), https://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/nvsr/nvsr69/nvsr69-12-508.pdf.

24 Ctrs. for Disease Control, National Vital Statistics Reports, United States Life Tables, 2018 (2020), https://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/nvsr/nvsr69/nvsr69-12-508.pdf.

25 Jennifer Karas Montez et al., Education Disparities in Adult Mortality across U.S. States: How Do They Differ, and Have They Changed since the Mid-1980s? 56 Demography 621 (2019).

26 For further discussion of this phenomenon, see Kohn, supra Footnote note 6 and Kohn, supra Footnote note 9.

27 Karl Pillemer, David Burnes & Andie MacNeil, Investigating the Connection between Ageism and Elder Mistreatment, Nature Aging 159 (2021).

28 See Erdman B. Palmore, Ageism: Negative & Positive 138 (1999).

29 Martha A. Fineman, The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition, 20 Yale J.L. & Feminism 1, 9–15 (2008) (originating the theory).

30 See, e.g., Alexander A. Boni-Saenz, Age, Equality, & Vulnerability, 21 Theoretical Inquiries L. 161 (2019).

31 Titti Mattsson & Lottie Giertz, Vulnerability, Law, and Dementia: An Interdisciplinary Discussion of Legislation and Practice, 21 Theoretical Inquiries L. 139 (2020).

32 Nina A. Kohn, Vulnerability Theory and the Role of Government, 26 Yale J.L. & Feminism 1 (2014).

9 Working to Death Labor Law and Collective Voice in the 100-Year Life

1 See Kate Andrias & Alexander Hertel-Fernandez, Ending At-Will Employment: A Guide for Just Cause Reform, Roosevelt Institute (Jan. 19, 2021), https://rooseveltinstitute.org/publications/ending-at-will-employment-a-guide-for-just-cause-reform/.

2 Josh Eidelson, COVID Gag Rules at U.S. Companies Are Putting Everyone at Risk, Bloomberg (Aug. 27, 2020), https://www.bloomberg.com/news/features/2020-08-27/covid-pandemic-u-s-businesses-issue-gag-rules-to-stop-workers-from-talking.

3 Center on Budget and Policy Priorities, Tracking the COVID-19 Economy’s Effects on Food, Housing, and Employment Hardships (2021), https://www.cbpp.org/research/poverty-and-inequality/tracking-the-covid-19-recessions-effects-on-food-housing-and.

4 Richard B. Freeman, Planning for the “Expected Unexpected:” Work and Retirement in the United States after the COVID-19 Pandemic Shock, in Overtime: America’s Aging Workforce and the Future of Working Longer 91, 100 (Lisa F. Berkman & Beth C. Truesdale eds., 2022); Richard Fry, Some Gender Disparities Widened in the U.S. Workforce during the Pandemic, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (Jan. 14, 2022), https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2022/01/14/some-gender-disparities-widened-in-the-u-s-workforce-during-the-pandemic/.

5 Christian Weller, A Hot Labor Market Is Not Enough for Racial Equality, Forbes (Sep. 12, 2022), https://www.forbes.com/sites/christianweller/2022/09/12/a-hot-labor-market-is-not-enough-for-racial-equality/.

6 Anne Alstott, Law and the Hundred-Year Life, 26 Elder L.J. 132, 142–144 (2018).

7 David Montgomery, Labor and the Political Leadership of New Deal America, 39 Int’l Rev. Soc. Hist. 335, 347–349 (1994).

8 Nelson Lichtenstein, From Corporatism to Collective Bargaining: Organized Labor and the Eclipse of Social Democracy in the Postwar Era, in The Rise and Fall of the New Deal Order, 1930–1980 122 (Steve Fraser & Gary Gerstle eds., 1989).

9 See, e.g., Kate Andrias, The New Labor Law, 126 Yale L.J. 2, 25–27 (2016).

10 Bureau of Labor and Statistics, Press Release: Union Members – 2024 (Jan. 28, 2025), https://www.bls.gov/news.release/pdf/union2.pdf.

11 Thomas Piketty, Capital in the Twenty-First Century 31 (2014).

12 See, e.g., Larry M. Bartels, Unequal Democracy: The Political Economy of the New Gilded Age 2, 285 (2008); Martin Gilens, Affluence and Influence: Economic Inequality and Political Power in America 73–85 (2012).

13 Annette Bernhardt et al., Broken Laws, Unprotected Workers: Violations of Employment and Labor Laws in America’s Cities, Nat’l Emp. L. Project (2009), https://s27147.pcdn.co/wp-content/uploads/2015/03/BrokenLawsReport2009.pdf.

14 See Epic Sys. Corp. v. Lewis, 138 S. Ct. 1612, 1621–1622 (2018); Samuel R. Bagenstos, Consent, Coercion, and Employment Law, 55 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 409, 414; Alexander J. S. Colvin, The Growing Use of Mandatory Arbitration, Econ. Pol’y Inst. (Sep. 27, 2017), https://www.epi.org/publication/the-growing-use-of-mandatory-arbitration/.

15 US Bureau of Lab. Stat., 67 Percent of Private Industry Workers Had Access to Retirement Plans in 2020 (Mar. 1, 2021), https://www.bls.gov/opub/ted/2021/67-percent-of-private-industry-workers-had-access-to-retirement-plans-in-2020.htm.

16 Eric Kingson & Monique Morrissey, Can Workers Offset Social Security Cuts by Working Longer? Econ. Pol’y Inst. (May 30, 2012), https://www.epi.org/publication/bp343-social-security-retirement-age/.

17 Katharine G. Abraham, Brad Hershbein & Susan N. Houseman, Contract Work at Older Ages, 20 J. Pension Econ. & Fin. 426, 432, 444–446 (2020).

18 Alicia H. Munnell, Geoffrey T. Sanzenbacher & Abigail N. Walters, How Do Older Workers Use Nontraditional Jobs? Center for Retirement Research: Boston College (Oct. 4, 2019), https://crr.bc.edu/working-papers/how-do-older-workers-use-nontraditional-jobs/.

19 Caroline Bruckner & Jonathan B. Forman, Women, Retirement and the Growing Gig Economy Workforce, 38 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 259, 265 (2022).

20 Jacob S. Hacker & Paul Pierson, The Biased Politics of “Working Longer,” in Overtime: America’s Aging Workforce, supra Footnote note 4, at 276, 280.

21 Steven Greenhouse, “We Deserve More:” An Amazon Warehouse’s High-Stakes Union Drive, Guardian (Feb. 23, 2021), https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2021/feb/23/amazon-bessemer-alabama-union.

22 Justin McCarthy, U.S. Approval of Labor Unions at Highest Point since 1965, Gallup (Aug. 30, 2022), https://news.gallup.com/poll/398303/approval-labor-unions-highest-point-1965.aspx. On obstacles to organizing see, e.g., Andrias, supra Footnote note 9, at 44; Paul Weiler, Striking a New Balance: Freedom of Contract and the Prospects for Union Representation, 98 Harv. L. Rev. 351, 362–363 (1984).

23 Protecting the Right to Organize Act of 2021, H.R. 842, 117th Cong. (2021).

24 See Clyde W. Summers, Worker Participation in the U.S. and West Germany: A Comparative Study from an American Perspective, 28 Am. J. Compar. L. 367, 385–388 (1980); Steven J. Silvia, Holding the Shop Together: German Industrial Relations in the Postwar Era 38–41 (2013).

25 Kathleen Thelen, Varieties of Liberalization and the New Politics of Social Solidarity 58 (2014).

26 Michael Oberfinchtner & Claus Schnabel, The German Model of Industrial Relations: (Where) Does It Still Exist? 239 J. Econ. & Stat. 5, 10, 21 (2019). (While workers at companies with five or more employees can form works councils, they are predominantly found at larger companies.).

27 Eur. Trade Union Inst., National Industrial Relations: Germany, http://www.worker-participation.eu/National-Industrial-Relations/Countries/Germany (accessed Mar. 12, 2021).

29 Thelen, supra Footnote note 25, at 65–67.

30 Toms Feifs et al., Role of Governments and Social Partners in Keeping Older Workers in the Labour Market, Eurofound (2013), https://www.eurofound.europa.eu/system/files/2021-05/EF13231EN.pdf.

31 Tore Langeland, Impact of the More Inclusive Working Life Agreement, Eurofound (Nov. 13, 2011), https://www.eurofound.europa.eu/publications/article/2011/impact-of-the-more-inclusive-working-life-agreement.

32 Bjorn Halvorsen & Asmund Lunde, Policy Measures to Support Older Workers in Norway, Norwegian Ministry of Labour and Social Affairs (2015), https://ec.europa.eu/social/BlobServlet?docId=14785&langId=en.

33 Todd E. Vachon et al., Union Decline in a Neoliberal Age: Globalization, Financialization, European Integration, and Union Density in 18 Affluent Democracies, 2 Socius (July 2016), at 1, 1314.

34 Eastex, Inc. v. Nat’l Lab. Rels. Bd., 437 U.S. 556, 564 (1978).

35 Kate Andrias & Brishen Rogers, Rebuilding Worker Voice in Today’s Economy, Roosevelt Inst. (2018), https://rooseveltinstitute.org/wp-content/uploads/2020/07/RI-Rebuilding-Worker-Voice-201808.pdf; Sharon Block & Benjamin Sachs, Clean Slate for Worker Power: Building a Just Economy and Democracy, https://clje.law.harvard.edu/clean-slate-for-worker-power-building-a-just-economy-and-democracy/ (accessed Oct. 1, 2023); Mark Barenberg, Widening the Scope of Working Organizing, Roosevelt Inst. (2015), https://rooseveltinstitute.org/publications/widening-the-scope-of-worker-organizing/.

36 See, e.g., Jonas Pontusson & David Rueda, Comparative Political Economy of Wage Distribution: The Role of Partisanship and Labour Market Institutions, 32 British J. Pol. Sci. 381, 289–290, 301 (2002); Andrias, supra Footnote note 9, at 94; Guy Mundlak, We Create Spots from Which We Shine to Others, 38 Compar. Lab. L & Pol’y J. 301 (2017).

37 For existing and historical examples of such administrative initiatives, see Kate Andrias, An American Approach to Social Democracy: The Forgotten Promise of the Fair Labor Standards Act, 128 Yale L.J. 616 (2019); K. Sabeel Rahman, Policymaking as Power-Building, 27 S. Cal. Interdisc. L.J. 315, 340–350 (2017).

38 Kate Andrias & Benjamin I. Sachs, Constructing Countervailing Power: Law and Organizing in an Era of Political Inequality, 130 Yale L.J. 546 (2021).

39 Frances Fox Piven & Richard A. Cloward, Poor People’s Movements: Why They Succeed and How They Fail 41, 50–60, 68–91 (1978).

40 Premilla Nadasen, Expanding the Boundaries of the Women’s Movement: Black Feminism and the Struggle for Welfare Rights, 28 Feminist Stud. 271, 275–277 (2002); Piven & Cloward, supra Footnote note 39, 286–287, 297–300.

41 For a history of care worker organizing, see generally Eileen Boris & Jennifer Klein, Caring for America: Home Health Workers in the Shadow of the Welfare State (2015).

42 Katherine Van Wezel Stone, Green Shoots in the Labor Market: A Cornucopia of Social Experiments, 36 Compar. Lab. L. & Pol’y J. 293, 319–320 (2015).

43 Ferpa, The History of Ferpa, https://ferpa.org/history-of-ferpa/ (accessed Mar. 5, 2021); see also Eurofound, Retirement, https://www.eurofound.europa.eu/topic/retirement (accessed Mar. 5, 2021); AGE, About AGE, https://www.age-platform.eu/about-age (accessed Mar. 5, 2020).

44 See Andrias & Sachs, supra Footnote note 38, at 555.

45 Matthew Dimick, Labor Law, New Governance, and the Ghent System, 90 N.C. L. Rev. 319, 329–336 (2012); Jochen Clasen & Elke Viebrock, Voluntary Unemployment Insurance and Trade Union Membership, 37 J. Soc. Pol’y 433, 437–438 (2008).

46 David Madland & Malkie Wall, American Ghent: Designing Programs to Strengthen Unions and Improve Government Services, Ctr. for Am. Progress (2019), https://www.americanprogress.org/issues/economy/reports/2019/09/18/474690/american-ghent/.

47 Alstott, supra Footnote note 6, at 147, 148.

48 Cynthia L. Estlund, The Ossification of American Labor Law, 102 Colum. L. Rev. 1527, 1530–1531 (2002).

49 See Andrias & Sachs, supra Footnote note 38, at 631–637.

10 The Savings Mirage

1 Guillermo Bermudez, Saving for Retirement Made Easy (2020).

2 Patrick Foley & Kristin Hillsley, Winning at Retirement: A Guide to Health, Wealth & Purpose in the Best Years of Your Life (2018).

3 Christine Ibbotson, How to Retire Debt-Free and Wealthy: A Finance Coach Reveals the Secrets, Tips, and Techniques of How Clients Become Millionaires (2020).

4 See, e.g., Alicia Lloro et al., Economic Well-Being of U.S. Households in 2022, Bd. of Governors of the Fed. Reserve Sys. (2023), at 31, https://www.federalreserve.gov/publications/files/2022-report-economic-well-being-us-households-202305.pdf.

5 Economic Policy Institute, The State of Working America, http://www.stateofworkingamerica.org/index.html%3Fp=4173.html. Among Black families with children, 57.5 percent are net-worth-poor. See Christina Gibson-Davis, Lisa A. Keister & Lisa A. Gennetian, Net Worth Poverty in Child Households by Race and Ethnicity, 1989–2019, J. Marriage & Fam. 1, 1 (2020).

6 Pamela Foohey & Sara S. Greene, How Government Rules Prevent Poor Americans from Saving, Politico (Sep. 3, 2020), https://www.politico.com/news/agenda/2020/09/03/how-government-keeps-poor-from-saving-407839.

7 Anne L. Alstott, A New Deal for Old Age 1–2 (2016); Anne Alstott, Law and the Hundred-Year Life, 26 Elder L. J. 131, 137–138 (2018). See also Deborah Thorne, Pamela Foohey, Robert M. Lawless & Katherine M. Porter, Graying of U.S. Bankruptcy: Fallout from Life in a Risk Society, 90 Soc. Inquiry 681, 684–685 (2020).

8 Thorne et al., supra Footnote note 7, at 685.

9 Alstott, A New Deal, supra Footnote note 7, at 18, 20; Alstott, Law and the Hundred-Year Life, supra Footnote note 7 at 131, 132; Lynda Gratton & Andrew Scott, The 100-Year Life 1 (2016).

10 Kevin C. Fleming, Jonathan M. Evans & Darryl S. Chutka, A Cultural and Economic History of Old Age in America, 78 Mayo Clin. Proc. 914, 914 (2003).

11 Gratton & Scott, supra Footnote note 9, at 1–4.

12 Anne Alstott provides a fascinating and important discussion of inequality in longevity. People who are poor have significantly lower life expectancies than those who are rich. Thus, there is no doubt that it will take longer for those who are poor to reach the 100-year life benchmark than those who are rich. Nonetheless, the upward trend in longevity holds for all groups. Alstott, A New Deal, supra Footnote note 7, at 20–21.

13 See Foohey & Greene, supra Footnote note 6. And obtaining a job available to low-wage workers when one is elderly, even if physically able, is elusive as there are almost always younger people in need, ready and willing to work. Research shows that employers prefer (and hire) these younger workers. So, the elderly are left poor and with few options.

14 Thorne et al., supra Footnote note 7, at 681, 682.

16 Fleming et al., supra Footnote note 10, at 914, 915; Thorne et al., supra Footnote note 7, at 681, 682.

17 Fleming et al., supra Footnote note 10, at 914, 917.

19 Thorne et al., supra Footnote note 7, at 681, 683.

20 Fleming et al., supra Footnote note 10, at 914, 917.

21 Sara Sternberg Greene, The Broken Safety Net: A Study of Earned Income Tax Credit Recipients and a Proposal for Repair, 88 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 515, 533 (2013).

22 Thorne et al., supra Footnote note 7, at 681, 684.

23 Jacob Hacker, The Great Risk Shift: The Assault on American Jobs, Families, Health Care, and Retirement and How You Can Fight Back (2006).

24 Lawrence H. Summers, Helping America to Save More, US Dep’t of the Treasury (Apr. 4, 2000), https://www.treasury.gov/press-center/press-releases/Pages/ls524.aspx.

28 See, e.g., US Dep’t of Lab., Top 10 Ways to Prepare for Retirement (Sep. 2021), https://files.eric.ed.gov/fulltext/ED496720.pdf; Fin. Literacy & Educ. Comm’n, Taking Ownership of the Future: The National Strategy for Financial Literacy 1–9, 19–28 (2006), https://www.treasury.gov/about/organizational-structure/offices/Domestic-Finance/Documents/Strategyeng.pdf.

29 J. Mark Iwry, Helping More Americans Save, US Dep’t of the Treasury (Feb. 26, 2015), https://www.treasury.gov/connect/blog/Pages/Helping-More-Americans-Save.aspx.

32 Summers, supra Footnote note 24.

34 See Alstott, A New Deal, supra Footnote note 7; Dorothy A. Brown, The Whiteness of Wealth (2021).

35 Kate Lobosco, Treasury Ends the MyRA, Obama’s Retirement Savings Program, CNN (July 28, 2017), https://money.cnn.com/2017/07/28/retirement/treasury-myra-retirement-account/index.html.

36 See Greene, supra Footnote note 21, at 563–564.

37 Martha Ross & Nicole Bateman, Low-Wage Work Is More Pervasive Than You Think and There Aren’t Enough “Good Jobs” to Go Around, Brookings (Nov. 21, 2019), https://www.brookings.edu/blog/the-avenue/2019/11/21/low-wage-work-is-more-pervasive-than-you-think-and-there-arent-enough-good-jobs-to-go-around/.

40 Kaitlyn Henderson, The Crisis of Low Wages in the US 3 (2022).

41 See Greene, supra Footnote note 21, at 544–552.

42 U.S. Gov’t Accountability Office, Federal Social Safety New Programs: Millions of Full-Time Workers Rely on Federal Health Care and Food Assistance Programs (Oct. 2020), https://www.gao.gov/assets/720/710203.pdf.

43 Juliet M. Brodie, Clare Pastore, Ezra Rosser & Jeffrey Selbin, Poverty Law, Policy, and Practice 89 (2014).

44 Kathryn J. Edin & H. Luke Schaefer, $2.00 a Day: Living on Almost Nothing in America 15 (2016); Martin Gilens, Why Americans Hate Welfare: Race, Media, and the Politics of Antipoverty Policy 1–32 (2000).

45 Elizabeth Powers, Does Means Testing Welfare Discourage Saving? Evidence from a Change in AFDC Policy in the United States, 68 J. of Pub. Econ. 33, 33–53 (1998).

46 See Vicki Lens, Public Voices and Public Policy: Changing the Societal Discourse on “Welfare,” 39 J. Soc. & Soc. Welfare 137, 144–146 (2002).

47 Sara Sternberg Greene, The Bootstrap Trap, 67 Duke L. J. 233, 236–237 (2016).

49 Leah Hamilton, The Forgotten 1980s Rule That’s Hurting Poor Families Savings, The Atlantic (Mar. 11, 2015), https://www.theatlantic.com/business/archive/2015/03/the-forgotten-1980s-rule-thats-hurting-poor-families-savings/387373/.

50 U.S. Dep’t of Health and Human Services, Welfare Indicators and Risk Factors (Apr. 26, 2022), 33, https://aspe.hhs.gov/sites/default/files/documents/85da9415ece89b2989ad290755d38f7b/welfare-indicators-rtc.pdf.

51 US Census Bureau, 21.3 Percent of U.S. Population Participates in Government Assistance Programs Each Month (May 28, 2015), https://www.census.gov/newsroom/press-releases/2015/cb15-97.html.

52 Kathleen Romig et al., The Case for Updating SSI Asset Limits, Center on Budget and Policy Priorities (Sep. 2023), https://www.ssa.gov/ssi#:~:TEXT=SUPPLEMENTAL%20SECURITY%20INCOME%20(SSI)%20IS,OR%20%243%2C000%20FOR%20A%20COUPLE.

53 US Dep’t of Agriculture, Food and Nutrition Services, SNAP Eligibility for October 1, 2022–September 30, 2023, https://www.fns.usda.gov/snap/recipient/eligibility (accessed Jan. 7, 2024). Unlike Medicaid, for example, some retirement and pension plans are excluded from SNAP asset limits. However, most low-wage workers do not have jobs that provide employer-sponsored pension or retirement plans. Further, low-wage workers may rationally be hesitant to tie savings up in retirement plans that have penalties for early withdrawal, given the general instability of their financial lives and the potential for a shock to occur, requiring them to use at least some of their savings to recover from the shock. See Greene, supra Footnote note 21, at 533.

54 Maureen Pirog, Edwin Gerrish & Lindsey Bullinger, A Report to the Pew Charitable Trusts: TANF and SNAP Asset Limits and the Financial Behavior of Low-Income Households, https://www.pewtrusts.org/-/media/assets/2017/09/tanf_and_snap_asset_limits_and_the_financial_behavior_of_low_income_households.pdf.

55 Noelle Cornelio et al., Increasing Medicaid’s Stagnant Asset Test for People Eligible for Medicare and Medicaid Will Help Vulnerable Seniors, 40 Health Affs. 1943 (Dec. 2021).

56 The Retirement Security Project, Removing Barriers to Retirement Saving in Medicaid and Supplemental Security Income (2016), at 4, https://www.brookings.edu/wp-content/uploads/2016/07/10_removing_barriers.pdf. Many states do count retirement savings in traditional retirement accounts as assets. American Council on Aging, How Retirement Savings (IRAs, 401Ks or Pensions) Impact Medicaid Long Term Care Eligibility (updated Nov. 10, 2023), https://www.medicaidplanningassistance.org/medicaid-eligibility-401k-ira/.

57 The Retirement Security Project, supra Footnote note 56, at 4.

59 The Retirement Security Project, Increasing Retirement Savings: Clarifying Food Stamp Asset Test Rules (2007), at 1, https://www.brookings.edu/wp-content/uploads/2016/07/03_increasing_saving.pdf.

60 Pirog et al., supra Footnote note 54; Henry Chen & Robert I. Lerman, Do Asset Limits in Social Programs Affect the Accumulation of Wealth, The Urban Institute (2005), https://www.urban.org/research/publication/do-asset-limits-social-programs-affect-accumulation-wealth; Erik Hurst & James P. Ziliak, Do Welfare Asset Limits Affect Household Saving? Evidence from Welfare Reform, 41 J. Hum. Resources 46 (2006).

61 See Michael S. Barr, Banking the Poor: Policies to Bring Low-Income Americans into the Financial Mainstream, Brookings Inst. (Sep. 2004), https://www.brookings.edu/wp-content/uploads/2016/06/20041001_Banking.pdf; Mehrsa Baradaran, How the Other Half Banks: Exclusion, Exploitation, and the Threat to Democracy (2015).

62 US Census Bureau, 21.3 Percent of U.S. Population Participates in Government Assistance Programs Each Month (May 28, 2015), https://www.census.gov/newsroom/press-releases/2015/cb15-97.html.

63 See Alstott, A New Deal, supra Footnote note 7, at 1–2.

64 See Alstott, Law and the Hundred-Year Life, supra Footnote note 7, at 141.

65 National Council on Aging, Get the Facts on Economic Security for Seniors (Mar. 2021), https://www.ncoa.org/article/get-the-facts-on-economic-security-for-seniors.

67 Teresa Ghilarducci, Michael Papadopoulos & Anthony Webb, 40% of Older Workers and Their Spouses Will Experience Downward Mobility in Retirement, Schwartz Center for Economic Policy Analysis (2018), http://www.economicpolicyresearch.org/images/docs/research/retirement_security/Downward_Mobility_in_Retirement_P_N.pdf.

68 See Summers, supra Footnote note 24.

11 Trusts and the 100-Year Life

1 John H. Langbein, The Twentieth-Century Revolution in Family Wealth Transmission86 Mich. L. Rev. 722 (1988).

12 The Right to Grow Old

1 Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, 473 U.S. 432, 445–446 (1985).

2 US Const. Amend. V, Amend. XIV, Amend. VIII.

3 See Kimel v. Fla. Board of Regents, 528 U.S. 62 (2000); Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452 (1991).

4 See Gregory, 501 U.S. at 470–471; Vance v. Bradley, 440 U.S. 93, 108–109 (1979).

5 See Lynda Gratton & Andrew Scott, The 100-Year Life: Living and Working in an Age of Longevity 22–25 (2016).

6 See Castle Rock v. Gonzales, 545 U.S. 748 (2005); DeShaney v. Winnebago County Dep’t of Soc. Servs., 489 U.S. 189 (1989); Harris v. McRae, 448 U.S. 297 (1980); San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973); Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.S. 471 (1970).

7 See Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229 (1976); Personnel Administrator of Mass. v. Feeney, 442 U.S. 256 (1978); Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990).

8 DeShaney, 489 U.S. 189.

9 Footnote Id. at 196.

10 See Dandridge, 397 U.S. 471.

11 Maher v. Roe, 432 U.S. 464 (1977); Harris, 448 U.S. 297.

12 Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1.

13 See Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390 (1923).

14 See Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335 (1963).

15 See David A. Strauss, Foreword: Does the Constitution Mean What It Says? 129 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 3 (2015).

16 See United States v. Guest, 383 U.S. 745, 762 (1966) (Clark, J., concurring); Footnote id. at 774, 777 (Brennan, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).

17 See Burton v. Wilmington Parking Auth., 365 U.S. 715 (1961); Peterson v. City of Greenville, 373 U.S. 244 (1963); Robinson v. Florida, 378 U.S. 153 (1964); Lombard v. Louisiana, 373 U.S. 267 (1963); see also Jones v. Alfred H. Mayer Co., 392 U.S. 409 (1968).

18 See Gideon, 372 U.S. 335.

19 Douglas v. California, 372 U.S. 353, 357 (1963).

20 See Harper v. Va. Board of Elec., 383 U.S. 663 (1966).

21 See Boddie v. Connecticut, 401 U.S. 371, 380–381 (1971).

22 See San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973).

23 See Footnote id. at 36–37.

25 457 U.S. 202 (1982).

26 Footnote Id. at 221.

28 See Kevin J. McMahon, Nixon’s Court: His Challenge to Judicial Liberalism and Its Political Consequences 7 (2011).

29 See Footnote id. at 36.

30 Footnote Id. at 43.

31 See Footnote id. at 58, 74.

32 See Footnote id. at 80, 87.

33 See John C. Jeffries, Jr., Justice Lewis F. Powell, Jr.: A Biography 40–41 (2001).

34 See Brad Snyder & John Q. Barrett, Rehnquist’s Missing Letter: A Former Law Clerk’s 1955 Thoughts on Justice Jackson and Brown, 53 B.C. L. Rev. 631 (2012).

35 Footnote Id. at 298 n.53.

36 397 U.S. 471.

37 432 U.S. 464.

38 448 U.S. 297.

39 Footnote Id. at 343–344 (Marshall, J., dissenting).

40 San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973).

41 See Footnote id. at 12.

42 See Goss v. Knoxville Bd. of Educ., 373 U.S. 683 (1963).

43 See Griffin v. Prince Edward County Sch. Bd., 377 U.S. 218 (1964).

44 426 U.S. 229 (1976).

45 J. M. Barrie, Peter and Wendy 1 (1911).

46 See Nicholas J. G. Winter, Beyond Welfare: Framing and the Racialization of White Opinion on Social Security, 50 Am. J. Pol. Sci. 400 (2006).

47 [1990] 3 S.C.R. 229 (Can.).

48 [1991] 2 S.C.R. 22 (Can.).

49 Gregory, 501 U.S. 452.

50 Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act, 1982, c. 11 (U.K.), § 15(1) [hereinafter Charter].

51 Footnote Id., sec. 1; see McKinney, 3 S.C.R., at 278.

52 See McKinney, 3 S.C.R., at 282–289.

53 See Tetreault-Gadoury, 2 S.C.R., at 41; McKinney, 3 S.C.R., at 279; Andrews v. Law Soc’y of Brit. Col., [1989] 1 S.CR. 143 (Can.).

54 See Tetreault-Gadoury, 2 S.C.R., at 45.

55 [1997] 3 S.C.R. 624 (Can.).

56 See Footnote id. at 676, 686.

57 Footnote Id. at 687–688.

58 Footnote Id. at 688.

59 Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990, Pub. L. No. 101–336, 104 Stat. 327 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 29, 42, and 47 U.S.C.).

60 Rehabilitation Act of 1973, Pub. L. No. 93–112, 87 Stat. 355 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 29 U.S.C.).

61 Individuals with Disabilities Education Act (IDEA), Pub. L. No. 101–476, 104 Stat. 1103 (1990) (codified as amended and reauthorized at 20 U.S.C. §§ 1400–1485).

62 Age Discrimination in Employment Act of 1967, Pub. L. No. 90–202, 81 Stat. 602 (codified as amended at 29 U.S.C. §§ 621–634).

63 Age Discrimination Act of 1975, Pub. L. No. 94–135, 89 Stat. 728 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 6101–6107).

64 See Bd. of Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356 (2001); Kimel v. Fla. Bd. of Regents, 528 U.S. 62 (2000).

65 See Kimel, 528 U.S., at 80.

66 Nat’l Fed’n of Indep. Bus. v. Sebelius, 567 U.S. 519, 550–555 (2012) (opinion of Roberts, J.).

67 See U.N. Comm. on Econ., Soc. & Cultural Rights, Report on the Fifth Session, Supp. No. 3, Annex III ¶ 10, U.N. Doc. E/1991/23 (1991).

68 U.N. Comm. on Econ., Soc. & Cultural Rights, 22d Sess., The Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of Health, U.N. Doc. E/C, Dec. 4, 2000, ICESR General Comment 14 (2000), at ¶43.

69 See Gov’t of the Republic of S. Afr. v. Grootboom & Others, 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) (S.Afr.).

70 See David Landau, The Promise of a Minimum Core Approach: The Colombian Model for Judicial Review of Austerity Measures, in Economic and Social Rights after the Global Financial Crisis 267 (Aoife Nolan ed., 2014).

71 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, Art. 2(1), Dec. 16, 1966, 993 U.N.T.S. 3.

72 Katharine G. Young, Waiting for Rights: Progressive Realization and Lost Time, in The Future of Economic and Social Rights 654, 654 (Katharine G. Young ed., 2019).

73 See Footnote id. at 661–662; S. Afr. Const. §§ 26–27; see also Maldives Const. § 23; Kenya Const. §§ 21, 82; S. Sudan Const. § 34; Zimbabwe Const. §§ 73, 75, 82; Fiji Const. §§ 31–38; Guyana Const. § 154a.

74 Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 349 U.S. 294, 301 (1955).

75 See Charles F. Sabel & William H. Simon, Destabilization Rights: How Public Law Litigation Succeeds, 117 Harv. L. Rev. 1016 (2004).

76 State v. Ntuli, 1996 (1) SA 1207 (CC) (S. Afr.).

77 N. Pipeline Constr. Co. v. Marathon Pipe Line Co., 458 U.S. 50, 88 (1981).

Accessibility standard: Unknown

Accessibility compliance for the HTML of this book is currently unknown and may be updated in the future.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×