Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T00:46:35.573Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Can Human Irrationality Be Experimentally Demonstrated?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

L. Jonathan Cohen
Affiliation:
Oxford University
Jonathan E. Adler
Affiliation:
Brooklyn College, City University of New York
Lance J. Rips
Affiliation:
Northwestern University, Illinois
Get access

Summary

Introduction

The experimental study of human rationality – that is, of validity in deductive or probabilistic reasoning – has become entangled during the past decade or so in a web of paradox. On the one hand, reputable investigators tell us that “certain psychological discoveries have bleak implications for human rationality” (Nisbett & Borgida 1975), or that “for anyone who would wish to view man as a reasonable intuitive statistician, such results are discouraging” (Kahneman & Tversky 1972b) or that “people systematically violate principles of decision-making when judging probabilities, making predictions, or otherwise attempting to cope with probabilistic tasks” and they “lack the correct programs for many important judgmental tasks” (Slovic, Fischhoff & Lichtenstein 1976). On the other hand, those investigators are reminded that people could not even drive automobiles unless they could assess uncertainties fairly accurately (Edwards 1975). The ordinary person is claimed to be prone to serious and systematic error in deductive reasoning, in judging probabilities, in correcting his biases, and in many other activities. Yet, from this apparently unpromising material – indeed, from the very same students who are the typical subjects of cognitive psychologists' experiments – sufficient cadres are recruited to maintain the sophisticated institutions of modern civilisation. Earlier decades, in an era of greater optimism, may well have overestimated the natural reasoning powers of human beings. But there seems now to be a risk of underestimating them.

Type
Chapter
Information
Reasoning
Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations
, pp. 136 - 155
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, A. R. & Belnapr, N. D. (1974) Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity. Vol. 1. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. (1946) Language, truth and logic. (London: Gollancz).Google Scholar
Bergson, H. (1903) Introduction a la métaphysique. (Paris: A. Bourgeois Cahiers de la quinzaine).Google Scholar
Bernoulli, J. (1713) Ars conjectandi. Basle.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1947) Meaning and necessity. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar
Carnap, K.. (1950) Logical foundations of probability. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar
Chapman, L. J. & Chapman, J. P. (1967) “Genesis of popular but erroneous psychodiagnostic observations.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 72 (3): 193–204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chapman, L. J. & Chapman, J. P.. (1969) “Illusory correlation as an obstacle to the use of valid psychodiagnostic signs.”Journal of Abnormal Psychology 74 (3): 271–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1965) Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. J. (1970) The implications of induction. (London: Methuen).Google Scholar
Cohen, L. J. (1971) “Some remarks on Grice's views about the logical particles of natural language.” In: Pragmatics of natural language, ed. Bar-Hillel, Y.. (Dordrecht: Reidel.)Google Scholar
Cohen, L. J.. (1977a) “Can the conversationalist hypothesis be defended?Philosophical Studies 31: 81–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J.. (1977b) The probable and the provable. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J.. (1979) “On the psychology of prediction: Whose is the fallacy?Cognition 7: 385–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J..(1980b) “Some historical remarks on the Baconian conception of probability.” Journal of the History of Ideas 41: 219–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J.. (1980d) “Whose is the fallacy? A rejoinder to Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky.” Cognition 8: 89–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copi, I. M. (1954) Symbolic logic. (New York: Macmillan).Google Scholar
Daniels, N. (1979) “Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics.” Journal of Philosophy 76: 256–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daniels., N.. (1980) “On some methods of ethics and linguistics.” Philosophical Studies 37: 21–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1966) “The logical form of action sentences.” In: The logic of decision and action, ed. Rescher, N.. (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press).Google Scholar
Dawes, B. M. & Corrigan, B. (1974) “Linear models in decision making.” Psychological Bulletin 81: 95–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finetti, B. (1931) Sul significato soggettivo della probabilita. Fundamenta mathematicae 17: 298–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, , D. C. (1979) Brainstorms. (Hassocks: Harvester.)Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1978) “The justification of deduction.” In: Truth and other enigmas, ed. Dummett, M.. (London: Duckworth).Google Scholar
Edwards, W. (1975) “Comment.” Journal of the American Statistical Association 70: 291–93.Google Scholar
Einhorn, H. J. & Hogarth, R. M. (1981) “Behavioral decision theory: Processes of judgment and choice.” Annual Review of Psychology, 32: 53–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellis, B. (1979) Rational belief systems. (Oxford: Blackwell.)Google Scholar
Fischhoff, B. (1975) “Hindsight ≠ foresight: The effect of outcome knowledge on judgment under uncertainty.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 1: 288–99.Google Scholar
Goldberg, L. R. (1970) “Man versus model of man: A rationale, plus some evidence, for a method of improving on clinical inferences.” Psychological Bulletin 73(6): 422–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N. (1954) Fact, fiction, and forecast. (London: Athlone).Google Scholar
Goodman, N.. (1979) Fact, fiction, and forecast. 3rd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett).Google Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1975) “Logic and conversation.” In: The logic of grammar, ed. Davidson, D. and Harman, G.. (Encino, Calif.: Dickenson).Google Scholar
Griffin, N. (1977) Relative identity. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Haack, S. (1974) Deviant logic. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Hamblin, C. L. (1970) Fallacies. (London: Methuen).Google Scholar
Hammerton, M. (1973) “A case of radical probability estimation.” Journal of Experimental Psychology 101: 252–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hogarth, B. M. (1975) “Cognitive processes and the assessment of subjective probability distributions.” Journal of the American Statistical Association 70: 271–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1739) A treatise of human nature. (London: John Noon).Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1911) “Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft.” Logos 1: 289–341.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. (1980) “How is it reasonable to base preferences on estimates of chance?” In: Science, belief and behaviour, ed. Mellor, D. H.. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Jenkins, H. M. & Ward, W. C. (1965) “Judgment of contingency between responses and outcomes.” Psychological Monographs: General and Applied 79, whole no. 594.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Johnson-Laird, P. N., Legrenzi, P., & Legrenzi, Sonino H. (1972) “Reasoning and a sense of reality.” British Journal of Psychology 63: 395–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. N. & Wason, P. C. (1970) “A theoretical analysis of insight into a reasoning task.” Cognitive Psychology 1: 134–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. N. & Wason, P. C. (1977) “Postscript.” In: Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Science, ed. Johnson-Laird, P. N. & Wason, P. C.. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (1972a) “On the psychology of prediction.” Oregon Research Institute Research Bulletin 12, whole no. 4.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A.. (1972b) “Subjective probability: A judgment of representativeness.” Cognitive Psychology 3: 430–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A.. (1973) “On the psychology of prediction.” Psychological Review 80: 237–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (1974) “Subjective probability: A judgment of representativeness.” In: The concept of probability in psychological experiments, ed. Holstein, C. A. S. Stael. (Dordrecht: Reidel.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A.. (1979) “On the interpretation of intuitive probability: A reply to Jonathan Cohen.” Cognition 7: 409–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kocher, P. H. (1957) “Francis Bacon on the science of jurisprudence.” Journal of the History of Ideas 18: 3–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolmogorov, A. (1950) Foundations of probability. (New York: Chelsea).Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1972) “Naming and necessity.” In: Semantics of natural language, ed. Davidson, D. and Harman, G.. (Dordrecht: Reidel).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970) “Falsificationism and the methodology of scientific research programs.” In: Criticism and the growth of knowledge, ed. Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. E.. (Amsterdam: North Holland).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemmon, E. J. (1965) Beginning logic. (London: Nelson).Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973) Counterfactuals. (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Lichtenstein, S. & Slovic, P. (1973) “Response-induced reversals of preference in gambling: An extended replication in Las Vegas.” Journal of Experimental Psychology 101: 16–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lopes, L. L. (1980) “Doing the impossible: A note on induction and the experience of randomness.” Paper presented at 18th Bayesian Research Conference, Los Angeles, Calif.
Lyon, D. & Slovic, P. (1976) “Dominance of accuracy information and neglect of base rates in probability estimation.” Acta Psychologica 40: 287–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manktelow, K. I. & Evans, J. St. B. T. (1979) “Facilitation of reasoning by realism: Effect or non-effect.” British Journal of Psychology 70: 477–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mellor, D. H. (1971) The matter of chance. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Mynatt, C. B., Doherty, M. E. & Tweney, R. D. (1977) “Confirmation bias in a simulated research environment: An experimental study of scientific inference.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 29: 85–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mynatt, C. B.; Doherty, M. E. & Tweney, R. D.. (1978) “Consequences of confirmation and disconfirmation in a simulated research environment.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 30: 395–406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. (1939) “Principles of the theory of probability.” International Encyclopaedia of Unified Science, vol. 1, no. 6. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. E. & Borgida, E. (1975) “Attribution and the psychology of predictions.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 32: 932–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, R. E. & Ross, L. (1980) Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of social judgment. (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall).Google Scholar
Piaget, J. (1972) The principles of genetic epistemology. (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Popper, K R. (1959a) The logic of scientific discovery. (London: Hutchinson).Google Scholar
Popper, K R.. (1959b) “The propensity interpretation of probability.” British Journal for Philosophy of Science 10: 25–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1968) “On the rules of detachment and so-called inductive logic.” In: The problem of inductive logic, ed. Lakatos, I.. (Amsterdam: North Holland).Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1952) Methods of logic. (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O.. (1960) Word and object. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. (1931) The foundations of mathematics. (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1972) A theory of justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1944) Philosophic foundations of quantum mechanics. (Berkeley: University of California Press).Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H.. (1949) The theory of probability. (Berkeley: University of California Press.)Google Scholar
Ross, L. & Lepper, M. B. (1980) “The perseverance of beliefs: Empirical and normative considerations.” In: New directions for methodology of behavioral science: Fallible judgment in behavioral research, ed. Shweder, R. A. & Fiske, D.. (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass).Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1919) Introduction to mathematical philosophy. (London: Allen & Unwin).Google Scholar
Sampson, C. K. (1975) The form of language. (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson).Google Scholar
Simon, H. A. (1957) Models of man. (New York: John Wiley).Google Scholar
Slovic, P., Fischhoff, B. & Lichtenstein, S. (1976) “Cognitive processes and societal risk taking.” In: Cognition and social behavior, ed. Carroll, J. S. & Payne, J. W.. (Hillsdale, N. J.: Erlbaum).Google Scholar
Slovic, P.; Fischlioff, B. & Lichtenstein, S.. (1977) “Behavioral decision theory.” Annual Review of Psychology 28: 1–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommers, F. (1981) The logic of natural language. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Spinoza, B.. (1914) Opera. (Hague: Nijhoff).Google Scholar
Stich, S. P. (1975) Logical form and natural language. Philosophical Studies 28: 397–418.
Swinburne, R. C. (1964) “Falsifiability of scientific theories.” Mind 73: 434–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todhunter, I. (1949) A history of the mathematical theory of probability from the time of Pascal to that of Laplace. Reprint of 1865 edition. (New York: Chelsea).Google Scholar
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1971) ‘The belief in the “law of small numbers.”Psychological Bulletin 76: 105–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D.. (1973) “Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability.” Cognitive Psychology 5: 207–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D.. (1974) “Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases.” Science 125: 1124–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1977) “Causal thinking in judgment under uncertainty.” In: Basic problems in methodology and linguistics, ed. Butts, R. & Hintikka, J.. (Dordrecht: Reidel).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duyne, P. C. (1974) “Realism and linguistic complexity.” British Journal of Psychology 65: 59–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duyne, P. C.. (1976) “Necessity and contingency in reasoning.” Acta Psychologica 40: 85–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mises, K. (1957) Probability, statistics and truth. (London: Allen & Unwin).Google Scholar
Wagenaar, W. A. (1972) “Generation of random sequences by human subjects: A critical survey of literature.” Psychological Bulletin 77: 65–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wason, P. C. (1960) “On the failure to eliminate hypothesis in a conceptual task.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 12: 129–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wason, P. C. (1966) “Reasoning.” In: New horizons in psychology, vol. 1, ed. Foss, B.. (Hammondsworth: Penguin).Google Scholar
Wason, P. C.. (1968) “Reasoning about a rule.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 20: 273–81.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wason, P. and Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1972) Psychology of reasoning: Structure and content. (London: Ratsford).Google Scholar
Wason, P. C. & Shapiro, D. (1971) “Natural and contrived experience in a reasoning problem.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 23: 63–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×