Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-11T09:40:00.400Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CHAPTER 4 - THE PROVABLY RECURSIVE FUNCTIONS OF ARITHMETIC

from Part 2 - Provable recursion in classical systems

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2012

Helmut Schwichtenberg
Affiliation:
Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität Munchen
Stanley S. Wainer
Affiliation:
University of Leeds
Get access

Summary

This chapter develops the classification theory of the provably recursive functions of arithmetic. The topic has a long history tracing back to Kreisel [1951], [1952] who, in setting out his “no-counter-example” interpretation, gave the first explicit characterization of the functions “computable in” arithmetic, as those definable by recursions over standard well-orderings of the natural numbers with order types less than ε0. Such a characterization seems now, perhaps, not so surprising in light of the groundbreaking work of Gentzen [1936], [1943], showing that these well orderings are just the ones over which one can prove transfinite induction in arithmetic, and hence prove the totality of functions defined by recursions over them. Subsequent work of the present authors [1970], [1971], [1972], extending previous results of Grzegorczyk [1953] and Robbin [1965], then provided other complexity characterizations in terms of natural, simply defined hierarchies of so-called “fast growing” bounding functions. What was surprising was the deep connection later discovered, first by Ketonen and Solovay [1981], between these bounding functions and a variety of combinatorial results related to the “modified” finite Ramsey theorem of Paris and Harrington [1977]. It is through this connection that one gains immediate access to a range of mathematically meaningful independence results for arithmetic and stronger theories. Thus, classifying the provably recursive functions of a theory not only gives a measure of its computational power; it also serves to delimit its mathematical power in providing natural examples of true mathematical statements it cannot prove.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×