Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-21T00:14:10.827Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why No True Reliabilist Should Endorse Reliabilism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 November 2020

Kristoffer Ahlstrom-Vij*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Birkbeck, University of London, UK
Jeffrey S. Dunn
Affiliation:
Department of Religion, Philosophy, and History, University of Agder, Norway

Abstract

Critics have recently argued that reliabilists face trade-off problems, forcing them to condone intuitively unjustified beliefs when they generate lots of true belief further downstream. What these critics overlook is that reliabilism entails that there are side-constraints on belief-formation, on account of which there are some things you should not believe, even if doing so would have very good epistemic consequences. However, we argue that by embracing side-constraints the reliabilist faces a dilemma: she can either hold on to reliabilism, and with it aforementioned side-constraints, but then needs to explain why we should allow the pursuit of justification to get in the way of the acquisition of true belief; or she can deny that there are side-constraints – and in effect give up on reliabilism. We'll suggest that anyone moved by the considerations that likely attract people to reliabilism in the first place – the idea the true belief is good, and as such should be promoted – should go for the second horn, and instead pursue a form of epistemic utilitarianism.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ahlstrom-Vij, K. (2013). Epistemic Paternalism: A Defence. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahlstrom-Vij, K. (2015). ‘The Social Virtue of Blind Deference.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91(3), 545–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahlstrom-Vij, K. (2017). ‘Judgment and Agency, by Ernest Sosa.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95(1), 196–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahlstrom-Vij, K. and Dunn, J. (2014). ‘A Defence of Epistemic Consequentialism.’ Philosophical Quarterly 64(257), 541–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berker, S. (2013 a). ‘Epistemic Teleology and the Separateness of Propositions.Philosophical Review 122(3), 337–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berker, S. (2013 b). ‘The Rejection of Epistemic Consequentialism.Philosophical Issues 23(1), 363–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, M. and Trout, J.D. (2004). Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coady, D. (2010). ‘Two Concepts of Epistemic Injustice.’ Episteme 7(2), 101–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driver, J. (2018). ‘The “Consequentialism” in “Epistemic Consequentialism”.’ In Ahlstrom-Vij, K. and Dunn, J. (eds), Epistemic Consequentialism, pp. 113–22. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dunn, J. (2012). ‘Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?Episteme 9(3), 225–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunn, J. and Ahlstrom-Vij, K. (2017). ‘Is Reliabilism a Form of Consequentialism?American Philosophical Quarterly 54(2), 183–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Firth, R. (1981). ‘Epistemic Merit, Intrinsic and Instrumental.Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 55(1), 523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2010). Relying on Others. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1978). ‘Epistemics: The Regulative Theory of Cognition.Journal of Philosophy 75(10), 509–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1979). ‘What Is Justified Belief?’ In Pappas, G. (ed.), Justification and Knowledge, pp. 1–23. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1992 a). ‘Foundations of Social Epistemic.’ In Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive Sciences, pp. 179–208. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1992 b). ‘Epistemic Folkways and Scientific Epistemology.’ In Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive Sciences, pp. 155–77. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1992 c). ‘Strong and Weak Justification.’ In Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive Sciences, pp. 127–42. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1999). Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (2001). ‘Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(1), 85110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (2015). ‘Reliabilism, Veritism, and Epistemic Consequentialism.’ Episteme 12(2), 131–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greaves, H. (2013). ‘Epistemic Decision Theory.Mind 122(488), 915–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, J. (2010). Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazlett, A. (2013). A Luxury of the Understanding: On the Value of True Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1975 [1777]). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, 3rd edition. Selby-Bigge, L.A. and Nidditch, P.H. (eds). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Jenkins, C. (2007). ‘Entitlement and Rationality.Synthese 157(1), 2545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahan, D. (2010). ‘Fixing the Communications Failure.Nature 463(21), 296–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahan, D. (2016). ‘The Politically Motivated Reasoning Paradigm, Part 1: What Politically Motivated Reasoning Is and How to Measure It.’ In R. Scott and S. Kosslyn (eds), Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences, pp. 1–16. New York, NY: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahan, D., Braman, D., Cohen, G.L., Gastil, J. and Slovic, P. (2010). ‘Who Fears the HPV Vaccine, Who Doesn't, and Why? An Experimental Study of the Mechanisms of Cultural Cognition.Law and Human Behavior 34(6), 501516.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahan, D., Jenkins-Smith, H., Tarantola, T., Silva, C.L. and Braman, D. (2015). ‘Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization: Testing a Two-Channel Model of Science Communication.Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 658(1), 192222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1990). ‘The Division of Cognitive Labor.’ Journal of Philosophy 87(1), 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and its Place in Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, H. (2012). On Reflection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, H. (2018). ‘The Naturalistic Origins of Epistemic Consequentialism.’ In Ahlstrom-Vij, K. and Dunn, J. (eds), Epistemic Consequentialism, pp. 70–84. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, C. and Pettit, P. (2004). ‘An Epistemic Free-riding Problem?’ In Catton, P. and Macdonals, G. (eds), Karl Popper: Critical Appraisals, pp. 128–58. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the Truth Connection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G.E. (1988 [1902]). Principia Ethica. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. (1981 [1874]). The Methods of Ethics, 7th edition. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (2003). ‘Neutral and Relative Value after Moore.’ Ethics 113, 576–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2009). Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, J.J. (1976). ‘Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem.’ Monist 59(2), 204–17.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed