Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-wq2xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T20:27:03.669Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justifying the Jury: Reconciling Justice, Equality, and Democracy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 February 2018

MELISSA SCHWARTZBERG*
Affiliation:
New York University
*
Melissa Schwartzberg is the Silver Professor of Politics, New York University, 19 W. 4th Street, 2nd Floor, New York, New York10012 (ms268@nyu.edu).

Abstract

The jury is a paradigmatic example of a democratic institution that may be justified strictly on instrumental and epistemic grounds: its ability to yield just outcomes. Yet why should we have confidence in its ability? The jury's reliability derives from the jurors’ status as local experts (hierarchical equality), as well as near-universal eligibility and selection by lot (horizontal equality): This dual egalitarianism is a condition of the jury's epistemic value. Yet ordinary citizens thereby acquire an interest in epistemic respect or recognition of their presumptively equal competence to judge. The instrumental value of the jury and intrinsic (respect-based) value of jury service may thus be reconciled; although trade-offs between just verdicts and respectful treatment are possible, the jury's ability to attain just verdicts may be improved by reforms generated by concerns about respectful treatment of jurors. This framework sheds light on the justification of democratic institutions more generally.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful for the financial support and educational opportunities provided by the Andrew W. Mellon “New Directions” Fellowship, undertaken at New York University School of Law, and the Laurance S. Rockefeller Visiting Faculty Fellowship at University Center for Human Values at Princeton University. I gratefully acknowledge comments from Kevin Elliott, Jeffrey Lenowitz, Bernard Manin, Ryan Pevnick, Susanna Rinard, Anna Stilz, and Daniel Viehoff and from audiences at the Oxford Political Thought Conference, the Emory University Department of Political Science, Fordham Law School, and the LSR Fellows’ seminar at Princeton. An earlier and different version of this paper, focusing on the civil jury, was presented at Harvard Law School; Washington University in St. Louis; University of California—Berkeley; CUNY Graduate Center; Tulane Law School; the University of Chicago; the Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales; and the New York University School of Law. I appreciate comments from audiences and discussants that clarified my argument and that led me to abandon that paper's framework in favor of the one adopted here. I am also grateful for the advice of APSR political theory editor Leigh Jenco and the anonymous reviewers.

References

REFERENCES

Alexander, Michelle. 2010. The New Jim Crow. New York: The New Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 1999. “What Is the Point of Equality?Ethics 109: 287336.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2012. “Epistemic Justice as a Virtue of Social Institutions.” Social Epistemology 26 (2): 163–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2004. “Democracy Is Not Intrinsically Just.” In Justice and Democracy, eds. Dowding, Keith, Goodin, Robert E., and Pateman, Carole. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bates, Robert, and Lien, Donald. 1985. “A Note on Taxation, Development and Representative Government.” Politics and Society 41 (1): 5370.Google Scholar
Brennan, Jason. 2016. Against Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Carter, Ian. 2011. “Respect and the Basis of Equality.” Ethics 121 (3): 538–71.Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2008. Constitution of Equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2009. “Debate: Estlund on Democratic Authority.” Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (2): 228–40.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua. 1986. “An Epistemic Conception of Democracy.” Ethics 97 (2): 638.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L. 1977. “Two Kinds of Respect.” Ethics 88 (1): 3649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewey, John. 1991. The Later Works: 1925–1953, vol. 11. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Donovan, James M. 2010. Juries and the Transformation of Criminal Justice in France in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1986. “The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory.” In Foundations of Social Choice Theory, eds. Elster, Jon and Hyllund, Aanund. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Engel, Steven A. 2000. “The Public's Vicinage Right: A Constitutional Argument.” 75 N.Y.U.L. Rev. 6, 1658–719.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2013. “Epistemic Justice as a Condition of Political Freedom?Synthese 190 (7): 1317–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gowder, Paul. 2016. Rule of Law in the Real World. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guerrero, Alexander. 2014. “Against Elections: The Lottocratic Alternative.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (2): 135–78.Google Scholar
Hay, Douglas. 1988. “The Class Composition of the Palladium of Liberty: Trial Jurors in the Eighteenth Century.” In Twelve Good Men and True, eds. Cockburn, J. S. and Green, Thomas A.. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 305–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hersch, Joni and Kip Viscusi, W.. 2004. “Punitive Damages: How Judges and Juries Perform.” Journal of Legal Studies 33 (1) 1–36.Google Scholar
Hirst, Derek. 1975. The Representative of the People? Voters and Voting in England under the Early Stuarts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kalt, Brian. 2003. “The Exclusion of Felons from Jury Service.” American University Law Rev 53: 65–189.Google Scholar
Kuskowski, Ada-Maria. 2013. “The Development of Written Custom in England and in France: A Comparative Perspective.” In Law, Justice, and Governance: New Views on Medieval English Constitutionalism, ed. Kaeuper, Richard. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Landemore, Hélène. 2013. Democratic Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Langbein, John H. 2003. The Origins of Adversary Criminal Trial. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levi, Margaret. 1988. Of Rule and Revenue. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Manin, Bernard. 1997. Principles of Representative Government. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Masschaele, James. 2008. Jury, State, and Society in Medieval England. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
North, Douglass, and Paul Thomas, Robert. 1973. The Rise of the Western World: A New Economic History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2009. “The Capabilities of People with Cognitive Disabilities.” Metaphilosophy 40: 34.Google Scholar
Oldham, James. 1983. “The Origins of the Special Jury.” The University of Chicago Law Review 50 (1): 137221.Google Scholar
Peter, Fabienne. 2008. “Pure Epistemic Proceduralism.” Episteme 5 (1): 3355.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2001. The Seeley Lectures: Value, Respect, and Attachment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Satz, Debra. 2007. “Equality, Adequacy, and Education for Citizenship.” Ethics 177, 623–48.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 2010. Equality and Tradition: Questions of Value in Moral and Political Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schlosser, Ralf W., Baladin, Susan, Hemsley, Bronwyn, Iacono, Teresa, Probst, Paul and von Tetzchner, Stephen. 2014. “Facilitated Communication and Authorship: A Systematic Review.” Augmentative and Alternative Communication 30 (4): 359–68.Google Scholar
Schwartzberg, Melissa. 2014. Counting the Many: The Origins and Limits of Supermajority Rule. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schwartzberg, Melissa. 2015. “Epistemic Democracy and Its Challenges.” Annual Review of Political Science 18: 187203.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999. “Democracy as a Universal Value.” Journal of Democracy 10 (3): 317.Google Scholar
Stasavage, David. 2011. States of Credit: Size, Power, and the Development of European Polities. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stone, Peter. 2011. Luck of the Draw. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strayer, Joseph R., and Taylor, Charles H.. 1939. Studies in Early French Taxation. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1999. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar