Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-r5zm4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-18T05:38:09.003Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Is Psychological Individualism a Piece of Ideology?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 March 2020

Abstract

I analyze and criticize Naomi Scheman's argument for the claim that psychological individualism—the thesis that psychological states are entities or particulars over which psychological theories may quantify—has no legitimate philosophical backing and is instead an element of patriarchal ideology. I conclude that Scheman's argument is flawed and that her thesis is false. Psychological individualism is perfectly compatible with and may even be required by feminist political theory.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1995 by Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Antony, Louise. 1989. Anomalous monism and the problem of explanatory force. Philosophical Review 98 (2): 153–87.10.2307/2185281CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antony, Louise. 1994. Conceptual connections and the observation/theory distinction. Grazer Philosophica, special issue on meaning holism, ed. Haller, R. and LePore, Ernest.10.1163/18756735-04601006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antony, Louise M. and Witt, Charlotte eds., 1993. A mind of one's own: Feminist essays on reason and objectivity. Boulder: Westview.Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1979. Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4: 73121.10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1959. Review of B. E Skinner's Verbal behavior. Language 35 (1): 2658.10.2307/411334CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Patricia. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind‐brain. Cambridge: MIT Press, Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1963. Actions, reasons and causes. Journal of Philosophy 60.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1975. The language of thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1980. Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1): 63109.10.1017/S0140525X00001771CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1994. The elm and the expert. Cambridge: MIT Press, Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry, and LePore, Ernest. 1991. Why meaning (probably) isn't conceptual role. Mind and Language 6 (4): 328343.10.1111/j.1468-0017.1991.tb00260.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry, and LePore, Ernest. 1992. Holism: A shopper's guide. Cambridge: MIT Press, Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Gallistel, C. R. 1990. The organization of learning. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gleitman, Henry. 1981. Psychology. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen Jay. 1987. Time's arrow, time's cycle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Harding, Sandra, and Hintikka, Merrill. B. eds., 1983. Discovering reality: Feminist perspectives on epistemology, metaphysics, and philosophy of science. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Jaggar, Alison M. 1983. Feminist politics and human nature. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1972. Naming and necessity. In Semantics of natural language, ed. Davidson, Donald and Harman, Gilbert. Dorcdrecht: D. Reidel. Reprinted, with a new introduction, as Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; London: Basil Blackwell, 1990.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1982. Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Genevieve. 1984. The man of reason: “Male” and “female” in western philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Mahowald, Mary. 1978. Philosophy of woman. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Morgan, Kathryn. 1979. Gender as a metaphysical dimension. In Philosophy and women, ed. Bishop, Sharon and Weinzweig, Marjorie. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1994. Review of A mind of one's own. New York Review of Books, 20 October.Google Scholar
Potter, Elizabeth. 1993. Gender and epistemic negotiation. In Feminist epistemologies, ed. Alcoff, Linda and Potter, Elizabeth. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. The Meaning of “meaning.”Reprinted in his Mind, language, and reality: Philosophical papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511625251CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1988. Representation and reality. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V.O. 1953. On what there is. In From a logical point of view. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scheman, Naomi. 1983. Individualism and the objects of psychology. In Discovering reality. See Harding and Hintikka 1983.Google Scholar
Scheman, Naomi. 1993. Tokens, types, and conjuring tricks. In Engenderings: Constructions of knowledge, authority and privilege. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Stich, Stephen. 1983. From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge: MIT Press, Bradford Books.Google Scholar