Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-06T00:56:04.155Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Statutory Interpretation as Problem Solving

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 December 2020

Douglas Walton
Affiliation:
University of Windsor, Ontario
Fabrizio Macagno
Affiliation:
Universidade Nova de Lisboa, Portugal
Giovanni Sartor
Affiliation:
Università di Bologna
Get access

Summary

For many readers the paradigm of argumentation in a legal setting is that of the trial, an instance of the type of dialogue called the persuasion dialogue or critical discussion in the argumentation literature (van Eemeren and Grootendorst, 1992; Walton, 1999; Prakken, 2009). This setting is an adversarial one. For example, in a criminal case the prosecution’s role is not only to support its claim that the defendant committed the crime by bringing forward evidence, but also to attack the arguments of the other side, defend its own arguments against these attacks, and prove its own claim to the standard required, that of beyond reasonable doubt in the common law system. With this paradigm in mind, it is easy to jump to the generalization that legal argumentation is a kind of persuasion dialogue in which each side is trying to persuade the trier of fact to accept its view of the matter (Feteris, 1999, 171–174; Kloosterhuis, 2013).

Type
Chapter
Information
Statutory Interpretation
Pragmatics and Argumentation
, pp. 55 - 96
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Abaelardus, Petrus. 1970. Dialectica. Edited by Marie, Lambertus de Rijk, Assen, Netherlands: Van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Anderson, Bruce. 2013. “Weighing and balancing in the light of deliberation and expression.” In Legal Argumentation Theory: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives, edited by Dahlman, Christian and Feteris, Eveline, 113123. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Anderson, Terence. 1999. “On generalizations I: A preliminary exploration.” South Texas Law Review 40: 455481.Google Scholar
Anderson, Terence, and Twining, William. 1991. Analysis of Evidence: How to Do Things with Facts, Based on Wigmore’s Science of Judicial Proof. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
Atlas, Jay David. 2005. Logic, Meaning, and Conversation. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bransford, John, and Stein, Barry. 1993. The Ideal Problem Solver: A Guide to Improving Thinking, Learning, and Creativity. New York, NY: Worth Publishers.Google Scholar
Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
Carston, Robyn. 2004. “Explicature and semantics.” In Semantics: A Reader, edited by Davis, Steven and Gillon, Brendan, 817845. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chiassoni, Pierluigi. 2016. “Legal interpretation without truth.Revus: Journal for Constitutional Theory and Philosophy of Law 29: 93118.Google Scholar
Crowe, Jonathan. 2013. “The Role of Contextual Meaning in Judicial Interpretation.Federal Law Review 41(3): 417442. https://doi.org/10.22145/flr.41.3.2.Google Scholar
Damele, Giovanni. 2011. “Rhetoric and persuasive strategies in High Courts’ decisions: Some remarks on the recent decisions of the Portuguese Tribunal Constitutional and the Italian Corte Costituzionale on same-sex marriage.” In Argumentation, edited by Araszkiewicz, Michał, Myška, Matej, Smejkalová, Terezie, Šavelka, Jaromír, and Škop, Martin, 8193. Brno, Czech Republic: Masarykova UP.Google Scholar
Damele, Giovanni. 2014. “Analogia Legis and Analogia Iuris: An overview from a rhetorical perspective.” In Systematic Approaches to Argument by Analogy, edited by Ribeiro, Henrique, 243256. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Depraetere, Ilse. 2014. “Modals and lexically-regulated saturation.Journal of Pragmatics 71: 160177. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2014.08.003.Google Scholar
Długosz, Joanna. 2017. “The principle of proportionality in European Union Law as a prerequisite for penalization.Przegląd Prawniczy Uniwersytetu Im. Adama Mickiewicza 7(1): 283300.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Frans van, Eemeren, and Rob Grootendorst. 2004. A Systematic Theory of Argumentation: The Pragma-Dialectical Approach. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Eemeren, Frans van, and Grootendorst, Rob. 1992. Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Endicott, Timothy. 2000. Vagueness in Law. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farber, Daniel. 1992. “The inevitability of practical reason: Statutes, formalism, and the rule of law.Vanderbilt Law Review 45: 533560.Google Scholar
Feteris, Eveline. 1999. Fundamentals of Legal Argumentation. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Gordon, Thomas. 2010. “An overview of the Carneades Argumentation Support system.” In Dialectics, Dialogue and Argumentation. An Examination of Douglas Walton’s Theories of Reasoning and Argument, edited by Reed, Christopher and Tindale, Christopher, 145156. London, UK: College Publications.Google Scholar
Grice, Paul. 1957. “Meaning.The Philosophical Review 66(3): 377388. https://doi.org/10.2307/2182440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, Paul. 1968. “Utterer’s meaning, sentence meaning and word-meaning.Foundations of Language 4: 225242. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2727-8_2.Google Scholar
Jaszczolt, Kasia. 1999. Discourse, Beliefs and Intentions. Oxford, UK: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Jaszczolt, Kasia. 2017. “Slippery meaning and accountability.” In Pragmatics and Law, edited by Poggi, Francesca and Capone, Alessandro, 322. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.Google Scholar
Jori, Mario. 2016. “Legal pragmatics.” In Pragmatics and Law, edited by Capone, Alessandro and Poggi, Francesca, 3360. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.Google Scholar
Kissine, Mikhail. 2012. “Sentences, utterances, and speech acts.” In Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, edited by Allan, Keith and Jaszczolt, Kasia, 169190. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kloosterhuis, Harm. 2013. “The rule of law and the ideal of a critical discussion.” In Legal Argumentation Theory: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives, edited by Dahlman, Christian and Feteris, Eveline, 7183. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Kok, Eric M, Meyer, John-Jules, Prakken, Henry, and Vreeswijk, Gerard. 2010. “A formal argumentation framework for deliberation dialogues.” In Argumentation in Multi-Agent Systems. ArgMAS 2010. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol 6614, edited by McBurney, Peter, Rahwan, Iyad, and Parsons, Simon, 3148. Berlin, Heidelberg, Germany: Springer.Google Scholar
Kompa, Nikola. 2016. “The role of vagueness and context sensitivity in legal interpretation.” In Vagueness and Law: Philosophical and Legal Perspectives, edited by Keil, Geert and Poscher, Ralf, 205227. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Macagno, Fabrizio. 2017. “The logical and pragmatic structure of arguments from analogy.Logique et Analyse 60(240): 465490. https://doi.org/10.2143/LEA.240.0.3254093.Google Scholar
Macagno, Fabrizio, and Walton, Douglas. 2009. “Argument from analogy in law, the classical tradition, and recent theories.Philosophy and Rhetoric 42(2): 154182. https://doi.org/10.1353/par.0.0034.Google Scholar
Macagno, Fabrizio, and Walton, Douglas. 2017. Interpreting Straw Man Argumentation. The Pragmatics of Quotation and Reporting. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Macagno, Fabrizio, and Walton, Douglas. 2018. “Practical reasoning arguments: A modular approach.Argumentation 32(4): 519547. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-018-9450-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macagno, Fabrizio, Walton, Douglas, and Tindale, Christopher. 2014. “Analogical reasoning and semantic rules of inference.Revue Internationale de Philosophie 270(4): 419–432.Google Scholar
Manning, John. 2003. “The absurdity doctrine.Harvard Law Review 116(8): 23872486. https://doi.org/10.2307/1342768.Google Scholar
Marmor, Andrei. 2016a. “Defeasibility and pragmatic indeterminacy in law.” In Pragmatics and Law: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Capone, Alessandro and Poggi, Francesca, 1532. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.Google Scholar
Marmor, Andrei. 2016b. “Pragmatic vagueness in statutory law.” In Vagueness and Law, edited by Keil, Geert and Poscher, Ralf, 161176. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Martí, Genoveva, and Lorena, Ramírez-Ludeña. 2016. “Legal disagreements and theories of reference.” In Pragmatics and Law: Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Capone, Alessandro and Poggi, Francesca, 121139. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.Google Scholar
McBurney, Peter, Hitchcock, David, and Parsons, Simon. 2007. “The eightfold way of deliberation dialogue.International Journal of Intelligent Systems 22(1): 95132. https://doi.org/10.1002/int.v22:1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morra, Lucia. 2016. “Conversational implicatures in normative texts.” In Interdisciplinary Studies in Pragmatics, Culture and Society, edited by Capone, Alessandro and Mey, Jacob, 537562. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.Google Scholar
Murrill, Brandon. 2018. “Modes of constitutional interpretation.” Washington, DC. www.crs.gov.Google Scholar
Nunberg, Geoffrey. 1979. “The non-uniqueness of semantic solutions: Polysemy.Linguistics and Philosophy 3(2): 143184. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00126509.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poggi, Francesca. 2012. “Contextualism, but not enough. A brief note on Villa’s theory of legal interpretation.Revus. Journal for Constitutional Theory and Philosophy of Law/Revija Za Ustavno Teorijo in Filozofijo Prava, no. 17: 5565.Google Scholar
Pollock, John. 1995. Cognitive Carpentry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Poole, David, and Mackworth, Alan. 2010. Artificial Intelligence: Foundations of Computational Agents. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poscher, Ralf. 2016. “An intentionalist account of vagueness: A legal perspective.” In Vagueness and Law: Philosophical and Legal Perspectives, edited by Keil, Geert and Poscher, Ralf, 6593. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prakken, Henry. 2009. “Models of persuasion dialogue.” In Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence, edited by Simari, Guillermo and Rahwan, Iyad, 281300. Boston, MA: Springer.Google Scholar
Recanati, François. 1987. Meaning and Force: The Pragmatics of Performative Utterances. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rehnquist, William. 1975. “The notion of a living constitution.Texas Law Review 54: 693706.Google Scholar
Russell, Stuart, and Norvig, Peter. 1995. Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Sartor, Giovanni. 1995. “Defeasibility in legal reasoning.” In Informatics and the Foundations of Legal Reasoning, edited by Bankowsk, Zenon, White, Ian, and Hahn, Ulrike, 119157. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Sartor, Giovanni. 2018. “Defeasibility in law.” In Handbook of Legal Reasoning and Argumentation, edited by Bongiovanni, Giorgio, Postema, Gerald, Rotolo, Antonino, Sartor, Giovanni, Valentini, Chiara, and Walton, Douglas, 315364. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Sbisà, Marina. 2017. “Implicitness in normative texts.” In Pragmatics and Law: Practical and Theoretical Perspectives, edited by Poggi, Francesca and Capone, Alessandro, 2342. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.Google Scholar
Schauer, Frederick. 2013. “Why precedent in law (and elsewhere) is not totally (or even substantially) about analogy.” In Legal Argumentation Theory: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives, edited by Dahlman, Christian and Feteris, Eveline, 4556. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
Schiffer, Stephen. 2016. “Philosophical and jurisprudential issues of vagueness.” In Vagueness and Law: Philosophical and Legal Perspectives, edited by Keil, Geert and Poscher, Ralf, 2348. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schum, David. 1994. The Evidential Foundations of Probabilistic Reasoning. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Schum, David, and Tillers, Peter. 1991. “Marshalling evidence for adversary litigation.Cardozo Law Review 13(1): 657704.Google Scholar
Soames, Scott. 2009. “Interpreting legal texts: What is, and what is not, special about the law.” In Philosophical Essays, 1:403–424. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Solum, Lawrence. 2011. “What is originalism? The evolution of contemporary originalist theory.” In The Challenge of Originalism: Essays in Constitutional Theory, edited by Huscroft, Grant and Miller, Bradley, 1241. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, Dan, and Wilson, Deirdre. 1995. Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
Summers, Robert. 1971. “The technique element in law.California Law Review 59(3): 733751. https://doi.org/10.15779/Z38KX9V.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarello, Giovanni. 1980. L’Interpretazione della Legge. Milano, Italy: Giuffrè.Google Scholar
Twining, William, and Miers, David. 2010. How to Do Things with Rules: A Primer of Interpretation. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, Douglas. 1999. “Dialectical relevance in persuasion dialogue.Informal Logic 19: 119143. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v19i2.2323.Google Scholar
Walton, Douglas. 2006. Fundamentals of Critical Argumentation. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Walton, Douglas. 2015. Goal-Based Reasoning for Argumentation. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Walton, Douglas, Reed, Christopher, and Macagno, Fabrizio. 2008. Argumentation Schemes. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Walton, Douglas, and Toniolo, Alice. 2016. “Deliberation, practical reasoning and problem-solving.” In Argumentation, Objectivity, and Bias: Proceedings of the 11th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 18–21, 2016, edited by Bondy, Pat and Benacquista, Laura, 119. Windsor, ON: OSSA.Google Scholar
Walton, Douglas, Toniolo, Alice, and Norman, Timothy. 2016. “Towards a richer model of deliberation dialogue: Closure problem and change of circumstances.Argument & Computation 7(2–3): 155173. https://doi.org/10.3233/AAC-160009.Google Scholar
Walton, Richard, and Robert, McKersie. 1966. “Behavioral dilemmas in mixed‐motive decision making.Behavioral Science 11(5): 370384. https://doi.org/10.1002/bs.3830110506.Google Scholar
Wigmore, John Henry. 1931. The Principles of Judicial Proof, 2nd Ed. Boston, MA: Little, Brown & Company.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre. 1998. “Discourse, coherence and relevance: A reply to Rachel Giora.” Journal of Pragmatics 29(1): 5774. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0378-2166(97)00012-X.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre, and Sperber, Dan. 2012. Meaning and Relevance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wooldridge, Michael. 2009. An Introduction to Multiagent Systems. Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Zipf, George Kingsley. 1949. Human Behavior and the Principle of Least Effort: An Introduction to Human Ecology. Cambridge, UK: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar

Cases Cited

Heydon’s Case. 1984 EWHC Exch J36.

Buckoke v. Greater London Council [1970] 2 All ER 193.

Google Spain SL and Google Inc. v. Agencia Española de Protección de Datos (AEPD) and Mario Costeja González 2014 ECLI:EU:C:2014:317.

Bodil Lindqvist v Åklagarkammaren i Jönköping 2003 ECLI:EU:C:2003:596

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×