Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T01:43:36.626Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE SAXON REPUBLIC AND ANCIENT CONSTITUTION IN THE STANDING ARMY CONTROVERSY, 1697–1699

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 October 2018

ASHLEY WALSH*
Affiliation:
Downing College, Cambridge
*
Downing College, Regent Street, Cambridge, cb2 1dqajw246@cam.ac.uk

Abstract

The pamphlet controversy caused by the proposal of William III to maintain a peacetime standing army following the Treaty of Ryswick (1697) tends to be understood as a confrontation of classicists and moderns in which the king's supporters argued that modern commerce had changed the nature of warfare and his opponents drew on classical republicanism to defend the county militia. But this characterization neglects the centrality of the Saxon republic and ancient constitution in the debate. English opponents of the standing army, including Walter Moyle, John Trenchard, and John Toland, went further than adapting the republicanism of James Harrington, who had rejected ancient constitutionalism during the Interregnum, to the restored monarchy. Their thought was more Saxon than classical and, in the case of Reverend Samuel Johnson, it was entirely so. However, the Scot, Andrew Fletcher of Saltoun, adapted neo-Harringtonian arguments to argue that modern politics could no longer be understood by their Gothic precedents. Above all, the king's supporters needed either to engage ancient constitutionalists on their own terms, as did one anonymous pamphleteer, or, as in the cases of John, Lord Somers, and Daniel Defoe, reject the relevance of ancient constitutionalism and Saxon republicanism completely.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I thank Mark Goldie, Callum Murrell, Katherine A. East, and the two peer reviewers for offering perceptive comments on earlier drafts of this article. I am grateful to the Sir John Plumb Charitable Trust for financial support in undertaking this research.

References

1 Moyle, Walter and Trenchard, John, An argument, shewing that a standing army is inconsistent with a free government and absolutely destructive to the constitution of the English monarchy (London, 1697), p. 26Google Scholar.

2 For early studies of the controversy, see Miller, E. Arnold, ‘Some arguments used by English pamphleteers, 1697–1700, concerning a standing army’, Journal of Modern History, 18 (1946), pp. 306–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Schwoerer, Lois, ‘The literature of the standing army controversy, 1697–1699’, Huntington Library Quarterly, 28 (1965), pp. 187212CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, The role of William III of England in the standing army controversy – 1697–1699’, Journal of British Studies, 5 (1966), pp. 7494CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, ‘No standing armies!’ The antiarmy ideology in seventeenth-century England (Baltimore, MD, 1974), pp. 155–87Google Scholar; Western, J. R., The English militia in the eighteenth century: the story of a political issue, 1660–1802 (London, 1965), pp. 89103Google Scholar.

3 Moyle and Trenchard, Argument, p. 18; Toland, John, The militia reform'd (London, 1698), p. 75Google Scholar; Trenchard, John, A short history of standing armies in England (London, 1698), p. 2Google Scholar.

4 See Worden, A. B., ‘Introduction’, in Ludlow, Edmund, A voyce from the watch tower, ed. Worden, A. B. (Camden Fourth Series, 21, London, 1978), pp. 1738, 41Google Scholar.

5 Hayton, D. W., ed., The parliamentary diary of Sir Richard Cocks, 1698–1702 (Oxford, 1996), pp. 31–2Google Scholar.

6 Ibid., p. 31. See also pp. 16, 122–3, 187, 199–200, 280–1.

7 Hayton, D. W., ed., Debates in the House of Commons, 1697–1699 (Camden Fourth Series, 34, London, 1987), pp. 343407Google Scholar. See also Horwitz, H. G., Parliament, policy and politics in the reign of William III (Manchester, 1977), pp. 224–7, 229Google Scholar.

8 Shaftesbury to Molesworth, 6 Jan. 1708/9, Letters from the right honourable the late earl of Shaftesbury to Robert Molesworth (London, 1721), p. 23Google Scholar.

9 Knights, Mark, Representation and misrepresentation in later Stuart Britain: partisanship and political culture (Oxford, 2005)Google Scholar.

10 Anon., A list of King James's Irish and popish forces in France (London, 1698)Google Scholar.

11 Moyle, Walter, The second part of an argument shewing that a standing army is inconsistent with a free government (London, 1697), p. 26Google Scholar.

12 For the opposition, see, classically, Fink, Zera, The classical republicans: an essay in the recovery of a pattern of thought in seventeenth-century England (Evanston, IL, 1945), p. 185Google Scholar; Robbins, Caroline, The eighteenth-century commonwealthman (Cambridge, MA, 1959), pp. 4, 99, 103–5CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 For civic humanism, see Baron, Hans, The crisis of the early Italian Renaissance: civic humanism and republican liberty in an age of classicism and tyranny (Princeton, NJ, 1955)Google Scholar; Pocock, J. G. A., The Machiavellian moment: Florentine political thought and the Atlantic republican tradition (Cambridge, 1975), chs. 1014Google Scholar.

14 Pocock, Machiavellian moment, pp. 423–32. See also Brewer, John, The sinews of power: war, money, and the English state, 1688–1783 (Cambridge, MA, 1990)Google Scholar.

15 Pocock, Machiavellian moment, pp. 426–36.

16 Robertson, John, ‘The Scottish Enlightenment at the limits of the civic tradition’, in Hont, István and Ignatieff, Michael, eds., Wealth and virtue: the shaping of political economy in the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, 1983), pp. 138–40Google Scholar; idem, The Scottish Enlightenment and the militia issue (Edinburgh, 1980), pp. 913Google Scholar.

17 Pocock, J. G. A., The ancient constitution and the feudal law: a study of English historical thought in the seventeenth century (revised edn, Cambridge, 1987), pp. 242–3, 268–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Burgess, Glenn, The politics of the ancient constitution: an introduction to English political thought, 1600–1642 (Basingstoke, 1992), pp. 3757CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cromartie, Alan, Sir Matthew Hale, 1609–1676: law, religion and natural philosophy (Cambridge, 1995), pp. 1129, 30–9, 98–102, 119–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Randolph, Julia, Common law and Enlightenment in England, 1689–1750 (Woodbridge, 2013), pp. 169–70Google Scholar.

18 Burgess, Politics of the ancient constitution.

19 Smith, R. J., The Gothic bequest: medieval institutions in British political thought, 1688–1863 (Cambridge, 1987)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sandoz, Ellis, ed., The roots of liberty: Magna Carta, ancient constitution, and the Anglo-American tradition of rule of law (Indianapolis, IN, 1993)Google Scholar; Kidd, Colin, British identities before nationalism: ethnicity and nationhood in the Atlantic world, 1600–1800 (Cambridge, 2004)Google Scholar; Randolph, Common law and Enlightenment.

20 Kenyon, J. P., Revolution principles: the politics of party, 1689–1720 (Cambridge, 1977), pp. 35–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 Moyle and Trenchard, Argument, p. 13.

22 Ibid., p. 14.

23 Trenchard, Short history, p. iv.

24 Pocock, Ancient constitution, pp. 372–4.

25 Pocock, Machiavellian moment, pp. 406–61.

26 Pocock, Ancient constitution, pp. 18–19; idem, Machiavellian moment, pp. 340–1. But, as Glenn Burgess and Janelle Greenberg have shown, ancient constitutionalists could propose reform and even rebellion and regicide. See Burgess, Politics of the ancient constitution, p. 6; Greenberg, Janelle, The radical face of the ancient constitution: St Edward's ‘laws’ in early modern political thought (Cambridge, 2006)Google Scholar. For the reception of Roman law among ancient constitutionalists, see Skinner, Quentin, ‘Classical liberty, Renaissance translation and the English Civil War’, in Visions of politics, ii: Renaissance virtues (Cambridge, 2002), pp. 308–43Google Scholar.

27 Johnson, Reverend Samuel, The second part of the confutation of the ballancing letter (London, 1700), p. 1Google Scholar.

28 Toland, Militia reform'd, p. 69.

29 Worden, A. B., ‘The Revolution of 1688–9 and the English republican tradition’, in Israel, Jonathan, ed., The Anglo-Dutch moment: essays on the Glorious Revolution and its world impact (Cambridge, 1981), pp. 242–3Google Scholar. See also Norbrook, David, Writing the English Republic: poetry, rhetoric and politics, 1627–1660 (Cambridge, 1999)Google Scholar; Scott, Jonathan, Commonwealth principles: republican writing of the English revolution (Cambridge, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Worden, ‘Revolution of 1688–9’, pp. 248–9.

31 Among Protestant humanist accounts of ancient constitutionalism in Europe, English republican favourites included François Hotman, Francogallia (1573), George Buchanan, De jure regni apud Scotos (1579), and Hugo Grotius, Liber de antiquitate reipublicae Batavicae (1610).

32 Robertson, John, ‘Universal monarchy and the liberties of Europe: David Hume's critique of an English whig doctrine’, in Phillipson, Nicholas and Skinner, Quentin, eds., Political discourse in early modern Britain (Cambridge, 1993), pp. 349–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

33 Moyle and Trenchard, Argument, pp. 2–3.

34 Toland, Militia reform'd, p. 93.

35 Moyle and Trenchard, Argument, p. 29.

36 Harrington, James, The political works of James Harrington, ed. Pocock, J. G. A. (Cambridge, 1977), p. 196Google Scholar.

37 Ibid., p. 198.

38 For another, see Mahlberg, Gaby, Henry Neville and English republican culture in the seventeenth century: dreaming of another game (Manchester, 2009), pp. 139–86Google Scholar.

39 Molesworth, Robert, An account of Denmark, with Francogallia and some considerations for the promoting of agriculture and employing the poor, ed. Champion, Justin (Indianapolis, IN, 2011), p. 174Google Scholar.

40 Moyle and Trenchard, Argument, pp. 2–3.

41 Ibid., p. 22.

42 Moyle, Second part of an argument, pp. 7–8.

43 Toland, Militia reform'd, p. 18.

44 Johnson, Reverend Samuel, A confutation of a late pamphlet (London, 1698), p. 31Google Scholar.

45 Johnson, Second part of the confutation, p. 80.

46 Greenberg, Radical face. See also Zook, Melinda, ‘Early whig ideology, ancient constitutionalism, and the Reverend Samuel Johnson’, Journal of British Studies, 32 (1993), pp. 139–65, at pp. 141–2, 143–4, 157–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, Radical whigs and conspiratorial politics in late Stuart England (University Park, PA, 1999), pp. 60, 62, 165–6Google Scholar.

47 Johnson, Second part of the confutation, p. 67.

48 Ibid., pp. 76–7. See Horn, Andrew, The booke called, the mirrour of justices (London, 1646), p. 9Google Scholar.

49 Johnson, Second part of the confutation, preface.

50 Bacon, Nathaniel, The continuation of an historicall discourse of the government of England (London, 1651), p. 195Google Scholar.

51 Johnson, Confutation, p. 23.

52 Greenberg, Radical face, p. 77.

53 Johnson, Confutation, pp. 26, 31, 19.

54 Goldie, Mark, ‘The unacknowledged republic: officeholding in early modern England’, in Harris, Tim, ed., The politics of the excluded, c. 1500–1850 (Basingstoke, 2001), p. 182Google Scholar. See also Walsh, Ashley, ‘John Streater and the Saxon republic’, History of Political Thought, 39 (2018), pp. 5782Google Scholar.

55 See Collinson, Patrick, ‘The monarchical republic of Queen Elizabeth I’, Bulletin of the John Rylands Library, 69 (1987), pp. 394424CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McDiarmid, John F., ed., The monarchical republic of early modern England: essays in response to Patrick Collinson (Aldershot, 2007)Google Scholar.

56 Skinner, Quentin, Liberty before liberalism (Cambridge, 1998)Google Scholar. For an alternative account, emphasizing the Greek origins of classical republicanism in ideas of happiness and justice, see Nelson, Eric, The Greek tradition in republican thought (Cambridge, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Moyle and Trenchard, Argument, p. 5.

58 Toland, Militia reform'd, p. 32.

59 Rahe, Paul, Republics ancient and modern: classical republicanism and the American Revolution (Chapel Hill, NC, 1992), pp. 429–30, 998Google Scholar; idem, Against throne and altar: Machiavelli and political theory under the English republic (Cambridge, 2008)Google Scholar. See also Sullivan, Vickie, ‘The civic humanist portrait of Machiavelli's English successors’, History of Political Thought, 15 (1994), pp. 7396Google Scholar; idem, Machiavelli, Hobbes, and the formation of a liberal republicanism in England (Cambridge, 2004)Google Scholar; Ward, Lee, The politics of liberty in England and Revolutionary America (Cambridge, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

60 John, Lord Somers, A letter ballancing the necessity of keeping a land-force in times of peace, with the dangers that may follow on it (London, 1697), p. 15Google Scholar; Trenchard, John, A letter from the author of the argument against a standing army, to the author of the ballancing letter (London, 1697), pp. 14, 15Google Scholar.

61 Moyle and Trenchard, Argument, pp. 7, 4.

62 Johnson, Second part of the confutation, p. 1.

63 Somers, Letter ballancing, p. 11.

64 Trenchard, Letter to the author of the ballancing letter, p. 9.

65 Johnson, Confutation, p. 11.

66 Toland, Militia reform'd, pp. 92–4.

67 For Sidney, see Scott, Jonathan, Algernon Sidney and the Restoration crisis, 1677–1683 (Cambridge, 1991), pp. 245–7, 257–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

68 Sidney, Algernon, Discourses concerning government, ed. West, Thomas (Indianapolis, IN, 1996), pp. 363–4Google Scholar.

69 Ibid., p. 376.

70 Ibid., pp. 366–7.

71 Ibid., pp. 252–3.

72 Ibid., p. 458.

73 See Kidd, British identities before nationalism, pp. 211–49.

74 Sidney, Discourses, p. 487. See also Sidney, Algernon, Court maxims, ed. Blom, Hans, Mulier, Eco Haitsma, and Janse, Ronald (Cambridge, 1996), pp. 67–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 Sidney, Discourses, pp. 526–7.

76 Ibid., p. 497.

77 Clare Jackson, Restoration Scotland, 1660–1690: royalist politics, religion and ideas (Woodbridge, 2002), p. 94.

78 For a general history, see Harris, Tim, Revolution: the great crisis of the British monarchy, 1685–1720 (London, 2006)Google Scholar.

79 Riley, P. W. J., King William and the Scottish politicians (Edinburgh, 1979), pp. 125, 150–1Google Scholar.

80 Fletcher, Andrew, Political works, ed. Robertson, John (Cambridge, 1997), pp. 34Google Scholar. See also Fletcher, Andrew, A discourse concerning militias and standing armies (London, 1697), pp. 511Google Scholar.

81 Fletcher, Discourse concerning militias, p. 7.

82 Ibid., p. 5; Fletcher, Political works, p. 6.

83 Fletcher, Political works, p. 2.

84 Ibid., pp. 5, 6.

85 Ibid., p. 43.

86 Ibid., p. 23.

87 Defoe, Daniel, Argument shewing, that a standing army, with consent of parliament, is not inconsistent with a free government (London, 1698), p. 15Google Scholar.

88 Ibid.

89 Defoe, Daniel, Some reflections on a pamphlet lately published (London, 1697), p. 16Google Scholar.

90 Defoe, Argument, p. 3.

91 Somers, Letter ballancing, pp. 9–10.

92 Ibid., p. 10.

93 Defoe, Argument, p. 3.

94 Ibid., p. 16.

95 Anon., A letter to A, B, C, D, E, F, &c. concerning their argument about a standing army (London, 1698)Google Scholar.

96 Ibid., p. 9.

97 Ibid., pp. 11–12.

98 For the Brady controversy, see Pocock, Ancient constitution, pp. 182–228.

99 Seaberg, R. B., ‘The Norman conquest and the common law: the Levellers and the argument from continuity’, Historical Journal, 24 (1981), pp. 791806CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Greenberg, Radical face, pp. 253–64, 269–70, 280–6.

100 Anon., Letter, p. 11.

101 Ibid., p. 14. See also Defoe, The true-born Englishman (London, 1701), lines 195–6, 229–32, 203–4Google Scholar.

102 Anon., Letter, p. 12.

103 Ibid., pp. 15–16.

104 Ibid., p. 21.

105 Ibid., p. 23.

106 Burgess, Politics of the ancient constitution, pp. 26–7.

107 Anon., Letter, p. 24.

108 Burton, I. F., Riley, P. W. J., and Rowlands, E., ‘Political parties in the reigns of William III and Anne: the evidence of division lists’, Bulletin of the Institute of Historical Research, special supplement no. 7 (1968), pp. 43, 33nGoogle Scholar.

109 Worden, ‘Introduction’, in Ludlow, Voyce from the watchtower, pp. 19, 39–41, 42–7; Klein, Lawrence E., Shaftesbury and the culture of politeness: moral discourse and cultural politics in early eighteenth-century England (Cambridge, 1994), pp. 126, 137–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

110 Justin Champion, ‘Introduction’, in Molesworth, Account of Denmark, pp. ix–xii, xix–xxi.

111 Shaftesbury to Molesworth, 12 Jan. 1708/9, Letters, p. 26. See Cruickshanks, Eveline, Handley, Stuart, and Hayton, D. W., eds., The history of parliament: the House of Commons, 1690–1715 (5 vols., Cambridge, 2002), iii, pp. 70–2, iv, pp. 826–35Google Scholar.

112 Cooper, Anthony Ashley, third earl of Shaftesbury, Characteristics of men, manners, opinions, times, ed. Klein, Lawrence E. (Cambridge, 1999), p. 403Google Scholar.

113 See Klein, Culture of politeness, pp. 123–37.

114 Browning, Reed, Political and constitutional ideas of the court whigs (Baton Rouge, LA, 1982), pp. 3566Google Scholar.

115 John, Henry St, Bolingbroke, Viscount, The works of the late right honourable Henry St John, Viscount Bolingbroke (8 vols., London, 1809), ii, pp. 158–9, 162Google Scholar.

116 Sir Blackstone, William, Commentaries on the laws of England (2 vols., Philadelphia, PA, 1893), i, pp. 408–9Google Scholar.

117 Burgh, James, Political disquisitions (3 vols., London, 1774–5), ii, p. 345Google Scholar.

118 Cartwright, Major John, An appeal, civil and military, on the subject of the English constitution (London, 1799), p. viGoogle Scholar. See also George Owers, ‘The political thought of Major John Cartwright’ (Ph.D. thesis, Cambridge, 2015), pp. 186–256.

119 Pocock, J. G. A., Barbarism and religion (6 vols., Cambridge, 1999–2015), i, pp. 94120CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

120 Cress, Lawrence Delbert, Citizens in arms: the army and militia in American society to the war of 1812 (Chapel Hill, NC, 1982), pp. 42, 45–6, 158Google Scholar.