Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-zzh7m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T12:40:09.883Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 October 2018

Arif Ahmed
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Newcomb's Problem , pp. 221 - 231
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abramson, P. R., Aldrich, J. H., Paolino, P. and Rohde, D. W.. 1992. ‘Sophisticated’ voting in the 1988 Presidential Primaries. American Political Science Review 86: 5569.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2007. Agency and causation. In Corry, R. and Price, H. (ed.), Causation, Physics and the Constitution of Reality: Russell’s Republic Revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 120–55.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2014a. Evidence, Decision and Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2014b. Dicing with death. Analysis 74: 587–92.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2015. Infallibility in the Newcomb problem. Erkenntnis 80: 261–73.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2017. Exploiting Causal Decision Theory. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. Forthcoming. Self-control and hyperbolic discounting. In Bermúdez, J. L. (ed.) Self-Control & Rationality: Interdisciplinary Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. and Caulton, A.. 2014. Causal Decision Theory and EPR correlations. Synthese 191: 4315–52.Google Scholar
Ainslie, G. 1991. Derivation of ‘rational’ economic behaviour from hyperbolic discount curves. American Economic Review 81: 334–40.Google Scholar
Al-Najjar, N. and Weinstein, J.. 2009. The ambiguity aversion literature: a critical assessment. Economics and Philosophy 25: 249–84.Google Scholar
Allais, M. 1953. Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: critique des postulats et axiomes de l’école Américaine. Econometrica 21: 503–46.Google Scholar
Alston, W. P. 1988. An internalist externalism. Synthese 74: 265–83.Google Scholar
Alston, W. P. 2005. Beyond ‘Justification’: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Andreou, C. 2008. The Newxin Puzzle. Philosophical Studies 139: 415–22.Google Scholar
Arntzenius, F. 2003. Some problems for conditionalization and reflection. Journal of Philosophy 100: 356–70.Google Scholar
Arntzenius, F. 2008. No regrets, or: Edith Piaf revamps decision theory. Erkenntnis 68: 277–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arntzenius, F., Elga, A. and Hawthorne, J.. 2004. Bayesianism, infinite decisions, and binding. Mind 113: 251–83.Google Scholar
Aumann, R. 1987. Correlated equilibrium as an expression of Bayesian rationality. Econometrica 55: 118.Google Scholar
Aumann, R. and Brandenburger, A.. 1995. Epistemic conditions for Nash equilibrium. Econometrica 63: 1161–80.Google Scholar
Balleine, B. W., Espinet, A. and Gonzalez, F.. 2005. Perceptual learning enhances retrospective revaluation of conditioned flavour preferences in rats. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Learning and Cognition 31: 341–50.Google Scholar
Baratgin, J. and Politzer, G.. 2010. Updating: a psychologically basic situation of probability revision. Thinking & Reasoning 16: 253–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Battigalli, P. and Bonanno, G. 1999. Recent results on belief, knowledge and the epistemic foundations of game theory. Research in Economics 53: 149225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beebee, H. and Papineau, D.. 1997. Probability as a guide to life. Journal of Philosophy 94: 217–43.Google Scholar
Berkeley, G. 1980 [1710]. Principles of Human Knowledge. In his Philosophical Works, Ayers, M. (ed.). London: Everyman.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2009. Decision Theory and Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2013. Prisoner’s dilemma and Newcomb’s problem: why Lewis’s argument fails. Analysis 73: 423–29.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2015a. Prisoner’s dilemma cannot be a Newcomb problem. In Peterson, M. (ed.), The Prisoner’s Dilemma. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 115–32.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2015b. Strategic vs. parametric choice in Newcomb’s Problem and the Prisoner’s Dilemma: reply to Walker. Philosophia 43: 787–94.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. 1988. Modeling rational players: part II. Economics and Philosophy 4: 955.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K. 1993. De-Bayesing game theory. In Binmore, K., Kirman, A. and Tani, P. (ed.), Frontiers of Game Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 321–40.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. 1998. A representation theorem for a decision theory with conditionals. Synthese 116: 187229.Google Scholar
Brandenburger, A. 1992. Knowledge and equilibrium in games. Journal of Economic Perspectives 6: 83101.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. E. 1999. Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Briggs, R. A. 2010. Decision-theoretic paradoxes as voting paradoxes. Philosophical Review 119: 130.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1989. An economic Newcomb problem. Analysis 49: 220–22.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1990a. Bolker-Jeffrey expected utility theory and axiomatic utilitarianism. Review of Economic Studies 57: 477502.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1990b. Should a rational agent maximize expected itility? In Schweers Cook, Karen and Levi, Margaret (ed.), The Limits of Rationality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press: 132–45.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1991a. Weighing Goods. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1991b. Rationality and the Sure Thing Principle. In Meeks, J. G. T. (ed.), Thoughtful Economic Man. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 74102.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2001. Are intentions reasons? And how should we cope with incommensurable values? In Morris, C. and Ripstein, A. (ed.), Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 98120.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. and Hájek, A.. 1997. David Hume, David Lewis, and decision theory. Mind 106: 411–28.Google Scholar
Cain, B. E. 1978. Strategic voting in Great Britain. American Journal of Political Science 22: 639–55.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1979. Causal laws and effective strategies. Noȗs 13: 419–37.Google Scholar
Cavalcanti, E. 2010. Causation, decision theory and Bell’s theorem: a quantum analogue of the Newcomb problem. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61: 569–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charig, C. R., Webb, D. R., Payne, S. R. and Wickham, O. E.. 1986. Comparison of treatment of renal calculi by operative surgery, percutaneous nephrolithotomy, and extracorporeal shock wave lithotripsy. British Medical Journal 292: 879–82.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 2001. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dawes, R. M. 1990. The potential nonfalsity of the false consensus effect. In Hogarth, R. M. (ed.), Insight in Decision Making. Chicago: University of Chicago Press: 179–99.Google Scholar
Dickinson, A. 2012. Associative learning and animal cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 367: 2733–42.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1984. Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1987. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 2003. Freedom Evolves. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 2015. Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. A. E. 1954. Can an effect precede its cause? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 28: 2744.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. A. E. 1964. Bringing about the past. Philosophical Review 73: 338–59. Reprinted in his Truth and Other Enigmas. London: Duckworth: 333–50.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. A. E. 1987. Reply to D. H. Mellor. In Taylor, B. (ed.), Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff: 287–98.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. A. E. 1986. Causal loops. In Flood, R. and Lockwood, M. (ed.), The Nature of Time. Oxford: Blackwell: 135–69. Reprinted in Dummett, M. A. E., The Seas of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press 1993: 349–75.Google Scholar
Downs, A. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Eells, E. 1981. Causality, utility, and decision. Synthese 48: 295329.Google Scholar
Eells, E. 1982. Rational Decision and Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Eells, E. 1984. Newcomb’s many solutions. Theory and Decision 16: 59105.Google Scholar
Eells, E. 1985. Causality, decision, and Newcomb’s paradox. In Campbell, R. and Sowden, L. (ed.), Paradoxes of Rationality and Cooperation: Prisoner’s Dilemma and Newcomb’s Problem. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press: 183213.Google Scholar
Eells, E. and Harper, W.. 1991. Ratifiability, game theory, and the principle of independence of irrelevant alternatives. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69: 119.Google Scholar
Egan, A. 2007. Some counterexamples to Causal Decision Theory. Philosophical Review 116: 93114.Google Scholar
El Skaf, R. and Imbert, C.. 2013. Unfolding in the empirical sciences: experiments, thought experiments and computer simulations. Synthese 190: 3451–74.Google Scholar
Ellsberg, D. 1961. Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics 75: 643–69.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1989. Solomonic Judgements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Field, H. H. 1977. Logic, meaning, and conceptual role. Journal of Philosophy 74: 379409.Google Scholar
Fiorina, M. P. 1990. Information and rationality in elections. In Ferejohn, J. A. and Kuklinski, J. H. (ed.), Information and Democratic Processes. Urbana: University of Illinois Press: 329–42.Google Scholar
Fischer, A. J. 1999. The probability of being decisive. Public Choice 101: 267–83.Google Scholar
Fishburn, P. C. 1964. Decision and Value Theory. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Fiske, S. T. and Taylor, S. E.. 1984. Social Cognition. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Fleurbaey, M. and Voorhoeve, A.. 2013. Decide as you would with full information! An argument against ex ante Pareto. In Eyal, N., Hurst, S. A., Norheim, O. F. and Wikler, D. (ed.), Inequalities in Health: Concepts, Measures, and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 113–28.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1953. Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Frydman, R., O’Driscoll, G. P. and Schotter, A.. 1982. Rational expectations of government policy: an application of Newcomb’s problem. Southern Economic Journal 1982: 311–19.Google Scholar
Fudenberg, D. and Tirole, J.. 1991. Game Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1989. In the neighbourhood of the Newcomb-Predictor. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89: 179–94.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1994. Assure and threaten. Ethics 194: 690721.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1992. Weakly self-ratifying strategies: comments on McClennen. Philosophical Studies 65: 217–25.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. and Harper, W.. 1978. Counterfactuals and two kinds of expected utility. In Hooker, A., Leach, J. J. and McClennen, E. F. (ed.), Ifs: Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance and Time. Dordrecht: D. Reidel: 153–90.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. 1967. On the principle of total evidence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17: 319–21.Google Scholar
Grafstein, R. 1991. An Evidential Decision Theory of turnout. American Journal of Political Science 35: 9891010.Google Scholar
Grafstein, R. 1999. Choice-Free Rationality. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Grafstein, R. 2002. What rational political actors can expect. Journal of Theoretical Politics 14: 139–65.Google Scholar
Grafstein, R. 2003. Strategic voting in presidential primaries: problems of explanation and interpretation. Political Research Quarterly 56: 513–19.Google Scholar
Greene, P. 2013. Rationality and Success. Dissertation. New Brunswick: Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. 2016. Deliberation welcomes prediction. Episteme 13: 507–28.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. A Puzzle about Degree of Belief. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Hall, N. 1994. Correcting the guide to objective chance. Mind 103: 505–18.Google Scholar
Hall, N. 2004. Two mistakes about credence and chance. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82: 93111.Google Scholar
Hare, C. and Hedden, B.. 2016. Self-reinforcing and self-frustrating decisions. Noûs 50: 604–28.Google Scholar
Harper, W. L. 1975. Rational belief change, Popper functions and counterfactuals. Synthese 30: 221–62.Google Scholar
Harper, W. L. 1986. Mixed strategies and ratifiability in Causal Decision Theory. Erkenntnis 24: 2536.Google Scholar
Hedden, B. 2015. Time-slice rationality. Mind 124: 449–91.Google Scholar
Hesslow, G. 1976. Discussion: two notes on the probabilistic approach to causality. Philosophy of Science 43: 290–2.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, C. 1996. Causal Decision Theory and decision-theoretic causation. Noûs 30: 508–26.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, C. 2015. Conditioning, intervening and decision. Synthese 193: 1157–76.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. 1981. Counterfactuals and Newcomb’s problem. Journal of Philosophy 78: 331–56.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. 1985. Newcomb’s problem: a stalemate. In Campbell, R. and Sowden, L. (ed.), Paradoxes of Rationality and Co-operation: Prisoner’s Dilemma and Newcomb’s Problem. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press: 223–33.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 1987. Asymmetries in Time: Problems in the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hurley, S. L. 1991. Newcomb’s problem, prisoners’ dilemma, and collective action. Synthese 86: 173–96.Google Scholar
Hurley, S. L. 1994. A new take from Nozick on Newcomb’s Problem and Prisoners’ Dilemma. Analysis 54: 6572.Google Scholar
Ismael, J. 2007. Freedom, compulsion, and causation. Psyche 13: 110.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. and Pargetter, R.. 1983. Where the tickle defence goes wrong. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 295–99.Google Scholar
Jacobi, N. 1993. Newcomb’s paradox: a realist resolution. Theory and Decision 35: 117.Google Scholar
James, W. 1912. The will to believe. In his Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy. New York: Henry Holt and Co.: 1–32. Reprinted in McDermott, J. J. (ed.), The Writings of William James. New York: Random House. Reprint, Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1978: 717–35.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. 1965. The Logic of Decision. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. 1983. The Logic of Decision. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 1998. A nonpragmatic vindication of probabilism. Philosophy of Science 65: 575603.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 1999. Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J. 2002. Levi on Causal Decision Theory and the possibility of predicting one’s own actions. Philosophical Studies 110: 69102.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 2007. Are Newcomb problems really decisions? Synthese 156: 537–62.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 2010a Causal reasoning and backtracking. Philosophical Studies 147: 139–54.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 2010b. A defence of imprecise credences in inference and decision making. Philosophical Perspectives 19: 153–78.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 2012. Regret and instability in Causal Decision Theory. Synthese 187: 123–45.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 2016. Review essay: Arif Ahmed, Evidence, Decision and Causality. Journal of Philosophy 113: 224–32.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A.. 1984. Choices, values, and frames. American Psychologist 39: 341–50.Google Scholar
Kanazawa, S. 2000. A new solution to the collective action problem: the paradox of voter turnout. American Sociological Review 65: 433–42.Google Scholar
Kane, R. 1996. The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Katsuno, H. and Mendelzon, A. O.. 1991. On the difference between updating a knowledge base and revising it. In Proceedings of the Second International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning. Vol. 2. San Francisco: Morgan Kaufman Publishers: 387–94.Google Scholar
Kavka, G. S. 1983. The Toxin Puzzle. Analysis 43: 3336.Google Scholar
Kneale, W. C. 1949. Probability and Induction. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lange, M. 1999. Calibration and the epistemological role of Bayesian conditionalization. Journal of Philosophy 96: 294324.Google Scholar
Ledyard, J. O. 1984. The pure theory of large two-candidate elections. Public Choice 44: 741.Google Scholar
Ledyard, J. O. 1995. Public goods: a survey of experimental research. In Kagel, J. H., and Roth, A. E. (ed.), The Handbook of Experimental Economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press: 111–94.Google Scholar
LeRoy, S. F. 1995. On policy regimes. In Hoover, K. D. (ed.), Macroeconometrics. Boston: Kluwer: 235–61.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 1974. On indeterminate probabilities. Journal of Philosophy 71: 391418.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 1975. Newcomb’s many problems. Theory and Decision 6: 161–75.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 1989. Rationality, prediction and autonomous choice. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplemental Vol. 19: 339–63.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 1992. Feasibility. In Bicchieri, C. and Dalla Chiara, M. L. (ed.), Knowledge, Belief, and Strategic Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 120.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 1997a. Advising rational agents. Economics & Politics 9: 221–24.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 1997b. The Covenant of Reason: Rationality and the Commitments of Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 2000. Review: James M. Joyce, The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Journal of Philosophy 97: 387402.Google Scholar
Levi, I. 2012. Hard Choices. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1973. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1976a. The paradoxes of time travel. American Philosophical Quarterly 13:145152. Reprinted in his Philosophical Papers Vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986: 67–80.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1976b. Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philosophical Review 85: 297315.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1979. Prisoners’ dilemma is a Newcomb problem. Philosophy and Public Affairs 8: 235–40.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1980. A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In Jeffrey, R. C. (ed.), Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability Vol. II. Berkeley: University of California Press: 263–94. Reprinted in his Philosophical Papers Vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986: 83–132.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1981a. Causal Decision Theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59: 530. Reprinted in his Philosophical Papers Vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986: 305–39.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1981b. Why ain’cha rich? Noûs 15: 377–80. Reprinted in his Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000: 37–41.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1994a. Reduction of mind. In Guttenplan, S. (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell: 412–31.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1994b. Humean supervenience debugged. Mind 103: 473–90.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1999. Why Conditionalize? In his Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 403–7.Google Scholar
Lindley, D. and Novick, M.. 1981. The role of exchangeability in inference. Annals of Statistics 9: 4558.Google Scholar
Luce, R. D. and Raiffa, H.. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Newcomb’s Paradox and the direction of causation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 213–25.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1980. The Cement of the Universe. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McClennen, E. F. 1990. Rationality and Dynamic Choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McClennen, E. F. 1992. The theory of rationality for ideal games. Philosophical Studies 65: 193215.Google Scholar
Meacham, C. J. G. 2010. Binding and its consequences. Philosophical Studies 149: 4971.Google Scholar
Meek, C. and Glymour, C.. 1994. Conditioning and intervening. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45: 1001–21.Google Scholar
Mehta, J., Starmer, C. and Sugden, R.. 1994. The nature of salience: an experimental investigation of pure coordination games. American Economic Review 84: 658–73.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 1971. The Matter of Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 1991. Objective decision making. In his Matters of Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 269–87.Google Scholar
Menzies, P. and Price, H.. 1993. Causation as a secondary quality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44: 187203.Google Scholar
Meyer, D., Feldmaier, J. and Shen, H.. 2016. Reinforcement learning in conflicting environments for autonomous vehicles. Conference proceedings: Robotics in the 21st Century: Challenges and Promises. arXiv: 1610.07089v1.Google Scholar
Monterosso, J. and Ainslie, G.. 1999. Beyond discounting: Possible experimental models of impulse control. Psychopharmacology 146: 339–47.Google Scholar
Moss, S. 2012. Updating as communication. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85: 225–48.Google Scholar
Moss, S. 2013. Epistemology formalized. Philosophical Review 122: 143.Google Scholar
Moss, S. Forthcoming. Probabilistic Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nash, J. 1951. Non-cooperative games. Annals of Mathematics 54: 286–95.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 2001 [1886]. Beyond Good and Evil. Tr. Norman, J.. Ed. Horstmann, R.-P.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1969. Newcomb’s problem and two principles of choice. In Rescher, N. (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel. Dordrecht: D. Reidel: 114–46. Reprinted in P. Moser (ed.), Rationality in Action: Contemporary Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990: 207–34.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1993. The Nature of Rationality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
O’Flaherty, B. and Bhagwati, J.. 1997. Will free trade with political science put normative economists out of work? Economics & Politics 9: 207–19.Google Scholar
Okasha, S. 2015. On the interpretation of decision theory. Economics and Philosophy 32: 409–33.Google Scholar
Orbell, J. M., van de Kragt, A. J. C., and Dawes, R. M.. 1991. Covenants without the sword: the role of promises is social in social dilemma circumstances. In Koford, K. J. and Miller, J. B. (ed.), Social Norms and Economic Institutions. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press: 117–34.Google Scholar
Palfrey, T. R. and Rosenthal, H.. 1985. Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. American Political Science Review 79: 6278.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. 2000. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. 2009. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. 2014. Understanding Simpson’s Paradox. American Statistician 68: 813.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1988. The prisoner’s dilemma is an unexploitable Newcomb problem. Synthese 76: 123–34.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1991. Decision theory and folk psychology. In Bacharach, M. and Hurley, S. L. (ed.), Foundations of Decision Theory: Issues and Advances. Oxford: Basil Blackwell: 147–75.Google Scholar
Pollock, J. L. 2006. Thinking about Acting: Logical Foundations for Rational Decision Making. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1986. Against causal decision theory. Synthese 67: 195212.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1992. The direction of causation: Ramsey’s ultimate contingency. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association: 253–67.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2001. Causation in the special sciences: the case for pragmatism. In Costantini, D., Galavotti, M. C. and Suppes, P. (ed.), Stochastic Causality. Stanford: CSLI Publications: 103–20.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2007. Causal perspectivalism. In Corry, R. and Price, H. (ed.), Causation, Physics and the Constitution of Reality: Russell’s Republic Revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 250–92.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2012. Causation, chance, and the rational significance of supernatural evidence. Philosophical Review 121: 483538.Google Scholar
Quattrone, G. A. and Tversky, A.. 1986. Self-deception and the voter’s illusion. In Elster, J. (ed.), The Multiple Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 3558.Google Scholar
Quattrone, G. A. and Tversky, A.. 1988. Contrasting rational and psychological analyses of political choice. American Political Science Review 82: 719–36.Google Scholar
Quinn, W. 1990. The puzzle of the selftorturer. Philosophical Studies 59: 7990. Reprinted in his Morality and Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1993: 198–209.Google Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. 2002. Does practical deliberation crowd out self-prediction? Erkenntnis 57: 91122.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1990 [1926]. Truth and probability. In his Philosophical Papers, ed. Mellor, D. H.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990: 5294.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1978 [1929]. General propositions and causality. In Mellor, D. H. (ed.), Foundations: Essays in Philosophy, Logic, Mathematics and Economics. London: Routledge: 133–51.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. 1956. The Direction of Time. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Resnik, M. 1987. Choices: An Introduction to Decision Theory. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Sargent, T. J. 1981. Rational expectations and the theory of economic policy. In Lucas, R. E. Jr and Sargent, T. J. (ed.), Rational Expectations and Econometric Practice. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 199214.Google Scholar
Sargent, T. J. 1993. Bounded Rationality in Macroeconomics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sargent, T. J. and Wallace, N.. 1976. Rational expectations and the theory of economic policy. Journal of Monetary Economics 2: 169–83.Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. 1972. The Foundations of Statistics. 2nd ed. New York: Dover Press.Google Scholar
Schelling, T. C. 1960. The Strategy of Conflict. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Selten, R. 1975. Re-examination of the perfectness concept for equilibrium points in extensive games. International Journal of Game Theory 4: 2255.Google Scholar
Seidenfeld, T. 1985. Comments on Causal Decision Theory. PSA 1984 2: 201–12.Google Scholar
Shoham, Y. and Leyton-Brown, K.. 2009. Multiagent Systems: Algorithmic, Game-Theoretic, and Logical Foundations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sims, C. A. 1986. Are forecasting models usable for policy analysis? Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review 10: 216.Google Scholar
Sims, C. A. 2003. Implications of rational inattention. Journal of Monetary Economics 50: 665–90.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1980. Causal Necessity: A Pragmatic Investigation of the Necessity of Laws. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1982. Causal Decision Theory. Journal of Philosophy 79: 695711.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1990a. The value of knowledge. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14: 245–66.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1990b. The Dynamics of Rational Deliberation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Slezak, P. 2013. Realizing Newcomb’s problem. Available online at philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9634/1/Realizing_Newcomb’s_Problem.pdf (accessed 19 December 2017).Google Scholar
Smith, H. 1991. Deriving Morality from Rationality. In Vallentyne, P. (ed.), Contractarianism and Rational Choice: Essays on David Gauthier’s Morals by Agreement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 229–53.Google Scholar
Soares, N. and Fallenstein, B.. 2015. Toward idealized decision theory. arXiv: 1507.01986 [cs.AI].Google Scholar
Soares, N., Fallenstein, B. and Levinstein, B.. Cheating Death in Damascus. Available online at https://intelligence.org/files/DeathInDamascus.pdf. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Soares, N., Fallenstein, B. and Yudkowsky, E.. Functional Decision Theory: A New Theory of Instrumental Rationality. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Sobel, J. H. 1985a. Not every prisoner’s dilemma is a Newcomb problem. In Campbell, R. and Sowden, L. (ed.), Paradoxes of Rationality and Cooperation. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press: 263–74.Google Scholar
Sobel, J. H. 1985b Circumstances and dominance in a Causal Decision Theory. Synthese 63: 167202.Google Scholar
Sobel, J. H. 1986. Notes on decision theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64: 407–37. Reprinted in his Taking Chances. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1994: 141–73.Google Scholar
Spencer, J. and Wells, I.. 2017. Why take both boxes? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi: 10.1111/phpr.12466.Google Scholar
Spirtes, P., Glymour, C. and Scheines, R.. 2000. Causation, Prediction, and Search. 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Spohn, W. 1977. Where Luce and Krantz do really generalize Savage’s decision model. Erkenntnis 11: 113–34.Google Scholar
Spohn, W. 2012. Reversing 30 years of discussion: why Causal Decision Theorists should one-box. Synthese 187: 95122.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. C. 1972. Letter to David Lewis. Reprinted in Harper, W. L., Stalnaker, R. and Pearce, G. (ed.), Ifs: Conditionals, Beliefs, Chance and Time. Dordrecht: Springer, 1981: 151–52.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. C. 1996. Knowledge, belief and counterfactual reasoning in games. Economics and Philosophy 12: 133.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. C. 1997. On the evaluation of solution concepts. In Bacharach, M., Gérard-Varet, L.-A., Mongin, P. and Shin, H. S. (ed.), Epistemic Logic and the Theory of Games and Decisions. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers: 345–64.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. C. 1999. Extensive and strategic forms: games and models for games. Research in Economics 53: 293319.Google Scholar
Stern, R. 2017. Interventionist decision theory. Synthese 194: 4133–53.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 1986. Freedom and Belief. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 2003. Evolution explains it all for you. New York Times March 2. Available online at www.nytimes.com/2003/03/02/books/evolution-explains-it-all-for-you.html.Google Scholar
Suddendorf, T. and Corballis, M. C.. 2007. The evolution of foresight: what is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioural and Brain Sciences 30: 299313.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. 1995. A theory of focal points. Economic Journal 105: 533–50.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. and Zamarrón, I. E.. 2006. Finding the key: the riddle of focal points. Journal of Economic Psychology 27: 609–21.Google Scholar
Tang, W. H. 2016. Reliability theories of justified credence. Mind 125: 6394.Google Scholar
Tawney, R. H. 1998 [1926]. Religion and the Rise of Capitalism. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Teller, P. 1973. Conditionalization and observation. Synthese 26: 218–58.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. 1983. Calibration: a frequency justification for personal probability. In Cohen, R. and Laudan, L. (ed.), Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis. Dordrecht: D. Reidel: 295319.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. 1984. Belief and the will. Journal of Philosophy 81: 235–56.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. 1989. Epistemic freedom. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70: 7397.Google Scholar
Von Neumann, J. and Morgenstern, O.. 1944. Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Walker, M. T. 2014. The real reason why the Prisoner’s dilemma is not a Newcomb problem. Philosophia 42: 841–59.Google Scholar
Weber, M. 1992 [1920]. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Tr. Parsons, T.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. 2013. Gandalf’s solution to the Newcomb problem. Synthese 190: 2643–75.Google Scholar
Weirich, P. 1985. Decision Instability. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63: 465–72.Google Scholar
Weirich, P. 2004. Realistic Decision Theory: Rules for Nonideal Agents in Nonideal Circumstances. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wells, I. Forthcoming. Equal opportunity and Newcomb’s problem. Mind.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. 2003. Making Things Happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yudkowsky, E. 2010. Timeless decision theory. Technical Report, Machine Intelligence Research Institute (MIRI): www.intelligence.org.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Edited by Arif Ahmed, University of Cambridge
  • Book: Newcomb's Problem
  • Online publication: 15 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316847893.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Edited by Arif Ahmed, University of Cambridge
  • Book: Newcomb's Problem
  • Online publication: 15 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316847893.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Edited by Arif Ahmed, University of Cambridge
  • Book: Newcomb's Problem
  • Online publication: 15 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316847893.012
Available formats
×