Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-05T11:18:43.960Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

8 - Liberalism and the best-judge principle

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 January 2010

Robert E. Goodin
Affiliation:
Australian National University, Canberra
Get access

Summary

Utilitarianism, in its various forms, is an essentially preference-respecting, want-regarding morality. In its insistent refusal to brook any perfectionist notion of The Good which is good independently of anyone ever thinking it to be good, utilitarianism just echoes the more general Enlightenment liberalism from which it sprang. Arguably the defining feature of modern liberalism is its value-neutrality, its agnosticism as regards matters of ultimate personal value. In liberalism more generally, as in utilitarianism more narrowly, each individual is deemed to be the “best” (indeed, ultimately the “only true”) judge of his own interests.

That claim can be construed in various different ways, however, depending on whether we talk about what people actually do or sometime will or counterfactually would want. Therein lies the core of the controversy between liberal utilitarianism and its liberallibertarian cousins. Libertarianism is a radically antipaternalistic doctrine, taking whatever preferences people presently express as absolutely veridical. At root, utilitarianism is equally respectful of people's preferences. Utilitarians, however, are more sensitive to nuances within people's preferences and are more sensitive, in consequence, to possibilities for finding some warrant in people's own preferences for overriding some of the preferences they presently express.

What is at dispute between interventionist utilitarians and laissezfaire libertarians is, thus, merely the sense in which people ought to be said to be the best judges of their own interests. In this chapter, I identify four versions of the best-judge argument.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×