Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-qxsvm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-05T11:53:43.672Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Meta-Induction and Social Epistemology: Computer Simulations of Prediction Games

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

The justification of induction is of central significance for cross-cultural social epistemology. Different ‘epistemological cultures’ do not only differ in their beliefs, but also in their belief-forming methods and evaluation standards. For an objective comparison of different methods and standards, one needs (meta-)induction over past successes. A notorious obstacle to the problem of justifying induction lies in the fact that the success of object-inductive prediction methods (i.e., methods applied at the level of events) can neither be shown to be universally reliable (Hume's insight) nor to be universally optimal. My proposal towards a solution of the problem of induction is meta-induction. The meta-inductivist applies the principle of induction to all competing prediction methods that are accessible to her. By means of mathematical analysis and computer simulations of prediction games I show that there exist meta-inductive prediction strategies whose success is universally optimal among all accessible prediction strategies, modulo a small short-run loss. The proposed justification of meta-induction is mathematically analytical. It implies, however, an a posteriori justification of object-induction based on the experiences in our world. In the final section I draw conclusions about the significance of meta-induction for the social spread of knowledge and the cultural evolution of cognition, and I relate my results to other simulation results which utilize meta-inductive learning mechanisms.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alexander, J. McKenzie. 2007. The Structural Evolution of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cesa-Bianchi, Nicolo and Lugosi, Gabor. 2006. Prediction, Learning, and Games. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, Richard. 1989. The Selfish Gene. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd et al. 1999. Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Good, Irving J. 1983. Good Thinking. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Greeno, James G. 1971. “Evaluation of Statistical Hypotheses Using Information Transmitted.” In Salmon, W., Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Hegselmann, Rainer. 2002. “Opinion Dynamics and Bounded Confidence Models, Analysis, and Simulation.” Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation (JASSS) 5(3) http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/5/3/2.htmlGoogle Scholar
Hegselmann, Rainer and Krause, Ulrich. 2006. “Truth and Cognitive Division of Labour: First Steps towards a Computer Aided Social Epistemology.” Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation (JASSS) 9(3) http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/9/3/10.htmlGoogle Scholar
Hogarth, Robin M. and Karelaia, Natalia. 2006. “‘Take-The-Best’ and Other Simple Strategies.” Theory and Decision 61: 205–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, Kevin T. 1996. The Logic of Reliable Inquiry. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norton, John. 2003. “A Material Theory of Induction.” Philosophy of Science 70: 647–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans. 1938. Experience and Prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans. 1949. The Theory of Probability. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley C. 1957. “Should We Attempt to Justify Induction?Philosophical Studies 8(3): 45–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard. 2008a. “Third-Person Internalism: A Critical Examination of Externalism and a Foundation-Oriented Alternative.” Acta Analytica 23: 928.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard. 2008b. “The Meta-Inductivist's Winning Strategy in the Prediction Game: A New Approach to Hume's Problem.” Philosophy of Science 75: 278305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard. 2008c. “Meta-Induction. A Game-Theoretical Approach to the Problem of Induction.” In Glymour, C., Westerståhl, D., Wang, W. (eds.), Proceedings from the 13 th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy. London: King's College Publications.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard. 2009. “Meliorative Reliabilist Epistemology: Where Externalism and Internalism Meet.” Grazer Philosophische Studien.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 2000. Choice and Chance. 4th ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 2004. The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar