Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T21:42:27.272Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Marketplace of Ideas and the Agora: Herodotus on the Power of Isegoria

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2022

LINDSAY MAHON RATHNAM*
Affiliation:
Duke Kunshan University, China
*
Lindsay Mahon Rathnam, Assistant Professor of Political Science, Department of Social Sciences, Duke Kunshan University, China, lindsay.mahon@dukekunshan.edu.cn.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Popular discourse about freedom of speech tends to default to the metaphor of the marketplace of ideas, notwithstanding empirical evidence undermining this concept. Its persistence illustrates the profound attachment freedom of speech inspires, despite the difficulty of justifying it in epistemic terms. I suggest that the ancient Greek historian Herodotus offers a compelling alternative to the marketplace metaphor with his account of isegoria at Athens. In Herodotus’s telling, Athenian equal right of speech is worthwhile not because of its effects on speech but because of its effect on political culture; equal speech energizes the Athenians and Athens. He thus offers a nonepistemic defense of the right to speak, defending it instead in terms of power and belonging. Yet his account also highlights how Athenian equal speech unleashes political harms and therefore offers a way to defend free speech without minimizing its dangers. Herodotus thus helps us productively reframe contemporary free speech debates.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

Debates over free speech are some of the most contentious in modern liberal democracies, pitching those who wish to uphold the classical liberal commitment to freedom of expression against those who worry about the undue harms untrammeled speech can enact upon vulnerable groups. Strikingly, however, both sides tend to cast themselves as the true defenders of free speech.Footnote 1 The recent controversy over the “Letter on Justice and Open Debate,” (Harper’s Magazine Reference Magazine2020) illustrates this. In its condemnation of so-called cancel culture, the letter reiterates a classic liberal argument for free speech: “The way to defeat bad ideas is by exposure, argument, and persuasion, not by trying to silence or wish them away.”Footnote 2 A response in the Objective accused the signatories of hypocrisy, charging that “many of [them] have championed the free market of ideas, but actively ensured that it is free only for them.”Footnote 3 In this view, cancel culture is simply free speech at work; those who decry it are in fact trying to silence valid expression, for “calling out” bad or harmful speech is itself a form of free speech. Despite deep disagreement, it is telling that both sides invoke the metaphor of the marketplace of ideas: one side reiterating its basic premise (the only remedy for bad speech is more speech) and the other clamoring for expanded access. I suggest that this is not mere posturing but rather underscores the lasting appeal of the marketplace metaphor. Its claim is fundamentally an epistemic one: that the open competition of ideas will (eventually) lead to truth. Yet a growing empirical consensus suggests that in the “marketplace of ideas,” the victory of truth is far from assured (Bambauer Reference Bambauer2006; Glaeser and Sunstein Reference Glaeser and Susstein2014; Sparrow and Goodin Reference Robert and Robert2007). Given this, scholars have proposed a myriad of ways of reconceptualizing freedom of speech.Footnote 4 But the marketplace metaphor persists. Its resistance to empirical debunking undermines its central epistemic claim: that good ideas win on the open market. If free speech does not produce good speech, is it still worth it?

I argue that the worth of free speech should be understood in nonepistemic terms and that the persistence of the marketplace metaphor in fact offers a route to articulating such a defense. The marketplace metaphor endures, I suggest, not because it is the truth but because it tells a good story that justifies in legible (albeit empirically dubious) terms, something to which we are profoundly attached. What “sells” on the market is not truth but a good story, and the marketplace metaphor provides a great one: that in the clash of ideas, good will (eventually) win. This triumphant narrative spins the attachment to free speech in epistemic and therefore dignified terms—it provides a good story that we can feel good about. However, freedom of speech is not particularly dignified. The attempt to render its value in epistemic terms risks downplaying its harms as justified by the eventual victory of the truth. A nonepistemic defense of its worth allows us to better acknowledge and manage its risks, dangers, and harms while maintaining a commitment to its core principle. I argue that we value the experience of free speech more than its results. Because of this, a more apt metaphor than the marketplace is the agora: a freewheeling and unpredictable open arena where one can speak truth or lies, be persuaded or tricked, benefited or harmed.

To this end, I turn to Herodotus’s Histories and his account of isegoria (equal speech), a term that has its roots in the agora. Footnote 5 Herodotus locates the worth of equal speech not its epistemic efficacy but in the way that it empowers the Athenian people and Athens: “Equal speech is clearly a good: take the case of Athens, which under the rule of tyrants proved no better in war than any of her neighbors, but, once rid of those tyrants, was far the first of all. What makes this clear is that when held in subject they would not do their best, for they were working for a taskmaster, but, when freed, they sought to win, because each was trying to achieve for their very self” (5.78).Footnote 6 Equal speech empowered the Athenians and Athens to resist tyrants at home and domination abroad; it made them not wise but resilient. His account captures what is good about free speech while attending to the persistence of bad speech. It thus offers a viable correction to the marketplace metaphor that also makes sense of its lasting appeal.

Indeed, the Histories must be central to any account of isegoria; it is a relatively uncommon term and yet is central to Herodotus’s account of democratic Athens. Herodotus’s account has often been dismissed as unclear. This is because deliberation is largely absent from Herodotus’s account of equal speech/isegoria, so scholars have tended to treat isegoria in Herodotus as a general stand-in for democracy without particular reference to equal right to speech.Footnote 7 But this neglects the way Herodotus locates the primary effects of the right to speech in behavior rather than speech itself. It is this unexpected emphasis that renders his account particularly fruitful for rethinking contemporary free speech.Footnote 8 Building on recent work treating isegoria as a “language ideology … of the free, full citizen among his peers” (Gottesman Reference Gottesman2021, 197) and as a depiction of a “broader political culture” (Schlosser Reference Schlosser2020, 77), I argue that Herodotus offers a nonepistemic account of the way the right to speak energizes participants in a political culture that entitles such participation. The goodness of isegoria lies not in its effects on speech but on the speakers (and audience). It depicts a culture of confidence: a community of equals who feel entitled to speak (even if they rarely or never do) in front of an audience of equals. This parity instills confidence in their judgments and daring in their actions; their decisions are theirs, not a taskmaster’s, even if their side did not win—and even if their decision is, frankly, stupid.

Herodotus’s account thus supports (and as I shall argue, qualifies) accounts of democracy such as Bagg’s (Reference Bagg2018), which finds the worth of democratic institutions in “the power it denies to various elites” (892). I thus align with recent scholarly work that argues that ancient Athens was not a deliberative democracy (Cammack Reference Cammack2021) but, rather, one that asserted the right of the demos to creative self-assertion (Cammack Reference Cammack, Ando and Sullivan2020) and so effectively blocked elite domination (Kirshner Reference Kirshner2016). Isegoria, the right to speak, does not produce wisdom (indeed, Herodotus specifically denies the wisdom of the multitude, 5.97) but asserts and enables the dignity and power of the multitude. The Histories thus both illustrate and qualify the account of democratic dignity developed by Josiah Ober (Reference Ober2012). Isegoria allows the Athenians to be fully themselves as individuals while relating to others as equals; isegoria thus creates the conditions for dignity. But the Histories suggest that democratic dignity should not be understood in epistemic terms but in terms of power. My account thus departs from Teresa Bejan’s account of isegoria, which casts it as a claim of epistemic equality grounded in the formal rights of the Athenian assembly (Reference Bejan2021).Footnote 9 The Histories, I argue, instead display the transformative effects of isegoria on the Athenians and Athens. Herodotus shows that a practice birthed in the democratic assembly comes to full fruition elsewhere (and everywhere). To understand isegoria, we thus need to look beyond the assembly. We can only understand its worth in terms of the action it inspires, the way its citizens carry themselves and act in the larger political world. The character of isegoria thus emerges through the entire narrative Herodotus unfurls about Athens.

This narrative is complex.Footnote 10 The story Herodotus tells allows the ambiguity of isegoria and Athens to emerge and thus underscores the tensions of democratic dignity. The zeal that equal speech unleashes also enables the exploitation of others. The narrative invites us to think through the connections between isegoria and its costs, the way it encourages dignity as well as exclusion, greed, and imperialism. His treatment suggests that the dark side of democratic dignity is not incidental but inevitable—yet still, somehow, worth it. Herodotus’s superlative praise does not gloss over the flaws of Athenian democracy. Herodotus thus practices parrhesia, frank speech, in his discussion of isegoria, equal speech.Footnote 11 Distinguishing between these two allows us to disentangle the epistemic aspirations of free speech claims—that it finds the truth—from the intrinsic worth of a culture of free speech. Although isegoria describes the right to speak, it does not determine what one says, how one says it, or whether one will be heard.Footnote 12 Therefore, isegoria is distinct from (and makes possible) two other related modes of speech: diabole (tricking, pulling one across) and parrhesia (straight talk, frank speech). Under isegoria, speakers can fool one another or talk straight, speak wisdom or foolishness; what matters is not what they say or how they say it or whether they are believed or disbelieved but that they feel entitled to speak at all. Under isegoria, both parrhesia and diabole are possible. The truth might not win, but it can be uttered.

This article will develop Herodotus’s account of equal speech as an alternative to modern popular discourse about free speech. I will begin by briefly surveying the history of the marketplace metaphor before suggesting that its main premise is echoed by a character within the pages of the Histories. I will then show how the narrative as a whole undermines faith in the ultimate triumph of the truth by examining some examples within the Histories of good counsel gone unheeded. Herodotus’s account of deliberation thus anticipates epistocratic critics of democracy like Jason Brennan (Reference Brennan2017) or Daniel Bell (Reference Bell2016). Yet despite this, Herodotus celebrates the way in which isegoria energizes the individual. Because of this, his account complicates contemporary accounts that posit an abrupt break between ancient and modern liberty. Herodotus’s praise of equal speech is more “modern” than we might expect but diverges from contemporary liberalism in revealing ways. These differences are not without some disquieting consequences, which emerge when we go beyond the assembly and see what the Athenians actually do. The character of isegoria becomes plain not in the assembly but at war. Therefore, I turn to Herodotus’s depiction of the battle of Salamis. At Salamis, speeches inspire but fail to persuade; dirty tricks undercut deliberation but then are burnished with fine speeches; the Athenians save the Hellenes, but also dominate them. This limns the dark side to democratic dignity. Thus, the agora, beset by cheats and frauds but also a place of joy and verve, better captures the dynamics of free speech than does the order and efficacy envisioned by the marketplace-of-ideas metaphor. In conclusion, I argue that Herodotus, by simultaneously praising and censuring Athenian isegoria, practices parrhesia—a frank speech that offers us a way to appreciate free speech without denying its harms.

The Marketplace and the Touchstone

As Bejan notes, the doctrine of freedom of expression originated in religious arguments for liberty of conscience made by Protestant dissenters. In her apt phrase, it was “rendered secular and respectable” (Bejan Reference Bejan2021, 156) by John Stuart Mill (see also Bejan Reference Bejan2017). Although Mill never explicitly called for a marketplace of ideas, in On Liberty he claims that free speech is essential for finding the truth: “The peculiar evil of silencing the expression of an opinion is, that it is robbing the human race; posterity as well as the existing generation; those who dissent from the opinion, still more than those who hold it. If the opinion is right, they are deprived of the opportunity of exchanging error for truth: if wrong, they lose, what is almost as great a benefit, the clearer perception and livelier impression of truth, produced by its collision with error” ([1859] Reference Mill, Bromwich and Kateb2003, 87). Mill’s argument is more nuanced than is the marketplace metaphor popularized by the American legal tradition, Footnote 13 but it shares the similarly progressive premise that, over the long term, liberty of speech will produce better speech (even if the process was not without its harms). The marketplace of ideas has formidable philosophical foundations.

Notwithstanding its deep roots in the liberal tradition, a character within the Histories makes an argument that echoes its central premise. At an assembly convened by the despot Xerxes before the invasion of Greece, the royal advisor Artabanus insists that free debate is necessary to find the truth: “My lord, when no opposing opinions are presented, it is impossible to choose the better, but one must accept what is proposed. When such opposites are stated, it is as it is with gold, the purity of which one cannot judge in itself, but only if you rub it alongside other gold on the touchstone and see the difference” (7.10). Artabanus insists that the airing of bad opinions strengthens and reveals good ones, that good ideas will triumph if they are allowed to be tested. Artabanus’s opinion is daring; he speaks not to an audience of equals but in front of a despot. Therefore, his speech in defense of free debate is not itself free; he must flatter (Pelling Reference Pelling, Dewald and Marincola2006, 109), for speaking in front of despots is a fraught art (Forsdyke Reference Forsdyke2001; Gottesman Reference Gottesman2021; Hohti Reference Hohti1975; Landauer Reference Landauer2019; Zali Reference Zali2013). Despite this flattery, Xerxes is enraged:Footnote 14 “Artabanus, you are my father’s brother; that shall save you from a punishment adequate for your empty words” (7.11). Scholars often take Artabanus’s failure to persuade Xerxes as yet another iteration on the theme of despotic illogic (cf. Forsdyke Reference Forsdyke2001). If that is the case, Artabanus’s failure in fact vindicates his claim (and the marketplace metaphor). Yet the Histories are long, and, as many note (Baragwanath Reference Baragwanath2008; Irwin Reference Irwin2014; Landauer Reference Landauer2019; Pelling Reference Pelling, Dewald and Marincola2006; Reference Pelling, Irwin and Greenwood2007), its pages are rife with counterexamples where despots listen, learn, and adapt to changing and complex situations. Herodotus’s narrative does not uncritically reproduce the binary of free polis/unfree despotism. It is possible to speak frankly to despots, and, as we shall see, sometimes one must self-censor before the demos. Xerxes was wrong not to give Artabanus a hearing; the defeat of his army reveals that. However, it does not follow that Artabanus was right. His statement displays profound faith in the efficacy of open debate. In his presentation, deliberation is as reliable as, well, the gold standard: other opinions are the touchstone upon which we find the truth (7.10). Artabanus could not test this opinion, but Herodotus’s narrative will.

Testing the Touchstone Theory

The Ionian revolt provides several illuminating instances of multiple opinions failing to produce the truth. The Ionian narrative sets the stage for the later Persian invasion of Hellas, a tragi-comic dumb-show version of the later Persian war (Baragwanath Reference Baragwanath2008, 204; Munson Reference Munson, Irwin and Greenwoo2007). Although the Ionians do not practice Athenian isegoria, at many junctures they engage in open debates about how to face the Persian onslaught. This allows us to disentangle the effects of the political culture of isegoria from deliberation itself. Absent the culture of isegoria and its effects on the bearing of the citizens, we can see whether multiple opinions on their own act as a touchstone for gold. As Schlosser observes, the Ionians both have the potential to be free yet are unable to sustain freedom (Reference Schlosser2020, 120–1,134). I argue that isegoria (and its absence) is central to this: the Ionians have the opportunity to deliberate absent the feeling that one is entitled to speak. The text of the Histories suggests that thinking is beset by all sorts of cognitive biases, which are on full display during the Ionian Revolt. At the later battle of Salamis, the Athenian general Themistocles will successfully navigate the same hurdles that crippled the Ionian Revolt. As Landauer observes, “The text pushes its readers to learn from logos’ success as well as its failures” (Reference Landauer2019, 85). The events of Salamis will show how the political culture wrought by isegoria interacts with the bad thinking that can derail open debate; the Ionian revolt lets us see these limitations unmitigated by the culture of isegoria.

Herodotus underscores an especially bad decision made by the Ionian Carians. Facing the assembled might of the Persian military, they gather to debate how to defend themselves—and incidentally reveal the difficulty of recognizing wise policy. “As the Carians collected in strength, various plans were put forward. The best seems to me to have been that of Pixodarus… . The Carians would have no line of escape but would have to stand their ground there and prove better than their nature. However, this plan did not win out” (5.118). Pixodarus argues for putting the Carians into a position of utmost necessity—of choosing, in fact, that necessity. Stripped of any escape, they must either win or die. Because of this, Pixodarus suggests they just might win: the phrase “better than nature” suggests that it is in our nature to do more than the natural in situations of extreme duress. Herodotus deems Pixodarus’s plan the best, and its strategy is vindicated at the battle of Salamis (8.83–96). However, the Carians are not persuaded. They choose a less risky plan and fail. Free debate did not lead to the best outcome; the wisest decision was unappealing and difficult and therefore unpopular. Pixodarus’s plan required short-term sacrifice for long-term gain. The Carians’ rejection of this plan suggests the difficulties human beings have in weighing present hardships against future gain.

A later incident in the Ionian revolt brings this into sharp relief. Dionysius, a Phocaean general, states the choice starkly: “Men of Ionia, our fortunes are on the very razor edge of decision: whether we will be freemen or slaves… . If you people are willing, for now, to endure hardships, you will have, for the immediate moment a hard time, but you will be able to beat your enemies and be free. If you settle into sloth and disorder, I have no hope that any one of you shall avoid the punishment of the Great king for your revolt. Listen to me and entrust yourselves to me” (6.11).Footnote 15 The Ionians are at first persuaded, and initially they follow Dionysius’s grueling training regimen. After a week, however, they are worn out: “What god can we have sinned against that we pay a penalty like this? We must have been entirely mad and sailed out of our minds’ bearings to trust ourselves to this Phocaean braggart… . He takes us over and afflicts us with sufferings from which we will never recover… . Rather than horrors like these it would be better for us to endure anything at all, including this future slavery—whatever that maybe—rather than what now oppresses us” (6.12). The Ionians’ inability to withstand the discipline that they themselves have agreed to means that they are unable to remain free from domination by others.

Their stated reason for shirking discipline bears closer scrutiny. First, they conceive of their self-chosen activity as a punishment from the divine; they disown their decision to entrust themselves to the Phocaean braggart. What was chosen by them now appears to be an external oppression inflicted upon them—by a god, no less. If isegoria captures a state of autonomy, of commitment to one’s own, the Ionians have reverted to its opposite, reveling in the lack of autonomy, the powerlessness of the god-afflicted. They do not do—they suffer. The temporarily sore muscles resulting from uncharacteristic exertion are cast as suffering from which they will never recover, and the future slavery, destruction, and death that will result from military defeat seem preferable to the present yet fleeting pain of an overtaxed body. Herodotus suggests that human beings outweigh present circumstances and dismiss the pains of the future. The political culture of the Ionians—many of whom are ruled by tyrants—does not allow for the daring and commitment that the self-ownership characteristic of isegoria nourishes, even when given the formal opportunity to debate and decide for themselves.

Yet when open debates occur in a culture of isegoria, they incur their own failures. Herodotus highlights an idiotic—and disastrous—decision made by the Athenian assembly.Footnote 16 This episode demonstrates that if the desire for ease can inhibit judgment, so too does the desire for gain. Aristagoras, a tinpot tyrant from Ionia, appeals to Athens for support against the Persians in the doomed Ionian revolt. Aristagoras had earlier sought Spartan support but had been rejected by their king, Kleomenes (5.49–5.51). The Athenians were more easily duped: “It seems then that it is easier to fool (διαβάλλειν) many men than one; Kleomenes the Lacedaemonian was only one, but Aristagoras could not fool him, though he managed to do so to thirty thousand Athenians” (5.97). Aristagoras was not himself Athenian, but his audience is. To a crowd of individuals who seek to “achieve for their very self” (5.78), Aristagoras made promises of great gain. Their appetites whetted (the very same appetites that have been unleashed by isegoria), the Athenians accept Aristagoras’s claims without investigating them (Balot Reference Balot2006, 130; Baragwanath Reference Baragwanath2008, 201). The greatness of Athenian democracy lies in its energetic pursuit of what it deems good; this same zeal renders it incautious and easy to dupe. Isegoria dignifies the Athenians—and they in turn dignify their own appetites. They are thus more receptive to speeches that appeal to these. The political culture of isegoria thus affects not just speakers but audience. Equal say does not lead to wise deliberation.

Herodotus’s observations cohere with what political psychologists have generally found: people reason badly about politics. As Brennan summarizes, “The overwhelming consensus in political psychology, based on a huge and diverse range of studies, is that most citizens process political information in deeply biased, partisan, motivated ways rather than in dispassionate, rational ways” (Reference Brennan2017, 37). This faulty reasoning often leads to flawed outcomes. Because of this, Brennan argues that we should engage in politics less, that we should reduce or even do away with democratic engagement: “Democracy is a tool, nothing more. If we can find a better tool, we should feel free to use it” (Reference Brennan2017, xiv). The story that Herodotus tells shows us that people debate badly and make poor decisions with often disastrous consequences. In the pages of the Histories, and in real life, people die because we are bad at deliberating. Herodotus, then, agrees with critics of democracy, both modern (like Brennan) and ancient (like Plato) who argue that democracy is often unwise and unjust, fractious and stupid. Yet he still defends it. His defense has often been regarded as unclear. I argue that to understand Herodotus’s defense of equal speech and democracy, we have to look at his portrait of Athenian democracy in action.

Zeal Not Wisdom

For Herodotus, the value of democratic debate lies not in its truthfulness or wisdom, but in the energy it unleashes:

It is not only in respect of one thing but of everything that equal right of speech (ἰσηγορίη) is clearly a good; take the case of Athens, which under the rule of tyrants proved no better in war than any of her neighbors but, once rid of those tyrants, was far the first of all. What this makes clear is that when held in subjection they would not do their best, for they were working for a taskmaster, but when freed, they sought to win, because each was eager to achieve for his very self. (5.78)

What Herodotus praises about isegoria, equal right of speech, does not have to do with speech itself. Isegoria does not promote the truth or produce wisdom, or rather this is not what is praiseworthy about it. Equal speech matters because of its effects on the broader political culture, speakers and audience alike. As Schlosser puts it, “Everyone strives for what is best for himself, with the assumed reward being theirs; yet while each pursues his own cause, this leads to the strength of the whole” (Reference Schlosser2020, 70). It is critical to democratic self-rule, to freedom from tyranny.Footnote 17 Decisions and actions, for good or ill, are owned by the whole of the community; they do more and dare more because the doings of the city are the achievements of each individual within it.

This public spiritedness is not an unambiguous good. But first, I wish to note how it differs from the Berlin-Constant view of the ancients, which contrasts ancient moderation and self-restraint with modern hedonism. Patrick Deneen provides a recent articulation of this: “The Greeks especially regarded self-government as a continuity from the individual to the polity… . Self-governance in the city was possible only if the virtue of self-governance governed the souls of citizens” (Reference Deneen2018, 22). Yet as some have argued (Edge Reference Edge2009; Karagiannis and Wagner Reference Karagiannis, Wagner, Arneson, Raaflaub and Wagner2013; Miller Reference Miller2001; Raaflaub Reference Raaflaub2004), there is greater continuity (although not total similarity) between ancient and modern liberty than is often urged. Herodotus in particular complicates the notion of an abrupt fissure between the two. His treatment of democratic Athens locates resistance to tyranny not in an orderly soul but in the zeal that isegoria unleashes; sheer feistiness, rather than virtue, is critical to self-rule. By granting autonomy to individuals, free speech unleashes their vitality: “Each was eager to achieve for their very self” (5.78). Isegoria enlivens the Athenians by granting them autonomy. They belong to themselves, and in this, belong to the city. In contrast, the rule of tyrants was like “working for a taskmaster.” Deprived of autonomy, the Athenians willfully give less than their all. In contrast, under isegoria the individual is motivated to do well because their achievements are theirs.

This renders Herodotus’s treatment of isegoria much closer to modern accounts of liberty than is usually admitted. As Naketegawa puts it, “The most important characteristic of isegoria consists in a rousing sense of community, a sense that the Polis is not a tyrant’s possession but every citizen’s own property” (Reference Naketegawa1988, 270). The Athenians take pride in the city because they are the city: equal speech grants each Athenian a stake in Athens. This motivates the individuals to do better and to do more. Herodotus’s understanding of isegoria thus bears both some remarkable similarities with liberal respect for individual agency and some important differences. Its similarities lie in its commitment to individual autonomy: Herodotean equal speech enables the individual to pursue his own good, to exercise autonomy and agency in the development of a life. Each seeks to achieve for their very self. This way of valuing free speech resembles what Howard terms “speaker autonomy” (Reference Howard2019, 97–8). As Baker puts it, “Respect for personhood … requires that each person must be permitted to be herself and to present herself” (Reference Edwin1997, 992).Footnote 18 Equal right of say guarantees the person space in the public realm; it doesn’t matter how valuable or moral or wise their contribution is but rather that they are entitled to be there, to exist, to develop their own selves through their pursuit of their own good. As Kateb states, “Much expression comes out of the character of the expressers. Their expression is not only theirs, it is them. To tolerate their expression is to tolerate their being” (Reference Kateb and Yack1996, 233). To allow speech, to give each the right to have their say, is to recognize an individual’s existence, his right to occupy part of the public space. Isegoria, the equal right of speech, insists that each individual has a say—that they be included, whether or not they are wise, judicious, or virtuous.

Yet, whereas liberal proponents of free speech imagine it as a protection against a government that might seek to infringe an individual’s speech, as Saxonhouse has observed, equal right of speech is what includes the people within the city; it is freedom as autonomy, not from the state but within and through the civic realm (Reference Saxonhouse2006). This becomes evident when we turn to the proofs Herodotus provides that isegoria is a good: victory in war. The emphasis on war is a striking departure from the liberal emphasis on comfortable self-preservation. Athens’ greatness lay not in the increase of any given individual’s wealth but in their successful defense of their city, first against the Lacedaemonians (5.70–77) and later against the Persians at the battle of Marathon (6.112–117).Footnote 19 I have so far downplayed the role of the assembly in understanding Herodotean isegoria, precisely because the proofs of its worth are located on the battlefield. But actions on the battlefield are authorized by the assembly; those who vote are also those who fight. Although they may not deliberate wisely, they do so with spirit.Footnote 20 The Athenians choose to resist occupation and domination; they choose to fight rather than surrender. Therefore, epistocratic critiques of democracy (like Bell’s and Brennan’s) miss the point; the main strength of democracy is not its wisdom but the way in which it empowers people to resist domination (Cammack Reference Cammack, Ando and Sullivan2020; Kirshner Reference Kirshner2016). Herodotus’s account thus coheres with Bagg’s defense of the power of democracy (Reference Bagg2018): the Athenians resisted tyrants at home and the threat of Persian domination abroad.

Herodotus’s narrative urges that this resistance to domination can spur the domination of others. As Ward (Reference Ward2008) observes, Athenian freedom involves the domination of other Greek city-states, and as Bejan notes, the inclusive energy of the Athenian assembly rested on those whom it excluded (Reference Bejan2021, 165–6). Power affects character, for mass and elite alike, in ways that contemporary democratic theorists should consider. If epistemic accounts of democracy understate the challenges of voter ignorance, as Bagg (Reference Bagg2018) argues, instrumental accounts should not neglect the transformational power of democratic institutions. Holding power can transform, for better and for worse, those who hold it. Aristagoras succeeded in fooling the Athenians not because they were ignorant but because they were greedy. The confidence and autonomy characteristic of isegoria meant that the Athenians could and did act on their appetites. They “achieved” for their very selves, but these achievements have a dark side. The demos both acts and authorizes those actions; they vote and they do, and in all this, they “seek to win”—whatever it takes.

This suggests that Athenian imperialism is a choice; it is a project authorized by the self-governing people of isegoria. As Munson has observed, the Scythian narrative shows a possibility of freedom without domination (Munson Reference Munson2001a, 212–4): in the Histories, “an invasion is an act of the will and an unnecessary choice” (Munson Reference Munson2001b, 41). Athens’ success at war is not an unmitigated good—Herodotus calls war an evil (8.3). The superlative character of Herodotus’s praise of Athens effectively highlights the ambiguities in his portrayal. Athenian freedom leads her to dominate her neighbors but is also responsible for the success of the Greek allies against the Persian invasion. As Herodotus proclaims, “So, as it stands now, a man who declares that the Athenians were the saviors of Greece would hit the very truth. For to whichever side they inclined, that was where the scale would come down. They chose that Greece should survive free, and it was they who awakened all the part of Greece that had not Medized, and it was they who, under Heaven, routed the king” (7.139). Themistocles will probe this tension and put it to productive work at the Battle of Salamis. But his success underscores just how precarious the alliance between Athens and the rest of the Hellenes is. Herodotus repeatedly shows how close the allied Greeks came to collapsing into fractious infighting; the narrative is structured so as to render the fact that the Hellenes held together against the Persians surprising (Baragwanath Reference Baragwanath2008, 203–39).

Yet just as the coalition of Athens and her allies is precarious, so too is the coincidence of interest between Athens and individual Athenians; the zeal unleashed by Athenian isegoria threatens Athens as well.Footnote 21 The excellence of Athens rests in the way its norms stir the vigorous pursuit of what the individuals take to be their own good—and these whetted appetites can impair public deliberation, as Aristagoras’s temptation of Athens revealed.Footnote 22 The particular virtue of Athenian democracy, its zeal, seems especially in need of the guidance of wise speech. That Athenian equal speech does not in itself lead to wisdom does not mean that there is no wisdom to be found in Athens. Its equality opens up space for the wisdom of previously excluded individuals to emergeFootnote 23 while simultaneously leading to crises that require that wisdom. This will make plain the relationship between isegoria and diabole (trickery, deception). Gottesman contrasts these modes: “Isegoria describes the experience in sharing in a community of equals, without any need to dissemble or flatter” (Reference Gottesman2021, 180) while conceding that sometimes equal speech still involves deceptive speech (189–90). Yet this assumes that diabole in isegoria is incidental and that the primary reason to dissemble is fear. Themistocles’s efforts at Salamis will suggest that, for the isegoria to prevail, diabole might be required. The ambiguities of Themistocles’s character, and the deeds necessary to secure victory at Salamis, will suggest the dark side to democratic dignity. Equal speech captures the bearing of a citizen; but equals might not always talk straight to one another.

Dirty Tricks and a Good Story

This becomes clear through Themistocles, the Athenian general who successfully engineered the strategy that saved Hellas from the Persian invasion (7.144). Because Herodotus finds the ultimate proof of the goodness of isegoria in Athens’ military success, Themistocles’s central role in staving off annihilation at the hands of the Persians will illuminate just how Athenian isegoria promotes such success. Yet the character of his success also limns the dilemma of Athenian equal speech. Schemes and spin are his signature talents.Footnote 24 Both of these skills are put to use for Athens and for Greece as a whole, but their power to help is also the power to harm. The ambiguity of Themistocles thus encapsulates the complex character of speech at Athens.Footnote 25 Indeed, Themistocles’s first appearance in the Histories illustrates how equal speech opens up space for the previously unheard. Herodotus highlights his newness; the son of Neokles, “New Renown,” he only recently came into the front ranks of the city (7.143). Footnote 26 This new actor intervenes at a crucial moment to offer a wise speech that is also persuasive.

Faced with an oracle that seems to foretell the defeat of Athens at the hands of the Persians (7.141–142), Themistocles interprets in such a way that it promises success—if the Athenians were to take action. He spun his reading of the oracle to work with the motivation of the Athenians: “This was Themistocles’ explanation, and the Athenians decided that it was preferable to that of the oracle-interpreters; for the latter would not have them prepare for a sea fight or indeed, to tell the truth, put up a hand’s worth of resistance at all” (7.143). Themistocles provides an optimistic narrative that shapes the Athenians’ appetite for resistance into sound defensive action. Schlosser treats this incident as an example of successful democratic deliberation: “The Athenians allow Themistocles to propose an alternative interpretation. Themistocles does not persuade them or demand their obedience” (Reference Schlosser2020, 123). Yet Herodotus’s emphasis on the affective state of the Athenians shows that what Themistocles is doing is indeed persuasion (Ward likewise highlights Themistocles’s rhetorical skill; Reference Ward2008, 132). This does not undermine isegoria but rather confirms that Themistocles knows and shares its character: the Athenians are open to listening to him, but he is heard because he understands and directs their own motivations. The political culture that grants the upstart Themistocles the right to speak also kindles the desire to assert themselves within the Athenians. As Ober notes, this action was owned by the whole of the demos (Reference Ober2017, 152; cf. Schwarzberg Reference Schwarzberg2014). Ober reads this decision as confirming the validity and wisdom of democratic deliberation. Indeed, this spirited decision was also wise: as Herodotus makes plain, with this plan the Athenians became “the saviors of Greece” (7.139). Although spirited decisions can be wise, they are not necessarily so. The narrative will explore how zeal, wisdom, and deliberation at times intersect—and conflict.

Indeed, the Athenians are rather unseemly saviors. At the battle of Artemisium, Athens initially displays a noble Panhellenic solidarity. Despite Athens’ obvious naval superiority, the allies objected to putting them in charge of the Greek fleet. But “the Athenians gave way; they thought what mattered most was the survival of Greece and knew very well that if there was a dispute about the leadership, Greece would perish—and that thought was correct, for strife within the nation is as much a greater evil than a united war effort as war itself is more evil than peace” (8.3). They put aside vanity for the greater good, a fine moment for Athenian democracy. Yet Herodotus does not leave this noble vision of Athens untarnished, for they yielded “only so long as they had urgent need of the others, as they later proved” (8.3). Herodotus’s ever-restless narrative, which roves back and forth in time, keeps both sides of Athens’ character in frame: its brave selflessness and its predatory attitude toward its neighbors.

Themistocles’s behavior at Artemisum likewise combines both the interest of the group and his own self-interest, which here coincide—yet not quite seamlessly. Faced with the ominous spectacle of the Persian fleet, the assembled Greek allies become fearful and wish to flee. Despite this, Themistocles entices the Hellenes to fight an ultimately successful battle by accepting a bribe, bribing others, and managing to pocket the remainder for himself (8.4–5). His conduct has struck many as ignoble; some readers of Herodotus, aghast, have seen in it evidence of Herodotus’s reliance on hostile sources (How and Wells Reference How and Wells1928). But as Baragwanath notes, for an Athenian audience, Themistocles’ ability to reconcile the common interest with his own “rather enhance[d] his achievement” (Reference Baragwanath2008, 292). Themistocles’s selfish cunning here served the greater good (Fornara Reference Fornara1971, 72–3). Achieving “for his very self” (cf.5.78) helped him achieve for Athens—and for Greece. Themistocles once again understands and directs the self-interest of others in order to support the common good. However, what brings these together is not wise speech but bribery. Unlike his interpretation of the oracle, Themistocles’s persuasive speech is insufficient to move his audience.

Salamis and the Dark Side of Democratic Dignity

The limits of speech become more apparent during the battle of Salamis, often regarded as a foundational moment for Athenian democracy. As Euben writes, Herodotus suggests “that the victory at Salamis … was won by men because of their political culture” (Reference Euben1997, 65); Raaflaub (Reference Raaflaub2004) has likewise noted how fundamental Athenian power in the Persian war was to the development of democratic constitutionalism, Forsdyke (Reference Forsdyke2001) has explored its role in democratic ideology, and Ober notes how, after Salamis, “democratic Athens went on to become the preeminent state of the Greek world” (Reference Ober2017, 152). In Schlosser’s words, the Persian invasion “leads the Greeks to articulate a political notion of freedom not just as resistance to tyranny but as something secured through their cooperative effort—that is, as a political achievement” (Reference Schlosser2020, 126). Yet it is striking—and sobering—how vulnerable this achievement is: how close it came to not happening, the sneaky tricks required to pull it off. This emerges most clearly through the role of deliberation at Salamis. Schlosser suggests that persuasion is critical to the collective efforts of the Greeks at Salamis (Reference Schlosser2020, 126), and Ober likewise finds in Athenian victory proof of the wise judgment of the Athenians (Reference Ober2017, 151–2).Footnote 27 However, persuasion is remarkably impotent at Salamis.Footnote 28 Themistocles, an upstart who feels entitled to speak, will trick and scheme to save Hellas from itself. The character wrought by isegoria will in fact prove to be decisive for victory, but in ways that bring its ambiguity to the fore.

This ambiguity is evident from the moment the assembled Greeks debate where best to fight (8.49). The majority resolve to return to the Peloponnese and give up on Attica (8.49). But Mnesiphilus, an Athenian, tells Themistocles how disastrous this plan will be: “If once they draw off the ships from Salamis, you will never again fight for any fatherland at all; everyone will run off, each one to his own city, and neither Eurybiades [the Spartan commander], nor any other man will be able to keep the army from scattering. Greece will be lost, and all through sheer folly. If there is any means at all by which you can undo this decision, if by any means (μηχανή: contrivance, device, or art) you can persuade Eurybiades to change his mind and stay here, do so” (8.57). Each will prefer their own and will abandon the common project of fighting once the temptation of home is nearby. Much like the Carians, the preference for present ease and comfort will lead them to gamble their futures. Mnesphilus’s final entreaty for Themistocles to use any μηχανή/means conveys his desperation: do this by any means necessary.

Themistocles first tries persuasion, with some success: he persuades Eurybiades to summon the generals back to revisit their decision (8.58). Herodotus underscores the tactical and rhetorical aspect of Themistocles’s speech to the generals. The way he fashions his speech is a μηχανή, a scheme itself: the presentation of his words is designed to suit his purpose, which is to sway—to win. Themistocles begins by disguising his true opinion: as Herodotus says “for in the presence of the allies it would not have been suitable for him to make accusations against anyone” (8.60). As Pelling states, Themistocles “did not speak his mind… . He cannot say [his true opinion] in public” (Reference Pelling, Dewald and Marincola2006, 112). Although this is an open debate, Themistocles does not speak openly. His earlier successful speech interpreting the oracle to the Athenians suggests why. There, Themistocles had understood the Athenians’ desire to fight and gave it a concrete form. This suggests a profound limit to the persuasive power of speech. It can shift and direct, but it has to appeal to what people already want. The zealous Athenians, bred in a culture of isegoria, want to fight; the assembled generals do not.

Instead of accusation, Themistocles takes “quite another tack” (8.60). Rather than speak an insulting truth, he chooses to frame his message in a way that flatters. Themistocles tells them that “it is in your hands to save Greece if you will be persuaded by me” (8.60). Just like Artabanus had to flatter Xerxes (7.10–11), so too does Themistocles flatter an audience of his peers.Footnote 29 Yet this flattery does not contradict isegoria. Themistocles still displays the characteristic verve of Athenian isegoria, the character of a citizen who belongs and is entitled to speak. The Corinthian general admonishes him for this: “In the games, those who get off the mark too soon are whipped.” Themistocles’s reply is marked by the energy of democratic Athens: “Those who get left behind never get crowned” (8.59). One can be insouciant and bold yet still take care in how one’s opinions are expressed. Isegoria does not mandate parrhesia, frank speech.Footnote 30 Only after this flattery does he list concrete reasons why it would be superior to fight at Salamis, concluding that they are likely to win “if the probable chances of war occur” (8.60). He concludes that “it is when men make probable designs that success oftenest attends them; if their designs are improbable, not even the god is willing to lend his help to the plans of men” (8.60). Echoing his tactics in the interpretation of oracle, he recruits divine support in order to support human agency.

Flattery, reason, the divine: Themistocles employs three powerful hooks in order to persuade his audience. But these fail, and so Themistocles turns to threats: “There are no Greeks able to withstand an attack by us” (8.61). This is hardly an uplifting display of deliberation. Herodotus refers to these debates as a “verbal skirmish (ἀκροβολισάμενοι)” (8.64). Debate here is agonistic combat—not collaborative deliberation, but spectacle.Footnote 31 It works on the Spartan general Eurybiades, but what persuades is not reason but fear (Eurybiades “especially dreaded that the Athenians would desert them” [8.63]). Yet this does not persuade the other generals: “For a while they would stand close together … whispering their bewilderment at the stupidity of Eurybiades. But at last it all burst into the open” (8.74). The commander of the Greeks had resolved to fight but could not simply command the allies to do so. Without widespread support, his decision lacked force. The generals were bewildered by the “stupidity” of Eurybiades; yet their own plan to retrench at the Isthmus has already been impugned by what happened to the Carians. They are unable to see the wisdom of Themistocles’s proposition.

That the gifted orator Themistocles is unable to persuade the generals demonstrates that persuasion has its limits. He must seek other, more duplicitous methods—a μηχανή/scheme to override the flawed results of open debate. Themistocles dispatches a member of his household to transmit a message to the Persians: that Themistocles is an “adherent of the king” and as such is informing him of the dissent amongst the Greeks and the opportunity it provides (8.75). This apparent betrayal is successful because it is plausible. Not only do the Persians generally view the Greeks as fractious and disloyal (1.153, 7.9); many Greeks have in fact gone over to the Persian side (7.132; Pelling Reference Pelling, Irwin and Greenwood2007, 112). It is entirely plausible that the Greeks would collapse, because they are already on the verge of collapsing. Themistocles will use that disunity to ensure that the Greeks are all equally forced into a situation of extreme duress. Informed by Themistocles’s message, the Persians encircle the Hellenes, who now must fight. In this, they are forced into the extreme necessity that Pixodarus envisioned for the Carians, yet without the freedom to choose that necessity. Themistocles has stripped the Panhellenic council of choice (Collins Reference Collins2019). The allies may freely debate what to do, but Themistocles has engineered a situation in which the decision is out of their hands. Themistocles, empowered by the isegoria of Athens, has taken power away from the rest of the Greeks.

Ironically, having deprived the Hellenes of choice, Themistocles makes an impressive speech urging the gathered generals to “choose the better” (8.83). Herodotus does not let us hear this speech; he merely describes its contents. Herodotus thus disenchants his audience. We know that words are spoken, but because we do not experience their charm, we are prevented from being taken in by them. Herodotus thereby draws our attention to what Themistocles is doing, rather than what he is saying (Zali Reference Zali2013, 483–4). Herodotus’s treatment of this speech thus underscores its irony. Just when Themistocles seems to have abandoned speech in favor of sneaky tricks, he uses it again—to reframe and inspire, not to persuade. Themistocles has engineered a situation where the Hellenes have no choice, where they must fight or be destroyed. Once in that situation, however, the power of his speech encourages them to view their situation as a choice: he imbues it with dignity. In doing what they must, they are made to feel that they are acting nobly. Necessity forces them to fight, but Themistocles’s speech (and Herodotus’s praise of it) suggests that the proper mental framing—the right narrative—can help them to fight well. As Schlosser writes, Herodotus’s provocative narration asks us to consider the effects of stories on their audience, directing us to reflect on how “stories direct the reader toward particular activities” (Reference Schlosser2020, 89). Stories can elevate and motivate, and thus they have a political power reason often lacks. The speeches of isegoria sometimes persuade, sometimes flatter, sometimes trick, sometimes inspire, and sometimes dupe. This power becomes evident through Herodotus’s own story. Herodotus thus equips us to be more sophisticated audiences (Schlosser Reference Schlosser2014; Rathnam Reference Rathnam2018).

A more fitting metaphor for equal speech is thus not the marketplace of ideas but rather the agora as depicted by the Persian Cyrus in his mockery of the Hellenes: “I never yet feared men who have a place set apart in the midst of their cities where they gather to cheat one another and exchange oaths, which they break” (1.153).Footnote 32 Skulduggery and spin are characteristic of isegoria. We are less shoppers than hagglers, moved by performances, schemes, and a good story. This suggests that the marketplace metaphor itself succeeds not because it is true but because it sells a good story. Cyrus’s depiction of the agora more accurately grasps the nature of equal speech. Therefore, he is not wrong in his dismissal of the Greeks as duplicitous. Yet Cyrus underestimates the worth of unseemliness. If Themistocles had not been such a dirtbag, the Hellenes would have lost the war. But if such vice has its virtues, Herodotus never lets one eclipse the other—the narrative keeps both sides of Themistocles in view. In the aftermath of the battle, after failing to convince the other Hellenes to pursue the fleeing Persians, Themistocles changes his position and persuades the Athenians to let the Persians go (8.109). However sound this policy, Herodotus is clear about Themistocles’s motivations: “He intended that this act should be as a reserve to his credit with the Persians, that he might have a refuge if, one day, trouble overtook him at the hands of the Athenians, which is indeed what took place. With such words Themistocles deceived them (διέβαλλε), but the Athenians were convinced” (8.109–110). The verb recalls Aristagoras. The hero of the war has done to the Athenians what the petty tyrant who duped them into a disastrous military expedition did: tricked them (Pelling Reference Pelling, Irwin and Greenwood2007, 181).

Further shading this characterization of Themistocles is the way in which, after letting the Persians go, the Athenians quickly turn on their Hellenic neighbors who had medized. Although this can be framed as retribution for collaborating with the Persians, Herodotus is quite clear about Themistocles’s motivations, for his “greed for money was insatiable” (8.112). Themistocles’s personal greed mirrors that of Athens. This unleashed self-interest fosters the greatness of Athens, the unique and spectacular achievements of its citizens. But Themistocles’s career reminds us that such self-interest threatens both domestic and international politics. The best and worst of Athens are interconnected; its customs are volatile, a precarious balance. What is best about it also renders it vulnerable—to strife within, to domination and war without. As Herodotus says of the Athenian decision to (temporarily) put Hellas first, “For strife within the nation is as much a greater evil than a united war effort as war itself is more evil than peace” (8.3). Athens’ energy, the political culture nourished by equal speech, allows them to resist domination at home and abroad, but it also fosters its capacity for greed, domination, and imperialism.

By cultivating the wise judgment of his readers through his performance of inquiry, Herodotus equips us to recognize this. Athens might already be lost, given over to its temptation to empire, but we, the future audience of the Histories envisioned by the proem,Footnote 33 might learn from its example, its virtues, and its mistakes. And for this reason, Herodotus’s mode of speech—and his skills—differ from those of Themistocles. Themistocles understands his audience, and the power of a good story, but to accomplish his ends, he hides his art, obscures the ways in which he persuades, schemes, and tricks his way into securing Hellenic victory. Themistocles, the paragon of isegoria, must at times practice diabole—and this diabole may be for good or ill. But in showing us the schemes, stories, and spin, the diabole characteristic of the citizen of isegoria, Herodotus practices a form of parrhesia—frank speech. He boldly speaks the truth, what his inquiry has uncovered; he shows what some would conceal and what others would rather not hear. His praise of Athens is such frank speech. In declaring his opinion that the Athenians were the saviors of Greece, Herodotus acknowledges the unpopularity of this opinion yet the necessity of stating it: “At this point I am forced to declare an opinion that most people will find offensive; yet because I think it is true, I will not hold back” (7.139). His depiction of Athens praises what is offensive to others but does not shy away from what is unflattering about Athens. Herodotus feels compelled to speak the truth—but only after showing us how difficult it can be to hear it, the stories and biases that impair our ability to separate gold from the dross, the ways in which Artabanus’s faith in a marketplace might be mislaid—and ours as well.

Conclusion

Herodotus’s frank speech about equal speech, his parrhesia about isegoria, allows its harms to come into view alongside its benefits. Isegoria, the equal right to speech, describes a community of equals who belong to a free political community and are empowered by such belonging; its dangers are thus not only the well-documented untruths and harassment that speech can occasion but also exclusion and domination (Bejan Reference Bejan2021; Ward Reference Ward2008). If all forms of belonging involve some degree of exclusion, boundaries drawn between those who belong and those who do not, exclusion can be more or less justified, more or less legitimate. Exclusion can be domination—Athens excluded slaves, noncitizens, and women from full participation in the community. Exclusion can also be used to manage those who would dominate others; those who harass women and minorities on social media might be excluded in order to maintain an inclusive space. In this view, the maintenance of the marketplace requires the exclusion of pernicious actors.

Inclusion within an empowered community may necessitate a degree of exclusion. But we should be careful about licensing a more expansive scope for exclusion, as this can have unintended consequences. Viewing free speech as a matter of power centers its interplay with power dynamics; this reminds us to attend to the pragmatic and political considerations of limiting free speech. Arguments for exclusion can be used against the marginalized and oppressed (as witnessed by the increased push to ban challenging or controversial material from schools based on the discomfort such works might incur); target the undeserving; or leave no room for transformation, genuine regret, and reparation. We must remember that the power to exclude is still power, so it should be wielded with care. Herodotus, who praises isegoria in terms of its power, also warns of the dangers of such power; the Histories as a whole counsel moderation (Lateiner Reference Lateiner1989). Herodotus’s critique of the rule of taskmasters thus reminds us not to become taskmasters ourselves, for pushing pernicious voices out of the public might only make those beliefs more attractive to those inclined to believe them. Attempting to silence an opinion can instead amplify it, as Tim Wu notes (Reference Wu2018, 559). As Pixodarus and Themistocles knew, people fight back when they feel they have no escape. Excluding bad actors does not make them disappear—instead, it might inflame them. If free speech does not make for good speech, silencing speech can have unanticipated and deleterious effects on the broader political culture.

It is precisely because Herodotus finds the most significant effects of isegoria in the larger political culture rather than particular institutions or laws that his account is relevant today. Bejan (Reference Bejan2021) notes that the negative protection against government interference promised by the First Amendment and the popular belief in a substantive right to say what one wishes are often conflated in a way that obscures larger issues and offers her account of isegoria as epistemic dignity as a way of clarifying these different objectives. But Herodotus’s treatment of isegoria suggests that the very fact that public discourse blurs these distinctions is important. It suggests that a legal right can have a substantive effect on the culture and bearing of a people—that what people care about matters, even if it cannot be defended in epistemic terms. Herodotus’s treatment of the nonepistemic virtue of isegoria urges us to attend to this attachment, for the Histories show that the right to speak is not just a matter of law but the feeling that animates it. A recent New York Times pollFootnote 34 found that a majority of Americans believe that the culture of freedom of speech is under threat. Whether or not it is empirically true, that perception matters. Herodotus urges us to take that culture, and the attachment to it, seriously.

Herodotus’s frank speech in praise of isegoria thus grants us another metric by which we can evaluate free speech. If we expect that free speech will produce a marketplace of ideas where the best will inevitably win, Herodotus suggests that we will be disappointed. However, this disappointment is misplaced. Epistocratic critiques of democracy misunderstand the character of political knowledge and action; they treat politics as technocratic problem solving. As Cammack (Reference Cammack, Ando and Sullivan2020) writes, this conflates two separate kinds of inquiry: questions of episteme center on fact, but political decisions pertain to the future because they enact the creative self-assertion of the demos. Ancient Greek political practice thus offers a way of responding to epistocratic critics, and this is lost if we frame Athens as a primarily deliberative democracy (cf. Bejan Reference Bejan2021; Ober Reference Ober2012; Reference Ober2017). Herodotus’s account of isegoria in particular celebrates the right to speak as central to democratic self-assertion. The limits to isegoria, to equal speech, are thus also the limits to community: who can speak is also who belongs. In drawing these limits, we must remember that these boundaries are political, an act of self-definition. An ancient text cannot and should not settle these boundaries for us, but because the Histories also underscore the harms of isegoria, it can help us think through the dilemmas posed by free speech. Isegoria offers a powerful means of checking the exploitation and domination endemic to other forms of government. That it involves exploitation of its own means that we require parrhesia, frank speech to highlight this—again and again and again, given that the victory of truth is never guaranteed. Equal speech might be stupid, even harmful, and yet still somehow good.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

For their help with this article, my profound thanks go to the APSR editorial board and the anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful comments. I thank Lincoln Rathnam, Kiran Banerjee, Abraham Singer, and Jason Douglas Todd for their helpful contributions. I also wish to thank Clifford Orwin, Ryan Balot, Melissa Williams, and Judd Owen for their intellectual guidance and conversation. I presented earlier drafts of this article at a philosophy workshop at Wuhan University and at the Department of Ancient Mediterranean Studies at Emory University and received invaluable feedback at both. My colleagues at DKU, James Miller and Keping Wu, organized a writer’s retreat that provided a productive respite from pandemic parenting, and for that they have my eternal thanks.

CONFLICT OF INTEREST

The author declares no ethical issues or conflicts of interest in this research.

ETHICAL STANDARDS

The author affirms this research did not involve human subjects.

Footnotes

1 See also Bejan (Reference Bejan2021).

4 See Howard (Reference Howard2019) for an overview; Bejan (Reference Bejan2021).

5 For more on the history of isegoria, see Gottesman (Reference Gottesman2021), Hohti (Reference Hohti1975), Lewis (Reference Lewis1971), Naketegawa (Reference Naketegawa1988), Rhodes (Reference Rhodes, Harrison and Irwin2018), and Schlosser (Reference Schlosser2020). For more on isegoria and parrhesia, see Carter (Reference Carter, Sluiter and Rosen2004), Konstan (Reference Konstan2012), Landauer (Reference Landauer2012), Raaflaub (Reference Raaflaub2004), and Saxonhouse (Reference Saxonhouse2006).

6 Translation David Grene (Herodotus Reference Grene1987), with some emendations.

7 Naketgawa (Reference Naketegawa1988); Gottesman (Reference Gottesman2021) for history of scholarship on isegoria.

8 Bejan (Reference Bejan2021) also argues that isegoria helps reframe contemporary free speech debates, but her account is enmeshed in a legalistic/epistemic framework that misses out on what is particularly novel about ancient isegoria.

9 Cf. Gottesman: “No ancient text unequivocally supports the definition of isegoria as the right to address the assembly” (Reference Gottesman2021, 178).

10 For meta-narrative in Herodotus, see Baragwanath (Reference Baragwanath2008), Branscome (Reference Branscome2013), Christ (Reference Christ1994), Demont (Reference Demont2009), Dewald (Reference Dewald1987; Reference Dewald, Bakker, de Jong and van Wees2002), Irwin (Reference Irwin2014), and Zali (Reference Zali2013). For the political consequences of this, see Apfel (Reference Apfel2011), McWilliams (Reference McWilliams2014), Rathnam (Reference Rathnam2018), Schlosser (Reference Schlosser2014; Reference Schlosser2020), and Thompson (Reference Thompson1996).

11 Konstan (Reference Konstan2012).

12 Much thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this point.

14 Pelling (Reference Pelling, Dewald and Marincola2006, 109): “Xerxes’ response is one of magnificent fury, and it shows how right Artabanus was to watch his words.”

15 Munson notes the tragic aspect of Dionysius’s resistance (Reference Munson, Irwin and Greenwoo2007, 148).

16 But see Pelling (Reference Pelling, Irwin and Greenwood2007, 186–7) for the suggestion that the Athenians’ decision might not have been as straightforwardly stupid as is often assumed.

17 Saxonhouse links free speech in ancient Athens to its commitment to democratic self-rule, for it is freedom of speech that makes not history or hierarchy the ground of political authority but rather locates it in the free choice of the individual (Reference Saxonhouse2006, 53). Fornara locates the primary meaning of isegoria in freedom from despotism and de-emphasizes its connection to democracy: “The antithesis is between freedom and despotism, and democracy is secondary to it. ἐλευθερωθέντων is the key word; the quality of eleutheria rather than the intrinsic nature of democracy, as a specific form of government, is the issue” (Reference Fornara1971, 48–50, quoting 48.) Rhodes (Reference Rhodes, Harrison and Irwin2018) similarly focuses on isegoria as freedom from tyranny rather than a form of government in its own right. Yet to focus on the negative account of isegoria as freedom from tyranny neglects what it substantively unleashes: its effects on the individual, and how that individual then might or might not affect the city.

18 Cited in Howard (Reference Howard2019).

19 Naketegawa (Reference Naketegawa1988, 270) and Euben (Reference Euben1997, 67) note, “Athenian power derived from the fact … the Athenians above all others embodied freedom in their politeia and fought for it unstintingly.” See also Forsdyke (Reference Forsdyke2001) on how the Histories develop the theme of democracy and civic strength. Schlosser suggests that “the military victories offer only one piece of evidence among many possible examples of support. The context of this assertion shows another, broader set of reasons why isegoria supports collective power: namely the Athenians people’s ability to gather and respond to urgent matters” (Reference Schlosser2020, 77). This is undoubtedly correct, yet it remains important that the “urgent matters” the Athenians must respond to are primarily matters of war—either self-defense or domination of their neighbors.

20 Cammack (Reference Cammack2021, 164) states, “The currency of legitimation was not the quality of deliberation.”

21 Saxonhouse notes the complex reception of this (Reference Saxonhouse2006, 31).

22 Balot notes, “Herodotus shows that the demos’ greedy desires sometimes affected their sound judgment” (Reference Balot2006, 130).

23 Miller notes, “Equality of speech ensures that natural talent will have the chance to be heard and if sufficiently developed, recognized and honored by the demos” (Reference Miller2001, 412).

25 See Moles (Reference Moles, Bakker, de Jong and van Wees2002, 43–8) for an overview of Themistocles’s character as well as a survey of scholarly controversy it occasions. Debate revolves around whether we are to admire or disdain him; I insist, as do Konstan (Reference Konstan1987, 70–2) and Romm (Reference Romm1998, 187–9), that the ambiguity of his character is precisely the point.

26 Scholars have debated the meaning of his “newness.” Some contradict it (Frost Reference Frost1968), some read it as a slur (Podlecki Reference Podlecki1975, 69) or as an invocation of Homer (Fornara Reference Fornara1971, 68), and some find resonance between Themistocles’s origins and those of a key rival (Evans Reference Evans1987).

27 Ober notes the importance of 5.79 and Aristagoras’s diabole but depicts it as an incidental lapse.

28 Collins (Reference Collins2019) likewise notes how Salamis complicates Ober’s account of Athenian democracy.

29 Pelling also notes the parallels between Themistocles’s comportment here and speech in front of the despot (Reference Pelling, Dewald and Marincola2006, 112).

30 Irwin (Reference Irwin2014) argues for the ways in which Herodotus implicates the Athenians with despotic desires; Landauer notes the way the practice of parrhesia in Athens suggests that, historically, democratic Athens did behave remarkably like a tyrant: “One might even say that speaking with parrhesia—offering bold counsel in the face of significant personal risk—was a democratic virtue only insofar as the demos itself was structurally similar to a tyrant” (Reference Landauer2012, 188).

31 Pelling (Reference Pelling, Irwin and Greenwood2007) also notes the bellicosity of Herodotus’s language.

32 For Cyrus’s attitude toward the Greeks and the agora, see Rathnam (Reference Rathnam2018); for the agora and isegoria, see Schlosser (Reference Schlosser2020, 77–8).

33 See Bakker (Reference Bakker, Bakker, de Jong and van Wees2002) for the unfinished task of the Histories.

34 New York Times/Siena College Research Institute, February 9–22, 2022; “America Has a Free Speech Problem,” New York Times, March 18, 2022.

References

REFERENCES

Apfel, Lauren J. 2011. The Advent of Pluralism: Diversity and Conflict in the Age of Sophocles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagg, Samuel. 2018. “The Power of the Multitude: Answering Epistemic Challenges to Democracy.” American Political Science Review 112 (4): 891904.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bakker, Egbert J. 2002. “The Making of History: Herodotus’ Historiēs Apodexis.” In Brill’s Companion to Herodotus, eds. Bakker, Egbert J., de Jong, Irene J. F., and van Wees, Hans, 132. Leiden, NL: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balot, Ryan. 2006. Greek Political Thought. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwin, Baker C.. 1997. “Harm, Liberty, and Free Speech.” Southern California Law Review 70 (4): 9791020.Google Scholar
Baragwanath, Emily. 2008. Motivation and Narrative in Herodotus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bambauer, Derek. 2006. “Shopping Badly: Cognitive Biases, Communications, and the Fallacy of the Marketplace of Ideas.” University of Colorado Law Review 77 (3): 649710.Google Scholar
Bejan, Teresa. 2017. Mere Civility; Disagreement and the Limits of Toleration. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bejan, Teresa. 2021. “Free Expression or Equal Speech?Social Philosophy & Policy Foundation 37 (2): 153–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, Daniel. 2016. The China Model: Political Meritocracy and the Limits of Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Branscome, David. 2013. Textual Rivals: Self-Presentation in Herodotus’ Histories. Lansing: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, Jason. 2017. Against Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cammack, Daniela. 2020. “Were the Ancient Greeks Epistemic Democrats?” In The Discovery of the Fact, eds. Ando, Clifford and Sullivan, William P., 938. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Cammack, Daniela. 2021. “Deliberation and Discussion in Classical Athens.” Journal of Political Philosophy 29 (2): 135–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, D. M. 2004. “Citizen Attribute, Negative Right: A Conceptual Difference between Ancient and Modern Ideas of Freedom of Speech.” In Free Speech in Classical Antiquity, eds. Sluiter, Ineke and Rosen, Ralph, 197220. Leiden, NL: Brill.Google Scholar
Christ, Matthew. 1994. “Herodotean Kings and Historical Inquiry.” Classical Antiquity 13 (2): 167202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Susan D. 2019. “On the Use of Greek History for Life: Josiah Ober’s Athens and Paul Rahe’s Sparta.” Review of Politics 81 (2): 305–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deneen, Patrick J. 2018. Why Liberalism Failed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demont, Paul. 2009. “Figures of Inquiry in Herodotus’s Inquiries.” Mnemosyne 62 (2): 179205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewald, Carolyn. 1987. “Narrative Surface and Authorial Voice in Herodotus’ Histories.” Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20 (1/2): 147–70.Google Scholar
Dewald, Carolyn. 2002. “‘I Didn’t Give My Own Genealogy’: Herodotus and the Authorial Persona.” In Brill’s Companion to Herodotus, eds. Bakker, Egbert J., de Jong, Irene J. F., and van Wees, Hans, 267–89. Leiden, NL: Brill.Google Scholar
Edge, Matt. 2009. “Athens and the Spectrum of Liberty.” History of Political Thought 30 (1): 145.Google Scholar
Euben, Patrick. 1997. Corrupting the Youth: Political Education, Democratic Culture, and Political Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, J. A. S. 1987. “The ‘Recent’ Prominence of Themistocles.” The American Journal of Philology 108 (2): 382–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fornara, Charles.1971. Herodotus: An Interpretative Essay. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Forsdyke, Sara. 2001. “Athenian Democratic Ideology and Herodotus’ Histories.” The American Journal of Philology 122 (3): 329–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frost, Frank. 1968. “Themistocles’ Place in Athenian Politics.” California Studies in Classical Antiquity (1): 105–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glaeser, Edward, and Susstein, Cass. 2014. “Does More Speech Correct Falsehoods?Journal of Legal Studies 43 (1): 6593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gordon, Jill. 1997. “John Stuart Mill and the ‘Marketplace of Ideas.’Social Theory and Practice 23 (2): 235–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gottesman, Alex. 2021. “The Concept of Isegoria.” Polis 38 (2): 175–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magazine, Harper’s. 2020. “A Letter on Justice and Open Debate.” July 7. https://harpers.org/a-letter-on-justice-and-open-debate/.Google Scholar
Haworth, Alan. 2007. “On Mill, Infallibility, and Freedom of Expression.” Res Publica 13 (1): 77100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herodotus. 1987. The History, trans. Grene, David. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hohti, Paavo. 1975. “Freedom of Speech in Speech Sections in the Histories of Herodotus.” Arctos 8: 1927.Google Scholar
How, Walter W., and Wells, J.. 1928. A Commentary on Herodotus. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Howard, Jeffrey. 2019. “Free Speech and Hate Speech.” Annual Review of Political Science 22: 93109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Immerwahr, Henry. 1966. Form and Thought in Herodotus. Chapel Hill, NC: American Philological Association.Google Scholar
Irwin, Elizabeth. 2014. ‘Ethnography and Empire: Homer and the Hippocratic in Herodotus’ Ethiopian Logos, 3.17-26.” Histos 8: 2575.Google Scholar
Jordan, Borimir. 1988. “The Honors for Themistocles after Salamis.” The American Journal of Philology 109 (4): 547–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karagiannis, Nathalie, and Wagner, Peter. 2013. “The Liberty of the Moderns Compared with the Liberty of the Ancients.” In The Greek Polis and the Invention of Democracy: A Politco-Cultural Transformation and Its Interpretations, eds. Arneson, Johann P., Raaflaub, Kurt A., and Wagner, Peter, 371–88. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kateb, George. 1996. “The Freedom of Worthless and Harmful Speech.” In Liberalism without Illusions, ed. Yack, Bernard, 220–40. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kirshner, Alexander. 2016. “Legitimate Opposition, Ostracism, and the Law of Democracy in Ancient Athens.” Journal of Politics 78 (4): 10941106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Konstan, David. 1987. “Persians, Greeks and Empire.” In Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20 (1/2): 5973.Google Scholar
Konstan, David. 2012. “The Two Faces of Parrhesia: Free Speech and Self-Expression in Ancient Greece.” Antichthon 46:113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landauer, Matthew. 2012. “Parrhesia and the ‘Demos Tyrannos’: Frank Speech, Flattery, and Accountability in Democratic Athens.” History of Political Thought 33 (2): 185208.Google Scholar
Landauer, Matthew. 2016. “Democratic Theory and the Athenian Public Sphere.” Polis 33 (1): 3151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landauer, Matthew. 2019. Dangerous Counsel: Accountability and Advice in Ancient Greece. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lateiner, Donald. 1989. The Historical Method of Herodotus. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, John. 1971. “Isegoria at Athens: When did It Begin?Historia 20 (2/3): 129–40.Google Scholar
McWilliams, Susan. 2014. Traveling Back: Toward a Global Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1859] 2003. On Liberty, eds. Bromwich, David and Kateb, George. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Jeff. 2001. “Democratic Characterizations of Democracy: Liberty’s Relationship to Equality and Free Speech in Ancient Athens.” History of Political Thought 22 (3): 400–17.Google Scholar
Moles, John. 2002. “Herodotus and Athens.” In Brill’s Companion to Herodotus, eds. Bakker, Egbert J., de Jong, Irene J. F., and van Wees, Hans, 3352. Leiden, NL: Brill.Google Scholar
Munson, Rosaria. 2001a. Telling Wonders: Ethnographic and Political Discourse in the Work of Herodotus. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munson, Rosaria. 2001b. “Ananke in Herodotus.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 121 (February): 3050.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munson, Rosaria. 2007. “The Trouble with the Ionians: Herodotus and the Beginning of the Ionian Revolt.” In Reading Herodotus: A Study in the Logoi of Book 5 of Herodotus’ Histories, eds. Irwin, Elizabeth and Greenwoo, Emily, 146–67d. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naketegawa, Yoshio. 1988. “Isegoria in Herodotus.” Historia: Zeitschrift fur Alte Geschichte 37 (3): 257–75.Google Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 2012. “Democracy’s Dignity.” American Political Science Review 106 (4): 827–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ober, Josiah. 2017. Demopolis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pelling, Christopher. 2006. “Speech and Narrative.” In The Cambridge Companion to Herodotus, eds. Dewald, Carolyn and Marincola, John, 103–21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pelling, Christopher. 2007. “Aristagoras.” In Reading Herodotus: A Study in the Logoi of Book 5 of Herodotus’ Histories, eds. Irwin, Elizabeth and Greenwood, Emily, 179201. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Podlecki, Anthony. 1975. The Life of Themistocles. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Raaflaub, Kurt A. 1987. “Herodotus, Political Thought, and the Meaning of History.” Herodotus and the Invention of History, Arethusa 20 (1/2): 221–48.Google Scholar
Raaflaub, Kurt. 2004. The Discovery of Freedom in Ancient Greece. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Rathnam, Lindsay Mahon. 2018. “The Madness of Cambyses: Herodotus and the Problem of Inquiry.” Polis 35 (1): 6182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rhodes, P. J. 2018. “Herodotus and Democracy.” Chap. 12 in Interpreting Herodotus, eds. Harrison, Thomas and Irwin, Elizabeth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Riley, Jonathan. 2005. “J. S. Mill’s Doctrine of Free Expression.” Utilitas 17 (2): 147–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Romm, James. 1998. Herodotus. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Saxonhouse, Arlene. 2006. Free Speech and Democracy in Ancient Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schlosser, Joel Alden. 2014. “Herodotean Realism.” Political Theory 42 (3): 239–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlosser, Joel Alden. 2020. Herodotus in the Anthropocene. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarzberg, Melissa. 2014. Counting the Many: The Origins and Limits of Supermajority Rules. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Robert, Sparrow, and Robert, Goodin. 2007. “The Competition of Ideas: Market or Garden?Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 4 (2): 4558.Google Scholar
The New York Times. 2022. “America Has a Free Speech Problem.” March 18. https://www.nytimes.com/2022/03/18/opinion/cancel-culture-free-speech-poll.html.Google Scholar
The Objective. 2020. “A More Specific Letter on Justice and Open Debate.” July 10. https://objectivejournalism.org/2020/07/a-more-specific-letter-on-justice-and-open-debate/.Google Scholar
Thompson, Norma. 1996. Herodotus and the Origins of the Political Community: Arion’s Leap. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Urbinati, Nadia. 2002. Mill on Democracy: From the Athenian Polis to Representative Government. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ward, Ann. 2008. Herodotus and the Philosophy of Empire. Waco, TX: Baylor University Press.Google Scholar
Werhan, Keith. 2008. “The Classical Athenian Ancestry of American Freedom of Speech.The Supreme Court Review 2008 (1): 293347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wu, Tim. 2018. “Is the First Amendment Obsolete?Michigan Law Review 117 (3): 547–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zali, Vasiliki. 2013. “Themistocles’ Exhortation before Salamis: On Herodotus 8.83.” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 53 (3): 461–85.Google Scholar