Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T12:05:33.587Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

14 - Problems chasing methods or methods chasing problems? Research communities, constrained pluralism, and the role of eclecticism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

Rudra Sil
Affiliation:
Department of Political Science, University of Pennsylvania
Ian Shapiro
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Rogers M. Smith
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania
Tarek E. Masoud
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Get access

Summary

The idea of a method that contains firm, unchanging, and absolutely binding principles for conducting the business of science meets considerable difficulty when confronted with the results of historical research. We find, then, that there is not a single rule, however plausible, and however firmly grounded in epistemology, that is not violated at some time or another. It becomes evident that such violations are not accidental events … [D]evelopments, such as … the Copernican Revolution … occurred only because some thinkers either decided not to be bound by certain “obvious” methodological rules, or because they unwittingly broke them.

(Feyerabend 1993: 14)

[I]f the notion of a theory-neutral observation language had been viable, and if theory changes were in fact cumulative, and if all scientists subscribed to the same methodological standards, and if there were mechanical algorithms for theory evaluation … then the positivists might well have been able to show wherein scientific rationality and objectivity consist. But that was not to come to pass … These days, social constructionists, epistemological anarchists, biblical inerrantists, political conservatives, and cultural relativists all find in the surviving traces of positivism grist for their mills; for what they find there appears to sustain their conviction that science has no particular claim on us, either as a source of beliefs or as a model of progressive, objective knowledge.

(Laudan 1996: 25)

Feyerabend and Laudan have been represented, by Laudan himself among others (e.g., Sanderson 1987), as competing perspectives in the philosophy of science.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ames, Barry. 1996. “Comparative Politics and the Replication Controversy.” APSA-CP: Newsletter of the APSA Organized Section in Comparative Politics 7(1) (Winter)Google Scholar
Bates, Robert, Avner Greif, Margaret Levi, Jean-Laurent Rosenthal, and Barry Weingast. 1998. Analytic Narratives. Princeton: Princeton University Press
Bhaskar, Roy. 1986. Scientific Realism and Human Emancipation. London: Verso
Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce. 1985. “Toward a Scientific Understanding of International Conflict.” International Studies Quarterly 29: 121–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caporaso, James. 1995. “Research Design, Falsification, and the Qualitative-Quantitative Divide.” American Political Science Review 89(2) (June): 457–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collier, David. 1995. “Translating Quantitative Methods for Qualitative Researchers: The Case of Selection Bias.” American Political Science Review 89(2) (June): 461–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, Michael. 1991. “Aberrations of the Realism Debate.” Philosophical Studies 61: 43–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durkheim, Emile. 1984 [1933]. The Division of Labor in Society. New York: Free Press
Feyerabend, Paul. 1993. Against Method (3rd edn). London: Verso
Fish, Stanley. 1989. Doing What Comes Naturally. Durham: Duke University Press
Gadamer, Hans-Gorg. 1976. Philosophical Hermeneutics. Berkeley: University of California Press
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books
Goldthorpe, John. 1996. “Current Issues in Comparative Methodology.” Comparative Social Research 16: 1–26Google Scholar
Habermas, Jurgen. 1987. “Modernity – an Incomplete Project,” in Rabinow and Sullivan (eds.)
Hempel, Carl G. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall
Joas, Hans. 1993. Pragmatism and Social Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Johnson, James. 2002. “How Conceptual Problems Migrate: Rational Choice, Interpretation and the Hazards of Pluralism.” Annual Review of Political Science 5: 223–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter and Rudra Sil. 2004. “Rethinking Security in East Asia: A Case for Analytical Eclecticism,” in Jae-Jung Suh, Peter Katzenstein, and Allen Carlson (eds.), Rethinking Security in Asia: Identity, Power and Efficiency. Stanford: Stanford University Press
King, Gary. 1995. “Replication, Replication.” Political Science 28(3) (September): 444–52Google Scholar
King, Gary, Robert Keohane, and Sidney Verba. 1994. Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research. Princeton: Princeton University Press
Kiser, Edgar and Michael, Hechter. 1998. “The Debate on Historical Sociology: Rational Choice Theory and its Critics.” American Journal of Sociology 104(3) (November): 785–816CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn Thomas. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Lakatos, Imre. 1970. “Falsification, and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,” in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. New York: Cambridge University Press. 91–196
Lalman, David, Joe Oppehneimer, and Piotr Swistak. 1993. “Formal Rational Choice Theory: A Cumulative Science of Politics,” in Ada Finifter (ed.), Political Science: The State of the Discipline II. Washington, DC: American Political Science Association
Laudan, Larry. 1977. Progress and its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth. Berkeley: University of California Press
Laudan, Larry. 1996. Beyond Postivism and Relativism. Boulder: Westview
Lindblom, Charles. 1959. “The Science of ‘Muddling Through’.” Public Administration Review 19 (Spring)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lustick, Ian. 1996. “History, Historiography, and Political Science: Multiple Historical Records and the Problem of Selection Bias.” American Political Science Review 90(3) (September): 605–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahoney, James. 2000. “Rational Choice Theory and the Comparative Method: An Emerging Synthesis?Studies in Comparative International Development 35(2) (Summer)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Makinda, Samuel. 2000. “International Society and Eclecticism in International Relations Theory.” Cooperation and Conflict 35(2) 205–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mead, George Herbert. 1964 [1956]. On Social Psychology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Munck, Gerardo. 2001. “Game Theory and Comparative Politics: New Perspectives and Old Concerns.” World Politics 53(2) 173–204CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myerson, Roger. 1992. “On the Value of Game Theory in Social Science.” Rationality and Society 4: 62–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinow, Paul and William Sullivan (eds.). 1987. Interpretive Social Science: A Second Look. Berkeley: University of California Press
Ragin, Charles. 2000. Fuzzy-Set Social Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Ricoeur, Paul. 1971. “The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action Considered as Text.” Social Research 38: 529–55Google Scholar
Rouse, Joseph. 1987. Knowledge and Power. Ithaca: Cornell University Press
Ruggie, John G. 1998. Constructing the World Polity. New York: Routledge
Sanderson, Stephen K. 1987. “Eclecticism and its Alternatives,” in John Wilson (ed.), Current Perspectives in Social Theory. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press
Schegloff, Emanuel. 1992. “Repair after Next Turn: The Last Structurally Provided Defense of Intersubjectivity in Conversation.” American Journal of Sociology 97(5) (March)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 2002. “Problems, Methods, and Theories in the Study of Politics, or What's Wrong with Political Science and What to Do About It?Political Theory 30(4) (August): 588–611CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sil, Rudra. 2000a. “The Division of Labor in Social Science Research: Unified Methodology or ‘Organic Solidarity’?Polity 32(4) (Summer): 499–531CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sil, Rudra 2000b. “The Foundations of Eclecticism: Agency, Culture and Structure in Social Theory.” Journal of Theoretical Politics 2(3) (July): 353–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sil, Rudra 2002. Managing “Modernity”: Work, Community, and Authority in Late-Industrializing Japan and Russia. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press
Sil, Rudra and Peter Katzenstein. 2003. “Analytic Eclecticism in the Study of Asian Security.” Presented at the Annual Meeting of the International Studies Association, Portland, Oregon, February 26–March 1
Skocpol, Theda, and Margaret, Somers. 1980. “The Uses of Comparative History in Macrosocial Inquiry.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 2(2) (April): 174–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Somers, Margaret. 1998. “We're No Angels: Realism, Rational Choice, and Relationality in Social Science.” American Journal of Sociology 104(3) (November): 722–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinmetz, George. 1998. “Critical Realism and Historical Sociology.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 40: 170–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tönnies, Ferdinand. 1957. Community and Society [Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft]. Charles P. Loomis (trans. and ed.), New York: Harper and Row
Waltz, Kenneth. 1979. The Theory of International Politics. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley
Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society, Volume 1. Berkeley: University of California Press
Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×