We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
Zan, Luca 2016. Complexity, anachronism and time-parochialism: historicising strategy while strategising history. Business History, Vol. 58, Issue. 4, p. 571.
Asprem, Egil 2015. Dis/unity of Knowledge: Models for the Study of Modern Esotericism and Science. Numen, Vol. 62, Issue. 5-6, p. 538.
Maines, R. 2012. The Asbestos Litigation Master Narrative: Building Codes, Engineering Standards, and "Retroactive Inculpation". Enterprise and Society, Vol. 13, Issue. 4, p. 862.
Maines, Rachel 2012. The Asbestos Litigation Master Narrative: Building Codes, Engineering Standards, and “Retroactive Inculpation”. Enterprise and Society, Vol. 13, Issue. 04, p. 862.
Abadía, Oscar Moro 2011. Hermeneutical contributions to the history of science: Gadamer on ‘presentism’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, Vol. 42, Issue. 2, p. 372.
White, Michael V. 2009. Hunting a precursor: The limits of Mountifort Longfield on utility and value. The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, Vol. 16, Issue. 1, p. 65.
Abadía, Oscar Moro 2008. Beyond the Whig history interpretation of history: lessons on ‘presentism’ from Hélène Metzger. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, Vol. 39, Issue. 2, p. 194.
Tosh, Nick 2003. Anachronism and retrospective explanation: in defence of a present-centred history of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, Vol. 34, Issue. 3, p. 647.
Raven, Diederick 2001. How not to explain the Great Divide. Social Science Information, Vol. 40, Issue. 3, p. 373.
da Costa, Palmira Fontes 2001. The natural history files. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, Vol. 32, Issue. 3, p. 583.
Raven, Diederick 1999. Elizabeth eisenstein and the impact of printing. European Review of History: Revue européenne d'histoire, Vol. 6, Issue. 2, p. 223.
Dear, Peter 1995. Cultural History of Science. Science, Technology, & Human Values, Vol. 20, Issue. 2, p. 150.
1991. Presentism and the indeterminacy of translation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, Vol. 22, Issue. 2, p. 321.
van Krieken, Robert 1989. Violence, Self-Discipline and Modernity: Beyond the ‘Civilizing Process’. The Sociological Review, Vol. 37, Issue. 2, p. 193.
Cunningham, Andrew 1988. Getting the game right: Some plain words on the identity and invention of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, Vol. 19, Issue. 3, p. 365.
View all Google Scholar citations for this article.
In a previous article, we examined Herbert Butterfield's identification of a certain pattern of anachronism in historical writing, in his classic book The whig interpretation of history (1931). In the decades since that book was originally published, Butterfield's designation has been extended far beyond its original domain of political and religious history. The terms ‘whig history’ and ‘whiggish history’ have passed into the common parlance of historians. This very success, however, has masked a failure to define the nature of such anachronistic writing, its causes and remedies. Such definition is all the more necessary since Butterfield's own attempts were clearly inadequate. Building upon and amending certain tentative formulations of Butterfield's, we defined the root of the anachronistic error as present-centredness: that is, that the historian, in seeking to study, reconstruct and write about the past, is constrained by necessarily starting from the perceptual and conceptual categories of the present.
1 Wilson, Adrian and Ashplant, T. G., ‘Whig history and present-centred history’, The Historical Journal, 30, 1 (1988), 1–16.
2 For instance, Shorter, Edward, The making of the modern family (New York, 1975); Stone, Lawrence, The family, sex and marriage in England 1500–1800 (London, 1977).
3 Ariès, Philippe, L'Enfant et la vie familiale sous l'ancien règime (Paris, 1960; subsequent editions Paris, 1973, 1975); Centuries of childhood (trans. Baldick, Robert, London, 1962). The quoted passage is in Centuries, p. 406.
4 Wilson, Adrian, ‘The infancy of the history of childhood: an appraisal of Philippe Ariès’, History and Theory, XIX (1980), 132–53.
5 Ibid. p. 148. The use of the term ‘evidence’ here was, of course, inadequate. See Wilson, and Ashplant, , ‘Whig history and present-centred history’, pp. 12–13.
6 Wilson, , ‘Infancy of the history of childhood’, pp. 147–9 (categories); 139, 143, 151 (absences); 152 (evidence).
7 Thomas, Keith, Religion and the decline of magic (Harmondsworth, Peregrine edition, 1978), p. x. The epigraph from George Gifford appears on p. xxi.
8 Compare Butterfield on Aquinas, cited in Wilson, and Ashplant, , ‘Whig history and present-centred history’, p. 4.
9 See, however, Religion and the decline of magic, pp. 689, 691.
10 See for example ibid. pp. 640, 661 (Ady); 663, 674 (Scot); 501 (Hobbes and Selden).
11 Ibid. pp. 767–800, particularly 785–94. We quote from pp. 791–2, 794. Compare also pp. 331–2 (magic); 415–18 (astrology); 507–14, especially 513 (ancient prophecy); 691 (witchcraft). In each case, the root cause of the decline of magical beliefs is seen as mental. A functional or technological explanation is, however, supplied for the decline of two ‘allied beliefs’: ghosts (723–4) and the observance of times (744–5).
12 See Webster, Charles, The great instauration (London, 1975) and From Paracelsus to Newton (Cambridge, 1982); Curry, Patrick, ‘Revisions of science and magic’, History of Science, XXIII (1985), 299–325; Schaffer, Simon, ‘Occultism and reason’, in Holland, A.J. (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (London, 1985), 117–43. Quotes concerning Newton are from Thomas, , Religion and the decline of magic, pp. 771, 93, 268.
13 Thomas, , Religion and the decline of magic, Foreword, p. x.
14 Thompson, E. P., The making of the English working class (London, 1963; Harmondsworth, Pelican, 1968), p. 13.
15 Hexter, J. H., Reappraisals in history (London, 1961), pp. 194–6 (we quote from p. 195).
16 Skinner, , ‘Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas’, History and Theory, VIII (1969), 3–53. Quotations which follow are from pp. 10–11.
17 Ibid. p. 52.
18 ‘There is a tendency…to suppose that the best, not merely the inescapable, point of vantage from which to survey the ideas of the past must be our present situation, because it is by definition the most highly evolved’ (ibid. p. 52), our emphasis.
19 Ibid. pp. 5–6.
20 This is argued in Andrew Cunningham, ‘Getting the game right: some plain words on the identity and invention of science’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science (forthcoming).
21 The ways in which, and the extent to which, the discipline of history is necessarily present-centred are difficult questions which demand extended treatment. Some considerations are offered in our conclusion, below. The fact that both object of study, and interpretation, shift as history is written from different presents has often been noted in the context of particular historiographical issues. Among many examples, note Geyl, Pieter, Napoleon for and against (first published Paris, 1946), which examines successive interpretations of Napoleon by French historians during the nineteenth century; Cannadine, David, ‘The present and the past in the English industrial revolution 1880–1980’, Past and Present, 103 (1984), 131–72, which delineates four different periods in the interpretation of the industrial revolution during the past century, and links each of them to contemporary economic experience (e.g. optimistic histories being written during the post-war boom of the 1950s and '60s); Samuel, Raphael, ‘British Marxist historians 1880–1980: Part I’, New Left Review, 120 (1980), pp. 21–96, which shows how even a group of historians with a shared intellectual and political commitment have, over the past hundred years, taken widely differing views as to what constitutes the object of their historical enquiry; and Eley, Geoff and Nield, Keith, ‘Why does social history ignore politics?’, Social History, v (1980), pp. 249–71, which uncovers the ways in which British and German historians, writing about their own labour movements in the twentieth century, each compare it with an implicit ideal type drawn from the other country.
22 See note 31 below.
23 Wrigley, E. A. and Schofield, R. S., The population history of England 1541–1871: a reconstruction (London, 1981).
24 See note 12 above.
25 Goldstein, Leon J., Historical knowing (Austin, Texas, 1976).
26 Collingwood, R. G., An autobiography (Oxford, 1939), chapter 8, and The idea of history (Oxford, 1946), pp. 257–81; Wilson, , ‘Infancy of the history of childhood’, p. 146.
27 Willughby, Percival, Observations in midwifery (Warwick, 1863; reprint, Wakefield, 1972; originally written c. 1660–72).
28 See Harley, David, ‘Ignorant midwives – a persistent stereotype’, The Society for the Social History of Medicine Bulletin, 28 (1981), 6–9.
29 Wilson, Adrian, ‘Participant or patient? Seventeenth century childbirth from the mother's point of view’, in Porter, Roy (ed.), Patients and practitioners (Cambridge, 1985), pp. 129–44, and ‘William Hunter and the varieties of man-midwifery’, in Bynum, W. F. and Porter, Roy (eds.), William Hunter and the eighteenth-century medical world (Cambridge, 1985), pp. 343–69, particularly p. 364. In applying this approach to Willughby's Observations, A.F.W. was greatly helped by the critical advice of Andrew Cunningham, William Lamont and Roger Schofield.
30 In The practice of history (London, 1967; London, Fontana, 1969), Geoffrey Elton has enunciated the following principle of historical method: ‘There is a single question which the researcher must ask himself in assessing his evidence: how and why did this come into existence?’ (p. 100). This and similar injunctions in the same work (e.g. pp. 93, 102, 103, 111) seem to approach closely to the methodological conception which we have been advancing. However, as will become clear below, Elton's formulation differs importantly from our own.
31 Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, 5th series, XXVII, 41–68.
32 Elton, , Practice of history, pp. 96–108. Relatedly, Elton's usage of ‘source’ and ‘evidence’ differs from our own. For Elton, ‘the sources’ are ‘the physical survivals from the events to be studied’ (ibid. 88); or, in another place, ‘Evidence is the surviving deposit of an historical event’ (113). We introduce the term relic to describe materials surviving from the past independently of the historian's use of those materials; and we distinguish between ‘sources’ and ‘evidence’. See Wilson, and Ashplant, , ‘Whig history and present-centred history’, pp. 12–13. This helps to make visible the fact that the relationship between the events of the past and the relics of the past is much more complex than the process of ‘deposit’ which Elton's formulation assumes.
33 Another response to the structural nature of the present-centred approach to the past would be to take it as an argument in favour of some version of historical relativism. All there ever can be, it might be argued, are a variety of present-centred readings of past sources, present-centred constructions of past activities. We hold that there can be more and less reliable interpretations of past sources, and hence that it is meaningful to talk of historical ‘knowledge’ and ‘misunderstanding’. But the relationship between our delineation of present-centredness, and the question of historical relativism, demands a fuller treatment elsewhere.
* For their help with various aspects of this papers, we wish to thank David Amigoni, Andrew Cunningham, Patrick Curry, Geoffrey Elton, Rob Iliffe, Susan Morgan, Simon Schaffer, and Stephen Yeo. For financial support in this study Adrian Wilson wishes to thank the Wellcome Trust.
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this journal to your organisation's collection.
Full text views reflects the number of PDF downloads, PDFs sent to Google Drive, Dropbox and Kindle and HTML full text views.
Abstract views reflect the number of visits to the article landing page.
* Views captured on Cambridge Core between September 2016 - 26th April 2018. This data will be updated every 24 hours.