Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-20T16:53:45.762Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

REAL WORLD PROBLEMS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 July 2018

Abstract

In the real world, there can be constraints on rational decision-making: there can be limitations on what I can know and on what you can know. There can also be constraints on my ability to deliberate or on your ability to deliberate. It is useful to know what the norms of rational deliberation should be in ideal contexts, for fully informed agents, in an ideal world. But it is also useful to know what the norms of rational deliberation should be in the actual world, in non-ideal contexts, for imperfectly informed agents, especially for big, life-changing decisions. That is, we want to know how to deliberate as best we can, given the real-world limitations on what we can know, and given real-world limitations on how we are able to deliberate. In this paper, our concern is with the norms of rational deliberation in certain, important, non-ideal contexts, where the reasoning occurs from the agent's first person, subjective point of view. The norms governing the process of deliberation for real people in the sorts of non-ideal contexts we'll consider need to reflect the way that real agents, with an incomplete grasp on the facts and an imperfect ability to deliberate, can be expected to proceed. Our central contention is that framing and exploring the deliberative process from the first person perspective allows us to uncover and explore important, real-world constraints on boundedly rational agents deliberating from the subjective perspective.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Aumann, R. J. 1976. ‘Agreeing to Disagree.’ Annals of Statistics, 4: 1236–9.Google Scholar
Buchak, L. 2017. Risk and Rationality. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bykvist, K. 2006. ‘Prudence for Changing Selves.’ Utilitas, 18: 264–83.Google Scholar
Fagin, R. and Halpern, J. Y. 1987. ‘Belief, Awareness, and Limited Reasoning.’ Artificial Intelligence, 34: 3976.Google Scholar
Ellsberg, D. 1961. ‘Risk, Ambiguity and the Savage Axioms.’ Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75: 643–69.Google Scholar
Grant, S. and Quiggin, J. 2013 a. ‘Inductive Reasoning about Unawareness.’ Economic Theory 54: 717–55.Google Scholar
Grant, S. and Quiggin, J. 2013 b. ‘Bounded Awareness, Heuristics and the Precautionary Principle.’ Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 93: 1731.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1982. ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia.’ Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 127–36.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. 1990. ‘Formal Logic: Its Scope and Limits.’ New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking Fast and Slow. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Kolodny, N. and MacFarlane, J. 2010. ‘Ifs and Oughts.’ Journal of Philosophy, 107: 115–43.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1986. ‘What Experience Teaches.’ Reprinted in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 262–90. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Modica, S. and Rustichini, A. 1994. ‘Awareness and Partitional Information Structures.’ Theory and Decision, 37: 107–24.Google Scholar
Paul, L. A. 2015. Transformative Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Paul, L. A. 2016. ‘The Subjectively Enduring Self.’ In Phillips, I. (ed.), Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Temporal Experience. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Paul, L. A. 2018. ‘De se Preferences and Empathy for Future Selves.’ Philosophical Perspectives. doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12090.Google Scholar
Paul, L. A.and Healy, K. 2018. ‘Transformative Treatments.’ Noûs, 52: 320–35.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. 2015. ‘Transformative Experience and Decision Theory.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91: 766–74.Google Scholar
Quiggin, J. 1982. ‘A Theory of Anticipated Utility.’ Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3: 323–43.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1926. ‘Truth and Probability.’ In Braithwaite, R. B. (ed.), Ramsey, F. P., 1931, The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays, Ch. VII, pp. 156–98. London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.; New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace and Company.Google Scholar
Robbins, L. 1938. ‘Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: A Comment.’ Economic Journal, 48: 635–41.Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. 1954. Foundations of Statistics. New York, NY: Wiley.Google Scholar
Shear, E. and Quiggin, J. 2017. ‘Justification Logic with Confidence.’ Working Paper, University of Queensland.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. 2018. ‘Freedom.’ The Holberg Lecture, Oslo, Norway.Google Scholar
Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. R. 2008. Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Todd, P. M. and Gigerenzer, G. 2012. Ecological Rationality: Intelligence in the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1983. ‘Extensional Versus Intuitive Reasoning: The Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment.’ Psychological Review 90, 4. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.90.4.293.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1981. ‘Internal and External Reasons.’ In Moral Luck, pp. 101–13. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Winship, C. Ms. ‘Extrarationality.’Google Scholar