Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-21T05:17:53.973Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

Chapter 9 - Normality

Paul R. Halmos
Affiliation:
Santa Clara University
Get access

Summary

Unitary transformations

The three most obvious pleasant relations that a linear transformation on an inner product space can have to its adjoint are that they are equal (Hermitian), or that one is the negative of the other (skew), or that one is the inverse of the other (not yet discussed). The word that describes the last of these possibilities is unitary: that's what a linear transformation U is called in case it is invertible and U−1 = U*. The definition can be expressed in a “less prejudiced” way as U * U = 1—less prejudiced in the sense that it assumes less—but it is not clear that the less prejudiced way yields just as much. Does it?

Problem 139. If U is a linear transformation such that U * U = 1, does it follow that U * U = 1?

Unitary matrices

It seems fair to apply the word “unitary” to a matrix in case the linear transformation it defines is a unitary one. (Caution: when language that makes sense in inner product spaces only is applied to matrices, the basis that establishes the correspondence between matrices and linear transformations had better be an orthonormal one.) A quick glance usually suffices to tell whether or not a matrix is Hermitian; is there a way to tell by looking at a matrix whether or not it is unitary? The following special cases are a fair test of any proposed answer to the general question.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Mathematical Association of America
Print publication year: 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Normality
  • Paul R. Halmos, Santa Clara University
  • Book: Linear Algebra Problem Book
  • Online publication: 05 October 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.5948/9781614442127.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Normality
  • Paul R. Halmos, Santa Clara University
  • Book: Linear Algebra Problem Book
  • Online publication: 05 October 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.5948/9781614442127.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Normality
  • Paul R. Halmos, Santa Clara University
  • Book: Linear Algebra Problem Book
  • Online publication: 05 October 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.5948/9781614442127.010
Available formats
×