Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-v5vhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T13:53:03.843Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Doxic paradoxes without self-reference

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 January 2010

Get access

Summary

PARADOX IN OPERATOR LOGIC

Both Richard Montague and Richmond Thomason have taken their discoveries of liar-like paradoxes in certain epistemic and doxic logics as a compelling reason for representing such notions only in languages in which no pernicious self-reference is possible. This can be achieved by representing the relevant epistemic or doxic notion by means of a sentential operator, rather than as a predicate of sentences (or of other entities with syntactic, sentence-like structure).

If it is possible to construct self-referential propositions (objects of evaluation, things that can be true or be believed), then we must consider such paradoxical sentences as ‘This sentence is not true’, ‘This sentence is not knowable’, or ‘This sentence is not rationally credible’. A sentence that asserts, in effect, that it is not true is called a “liar,” the traditional name of the paradox of Epimenides. If we assume that the liar is not, then it is not true, since that is what it asserts. But if we try to conclude that the liar is not true, then we seem to be forced to admit that it is true after all, since its nontruth is exactly what it asserts. Trying to evaluate the liar sentence forces us to contradict ourselves. The intensionalist seeks to avoid this contradiction by banishing self-referential objects from the domain of evaluation.

Nicholas Asher and Hans Kamp, as well as Donald Perlis, have shown that this strategy (called the “intensionalist” approach) alone is not enough to block the construction of paradoxes.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×