Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 November 2012
Introduction
The Edgeworth Box is an economic model with which all economists are familiar. It began life in 1881, underwent substantial development over the next decades, and continues in use today: a modern version is shown in Figure 3.1. It is a small-scale, manipulable, diagrammatic object – undoubtedly a model – made to represent the exchange relations between two individuals. It introduced important new conceptual materials into economics and has functioned primarily as a device for theorizing with. The form, the content, and the history of this model can all be taken as exemplary both for the development of modelling in economics and for the movement to make economics a mathematical science. These late-nineteenth-century developments of modelling and mathematization are intimately linked in the discipline, though it is not clear exactly how, nor why it matters.
The pioneers who introduced mathematics into economics in the late nineteenth century argued that it would make economics more scientific, because economic ideas expressed in mathematics are expressed more exactly, and reasoned about more rigorously, than when expressed in words. These claims are also constitutive of what is involved in the activity of modelling, for, as I argued in Chapter 1, model-making gives form to ideas about the world and in the process gives formal rules to reason with. Yet, mathematization and model-making are not the same move: all models require a language of representation, but these need not be mathematical ones. The model of economic man was developed (as we shall see in Chapter 4) primarily in verbal terms, and each new version formed a specific portrait of a model man to argue with. Analogical models are sometimes found produced in the original language of the analogy rather than in mathematical descriptions of them, such as Fisher’s mechanical balance or the Newlyn-Phillips hydraulic machine (both found in Chapter 5), and these necessarily obey the language rules of those analogical objects and fields. And while it is fair to say that, historically considered, the mathematical languages became preeminent in model-making, to treat this development merely as a matter of language choice not only misses how and why modelling relates to mathematization in economics. It also risks seriously underestimating what was involved in modelling as a significant development in the practical reasoning modes of economics. So there are cognitive issues about these historical changes in the way economics is expressed that need to be seriously considered and clarified.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.