Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-16T17:22:27.022Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2020

Kostas Kampourakis
Affiliation:
University of Geneva
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

On the evidence for evolution: Coyne, J. A. (2009). Why Evolution is True. Oxford: Oxford University Press; Dawkins, R. (2009). The Greatest Show on Earth: The Evidence for Evolution. London: Bantam Press; Prothero, D. R. (2017). Evolution: What the Fossils Say and Why it Matters (2nd edition). New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
“Nothing in biology makes sense …”: Dobzhansky, T. (1973). Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher 35(3): 125129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Creationism and intelligent design: Numbers, R. L. (2006). The Creationists: From Scientific Creationism to Intelligent Design. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press; Pigliucci, M. (2002). Denying Evolution: Creationism, Scientism, and the Nature of Science. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.Google Scholar
Blind watchmaker and tinkerer metaphors: Dawkins, R. (2006 [1986]). The Blind Watchmaker. London: Penguin Books; Jacob, F. (1977). Evolution and tinkering. Science 196(4295): 1161–1166.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

“Make respondents feel uncomfortable”: Rughinis, C. (2011). A lucky answer to a fair question: Conceptual, methodological, and moral implications of including items on human evolution in scientific literacy surveys. Science Communication 33: 501532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
“Forced to choose”: Elsdon-Baker, F. (2015). Creating creationists: The influence of “issues framing” on our understanding of public perceptions of clash narratives between evolutionary science and belief. Public Understanding of Science 24: 422439.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Articles on the acceptance of evolution in Science: Miller, J. D., Scott, E. C., and Okamoto, S. (2006). Public acceptance of evolution. Science 313(5788): 765766; Hameed, S. (2008). Bracing for Islamic creationism. Science 322: 1637.Google Scholar
On the distinction between believe in and believe about: McCain, K. and Kampourakis, K. (2018). Which question do polls about evolution and belief really ask, and why does it matter? Public Understanding of Science 27(1): 210.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
On evolution and design: Ruse, M. (2004). Darwin and Design: Does Evolution Have a Purpose? Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Paley and Hume: Paley, W. (2006 [1802]). Natural Theology or Evidence of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity, Collected from the Appearances of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press; Hume, D. (1993 [1779/1777]). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion and Natural History of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
The studies discussed are Evans, M. E. (2001). Cognitive and contextual factors in the emergence of diverse belief systems: Creation versus evolution. Cognitive Psychology 42: 217266; Kelemen, D. (2003). British and American children’s preferences for teleo-functional explanations of the natural world. Cognition 88: 201–221; Kelemen, D. (2004). Are children “intuitive theists”? Reasoning about purpose and design in nature. Psychological Science 15(5): 295–301; Kelemen, D. and DiYanni, C. (2005). Intuitions about origins: Purpose and intelligent design in children’s reasoning about nature. Journal of Cognition and Development 6(1): 3–31.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
On the blind watchmaker: Dawkins, R. (2006 [1986]). The Blind Watchmaker. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Studies on what scientists think about religion: Ecklund, E. H. (2010). Science vs. Religion: What Scientists Really Think. Oxford: Oxford University Press; Ecklund, E. H., Johnson, D. R., Vaidyanathan, B., Matthews, K. R. W., Lewis S. W., Thomson, Jr. R. A., and Di, D. (2019). Secularity and Science: What Scientists Around the World Really Think About Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
On the views of Dawkins, Gould, and Conway Morris: Dawkins, R. (2006). The God Delusion. London: Bantam Press; Conway Morris, S. (2003). Life’s Solution: Inevitable Humans in a Lonely Universe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Gould, S. J. (1999). Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the Fullness of Life. New York: Ballantine Books.Google Scholar
On knowledge and belief: Audi, R. (2011). Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge (3rd ed.). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
On concepts and conceptual change: Arabatzis, T. (2019). What are scientific concepts? In McCain, K. and Kampourakis, K. (Eds.) What Is Scientific Knowledge? An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology of Science. New York: Routledge, pp. 8599; Vosniadou, S. (Ed.) (2013). International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
“Interesting study as an example”: Goldberg, R. F. and Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2009). Developmental “roots” in mature biological knowledge. Psychological Science 20(4): 480487.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
The studies on teleology discussed are reported in: Kelemen, D. (1999). The scope of teleological thinking in preschool children. Cognition 70: 241272; Keil, F. C. (1992). The origins of an autonomous biology. In M. R. Gunnar and M. Maratsos (Eds.) Modularity and Constraints in Language and Cognition: Minnesota Symposium on Child Psychology, Vol. 25. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 103–138; Kelemen, D. (1999). Why are rocks pointy? Children’s preference for teleological explanations of the natural world. Developmental Psychology 35: 1440–1452; Greif, M., Kemler-Nelson, D., Keil, F. C., and Guiterrez, F. (2006). What do children want to know about animals and artifacts? Domain-specific requests for information. Psychological Science 17(6): 455–459.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
The studies on essentialism discussed are reported in: Gelman, S. A. (2003). The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press; Asher, Y. M. and Kemler-Nelson, D. G. (2008). Was it designed to do that? Children’s focus on intended function in their conceptualization of artifacts. Cognition 106: 474–483; Keil, F. C. (1989). Concepts, Kinds and Cognitive Development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
On the essences of artifacts and organisms: Bloom, P. (2004). Descartes’ Baby: How the Science of Child Development Explains What Makes Us Human. New York: Basic Books; Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary essentialism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57(2): 425–448.Google Scholar
On teleology and essentialism as obstacles to understanding evolution: Kelemen, D. (2012). Teleological minds: How natural intuitions about agency and purpose influence learning about evolution. In Rosengren, K., Brem, S., Evans, E. M., and Sinatra, G. M. (Eds.) Evolution Challenges: Integrating Research and Practice in Teaching and Learning about Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 6692; Gelman, S. A. and Rhodes, M. (2012). “Two-thousand years of stasis”: How psychological essentialism impedes evolutionary understanding. In K. Rosengren, S. Brem, E. M. Evans, and G. M. Sinatra (Eds.) Evolution Challenges: Integrating Research and Practice in Teaching and Learning about Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
On the account of teleology followed, see: Lennox, J. G. and Kampourakis, K. (2013). Biological teleology: The need for history. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 421454; Kampourakis, K. (2020). Students’ “teleological misconceptions” in evolution education: Why the underlying design stance, not teleology per se, is the problem. Evolution: Education and Outreach, 13(1). DOI: 10.1186/s12052-019-0116-z.Google Scholar
Bowler, P. J. (2013). Darwin Deleted: Imagining a World Without Darwin. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Endersby, J. (2009). Charles Darwin: On the Origin of Species. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hodge, J. and Radick, G. (Eds.) (2009). The Cambridge Companion to Darwin (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kohn, D. (Ed.) (1985). The Darwinian Heritage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Numbers, R. N. & Kampourakis, K. (Eds.) (2015). Newton's Apple and Other Myths about Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ospovat, D. (1981). The Development of Darwin’s Theory: Natural History, Natural Theology and Natural Selection, 1838–1859. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. and Richards, R. J. (Eds.) (2009). The Cambridge Companion to the “Origin of Species.” Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Secord, J. A. (2000). Victorian Sensation: The Extraordinary Publication, Reception, and Secret Authorship of Vestiges on Natural History of Creation. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Spencer, N. (2009). Darwin and God. London: SPCK.Google Scholar
On the Huxley–Wilberforce debate: Lucas, J. R. (1979). Wilberforce and Huxley: A legendary encounter. The Historical Journal 22(2): 313330; Brooke, J. H. (2001). The Wilberforce–Huxley debate: Why did it happen? Science & Christian Belief 13(2): 127–141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, ’s writings, as well as the reviews of the Origin discussed, are available at: http://darwin-online.org.uk. Darwin’s correspondence is available at www.darwinproject.ac.uk.Google Scholar
On the human genome and design: Avise, J. C. (2010). Inside the Human Genome: A Case for Non-Intelligent Design. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 108112.Google Scholar
On microbial evolution and the universal common ancestor: Margulis, L. (1998). Symbiotic Planet: A New Look at Evolution. London: Basic Books; Margulis, L. and Sagan, D. (2002). Acquiring Genomes: A Theory of the Origins of Species. New York: Basic Books; Koonin, E. V. (2011). The Logic of Chance: The Nature and Origin of Biological Evolution. Upper Saddle River, NJ: FT Press; Doolittle, W. F. and Brunet, T. D. (2016). What is the tree of life? PLoS Genetics 12(4): e1005912; Koonin, E. V. and Novozhilov, A. S. (2017). Origin and evolution of the universal genetic code. Annual Review of Genetics 51: 45–62.Google Scholar
For a comprehensive discussion of how evolutionary trees are constructed and read, see: Baum, D. and Smith, S. (2013). Tree Thinking: An Introduction to Phylogenetic Biology. Greenwood Village, CO: Roberts and Company Publishers.Google Scholar
On digits and insect appendages: Hall, B. K. (2003). Descent with modification: The unity underlying homology and homoplasy as seen through an analysis of development and evolution. Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 78: 409433; Wagner, G. (2007). The developmental genetics of homology. Nature Reviews Genetics 8: 473–479.Google Scholar
On homologies and homoplasies: Carroll, S. B. (2005). Endless Forms Most Beautiful: The New Science of Evo-Devo. New York: W.W. Norton, pp. 6172; McGhee, G. R. (2011). Convergent Evolution: Limited Forms Most Beautiful. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
On deep homology: Shubin, N., Tabin, C., and Carroll, S. (2009). Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary novelty. Nature 457: 818823.Google Scholar
On the origin of multicellularity: Knoll, A. H. (2011). The multiple origins of complex multicellularity. Annual Review of Earth and Planetary Sciences 39: 217239; Libby, E., Conlin, P. L., Kerr, B., & Ratcliff, W. C. (2016). Stabilizing multicellularity through ratcheting. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 371(1701): 20150444.Google Scholar
On whales and bats: Thewissen, J. G., Cohn, M. J., Stevens, L. S., Bajpai, S., Heyning, J., and Horton, W. E. Jr. (2006). Developmental basis for hind-limb loss in dolphins and origin of the cetacean body plan. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 103(22): 84148418; Sears, K. E., Behringer, R. R., Rasweiler, J. J., and Niswander, L. A. (2006). Development of bat flight: morphologic and molecular evolution of bat wing digits. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 103(17): 6581–6586.Google Scholar
On changes in development that affect evolution: Arthur, W. (2011). Evolution: A Developmental Approach. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
On the inversion of the dorso-ventral axis of arthropods: De Robertis, E. M. (2008). Evo-devo: Variations on ancestral themes. Cell 132: 185195.Google Scholar
On adaptation, see: Sober, E. (1993 [1984]). The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press; Brandon, R. N. (1990). Adaptation and Environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; Reeve, H. K. and Sherman, P. W. (1993). Adaptation and the goals of evolutionary research. Quarterly Review of Biology 68(1): 1–32; Mayr, E. (2002). What Evolution Is. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson; Gould, S. J. and Vrba, E. S. (1982). Exaptation: A missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8(1): 4–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
On selection for and selection of, and the toy example, see: Sober, E. (1993 [1984]). The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
On selection for and against, see: Depew, D. (2013). Conceptual change and the rhetoric of evolutionary theory: “Force talk” as a case study and challenge for science pedagogy. In Kampourakis, K. (Ed.) The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 121144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
On stochastic processes: Millstein, R. L., Skipper, R. A., and Dietrich, M. R. (2009). (Mis)interpreting mathematical models: Drift as a physical process. Philosophy & Theory in Biology 1: e002, DOI:10.3998/ptb.6959004.0001.002; Skipper, R. A. (2006). Stochastic evolutionary dynamics: Drift versus draft. Philosophy of Science 73(5): 655–665; Nei, M. (2013). Mutation-Driven Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Picket fence example: McShea, D. W. and Brandon, R. N. (2010). Biology’s First Law: The Tendency for Diversity and Complexity to Increase in Evolutionary Systems. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
On evolutionary contingency: Gould, S. J. (2000 [1989]). Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History. London: Vintage; Kampourakis, K. (2018). Turning Points: How Critical Events Have Driven Evolution, Life and Development. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books; Losos, J. (2017). Improbable Destinies: Fate, Chance and the Future of Evolution. New York: Riverhead Books.Google Scholar
On adaptive radiation: Losos, J. B. (2010). A tale of two radiations: Similarities and differences in the evolutionary diversification of Darwin’s finches and Greater Antillean Anolis lizards. In Grant, P. R. and Grant, B. R. (Eds.) In Search of the Causes of Evolution: From Field Observations to Mechanisms. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 309331.Google Scholar
On evo-devo and speciation: Minelli, A. and Fusco, G. (2012). On the evolutionary developmental biology of speciation. Evolutionary Biology 39: 242254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
On species selection: Jablonski, D. (2008). Species selection: Theory and data. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution and Systematics 39: 501524.Google Scholar
On the K–Pg extinction: Cleland, C. E. (2002). Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science. Philosophy of Science 69: 474496; Cleland, C. E. (2011). Prediction and explanation in historical natural science. British Journal of Philosophy of Science 62: 551–582; Cleland, C. (2020). Is it possible to scientifically reconstruct the history of life on Earth? The biological sciences and deep time. In K. Kampourakis and T. Uller (Eds.) Philosophy of Science for Biologists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
On the evidence that people can be religious and accept science: Ecklund, E. H. and Scheitle, C. P. (2017). Religion vs. Science: What Religious People Really Think. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
On the arguments of antievolutionists: Miller, K. R. (2009). Only a Theory: Evolution and the Battle for America’s Soul. New York: Penguin Books; Pennock, R. T. (1999). The Tower of Babel: The Evidence Against the New Creationism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
On nature of science: Kampourakis, K. and McCain, K. (2020). Uncertainty: How it Makes Science Advance. New York: Oxford University Press; Firestein, S. (2015). Failure: Why Science is So Successful. New York: Oxford University Press; Firestein, S. (2012). Ignorance: How It Drives Science. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
On scientific understanding: De Regt, H. (2017). Understanding Scientific Understanding. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Virtues of a good theory: McMullin, E. (2008). The virtues of a good theory. In Psillos, S. and Curd, M. (Eds.) The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge, pp. 498508.Google Scholar
On Tiktaalik: Shubin, N. (2008). Your Inner Fish: The Amazing Discovery of our 375-Million-Year-Old Ancestor. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
On scientism: Haack, S. (2017). Scientism and Its Discontents. n.p.: Rounded Globe; Boudry, M. and Pigliucci, M. (Eds.) (2018). Science Unlimited? The Challenges of Scientism. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press; Rosenberg, A. (2011). The Atheist’s Guide to Reality: Enjoying Life without Illusions. New York: W.W. Norton; Dawkins, R. (2006). The God Delusion. London: Bantam Press; Dennett, D. (2006). Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Viking; Coyne, J. (2015). Faith vs. Fact: Why Science and Religion are Incompatible. New York: Viking, pp. 202–204.Google Scholar
On the ontological argument: Plantinga, A. (1967). God and Other Minds. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, quoted in Oppy, G., Ontological arguments. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (spring 2019 edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/ontological-arguments.Google Scholar
Effect of prayer on recovery: Benson, H., Dusek, J. A., Sherwood, J. B., et al. (2006). Study of the Therapeutic Effects of Intercessory Prayer (STEP) in cardiac bypass patients: A multicenter randomized trial of uncertainty and certainty of receiving intercessory prayer. American Heart Journal 151(4): 934942.Google Scholar
On metaphysical and methodological naturalism: Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific Perspectivism. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Quotations are from: Ruse, M. (2001). Can a Darwinian be a Christian? The Relationship between Science and Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 217; Kitcher, P. (2007). Living with Darwin. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 165–166.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×