Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-tj2md Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T11:50:00.962Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

25 - Are anthropic arguments, involving multiverses and beyond, legitimate?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 July 2014

William R. Stoeger S. J.
Affiliation:
University of Arizona
Bernard Carr
Affiliation:
Queen Mary University of London
Get access

Summary

Introduction

Though there has been much discussion of the Anthropic Principle (AP) over the last 35 years or so, it is still a very tantalizing and controversial subject, on the boundary between scientific cosmology and philosophy. As new scenarios and theories emerge for describing and explaining the origin of our observable universe, AP considerations inevitably surface. So, a critical review of the meaning and status of the AP — as well as of the directions anthropic arguments are now taking, their legitimacy and the fundamental philosophical issues involved — is perhaps warranted.

The anthropic idea was first introduced in 1961 by Robert Dicke, who noted the comparability of several very large numbers when fundamental physical constants are combined, and suggested that this might be connected with the conditions necessary for the presence of observers [1]. A decade later, Barry Collins and Stephen Hawking, realizing that the initial conditions for our universe seemed to be very special, suggested the following: ‘The fact that we have observed the universe to be isotropic is therefore only a consequence of our own existence’ [2]. One way of explaining this, they speculated, would be to have an ‘infinite set of universes with all possible initial conditions’ — thus anticipating the way many cosmologists now interpret the AP.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] R. H., Dicke. Dirac's cosmology and Mach's principle. Nature, 192 (1961), 440.Google Scholar
[2] C. B., Collins and S. W., Hawking. Why is the universe isotropic?Astrophys. J. 180 (1973), 317.Google Scholar
[3] B., Carter. Large number coincidences and the anthropic principle in cosmology. In Confrontation of Cosmological Theory with Astronomical Data, ed. M. S., Longair (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1974), pp. 291–298.Google Scholar
[4] B., Carter. The anthropic principle and its implications for biological evolution. Phil. Trans. Roy. Soc. Lond. A 310 (1983), 347.Google Scholar
[5] E., McMullin. Indifference principle and anthropic principle in cosmology. Studies Hist. Phil. Sci. 24 (1993), 359.Google Scholar
[6] J. D., Barrow and F. J., Tipler. The Cosmological Anthropic Principle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
[7] G. F. R., Ellis, U., Kirchner and W. R., Stoeger. Multiverses and physical cosmology. Mon. Not. Roy. Astron. Soc. 347 (2003), 921 [astro-ph/0305292v3].Google Scholar
[8] W. R., Stoeger, G. F. R., Ellis and U., Kirchner. Multiverses and cosmology: Philosophical issues (2004) [astro-ph/0407329v2].Google Scholar
[9] A., Linde. Chaotic inflation. Phys. Lett. B 129 (1983), 177.Google Scholar
[10] A., Linde. Particle Physics and Inflationary Cosmology (Chur: Harwood Academic Publishers, 1990).Google Scholar
[11] A., Linde. Inflation, quantum cosmology and the anthropic principle. In Science and Ultimate Reality, eds. J. D., Barrow, P. C. W., Davies and C. L., Harper (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 426–458 [hep-th/0211048].Google Scholar
[12] S., Weinberg. The cosmological constant problem. In Sources and Detection of Dark Matter and Dark Energy in the Universe, ed. D., Cline (Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2001) [astro-ph/0005265].Google Scholar
[13] S., Weinberg. A priori probability distribution of the cosmological constant. Phys. Rev. D 61 (2000), 103505 [astro-ph/0002387].Google Scholar
[14] J., Garriga and A., Vilenkin. Many worlds in one. Phys. Rev. D 64 (2001), 043511.Google Scholar
[15] J., Garriga and A., Vilenkin. A prescription for probabilities in eternal inflation. Phys. Rev. D 64 (2001), 0235074 [gr-qc/0102090].Google Scholar
[16] J., Garriga and A., Vilenkin. Testable anthropic predictions for dark energy. Phys. Rev. D 67 (2003), 043503 [astro-ph/0210358].Google Scholar
[17] S., Kachru, R., Kallosh, A., Linde and S. P., Trivedi. de Sitter vacua in string theory. Phys. Rev. D 68 (2003), 046005.Google Scholar
[18] L., Susskind. This volume (2007) [hep-th/03021219].
[19] D., Freivogel and L., Susskind. Framework for the string theory landscape. Phys. Rev. D 70 (2004), 126007.Google Scholar
[20] B., Freivogel, M., Kelban, M. R., Martinez and L., Susskind. Observational consequences of a landscape. JHEP, 0603 (2006), 039 [hep-th/0505232].Google Scholar
[21] L., Smolin. The Life of the Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
[22] M., Tegmark. Parallel Universes, Sci. Am. 288 (5) (May 2003), 30.Google Scholar
[23] C. S., Peirce. In Collected Papers, Vols. 1–6, eds. C., Hartstone and P., Weiss (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 19311935), vol. 1, para. 65; vol. 5, para. 188.Google Scholar
[24] C. S., Peirce. In Collected Papers, Vols. 7 & 8, ed. A., Burks (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1958), vol. 7, paras 202–207; 218–222.Google Scholar
[25] E., McMullin. The Inference that Makes Science (Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 1992), p. 112.Google Scholar
[26] E., McMullin. Is philosophy relevant to cosmology?Am. Phil. Quart. 18 (1981), 177–189. Reprinted in Physical Cosmology and Philosophy, ed. J. Leslie (New York: Macmillan, 1990), pp. 29–50.Google Scholar
[27] E., McMullin. Truth and explanatory success. In Proc. Am. Cath. Phil. Assoc. 59 (1985), 206.Google Scholar
[28] E., McMullin. Models of scientific inference. CTNS Bull. 8 (2) (1988), 1–14.Google Scholar
[29] P., Allen. A Philosophical Framework within the Science-Theology Dialogue: A Critical Reflection on the Work of E. McMullin. Ph.D. dissertation, St. Paul University, Ottawa, 2001, p. 113.Google Scholar
[30] A., Aguirre. The cold big-bang cosmology as a counter-example to several anthropic arguments. Phys. Rev. D 64 (2001), 083508 (astro-ph/0106143).Google Scholar
[31] C. W., Misner. The isotropy of the universe. Astrophys. J. 151 (1968), 431.Google Scholar
[32] R., Penrose. Difficulties with inflationary cosmology. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 571 (1989), 249.Google Scholar
[33] G. F. R., Ellis, P., McEwan, W. R., Stoeger and P., Dunsby. Causality in inflationary universes with positive spatial curvature. Gen. Rel. Grav. 34 (2002), 1461.Google Scholar
[34] W. R., Stoeger. Describing God's action in the world in light of scientific knowledge of reality. In Chaos and Complexity: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action, eds. R. J., Russell, N., Murphy and A. R., Peacocke (Rome: Vatican Observatory Publications and the Center for Theology and the Natural Science, 1995), pp. 239–261.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×